Skip to main content
  • Sean J. McGrath is a Full Professor of Philosophy at Memorial University of Newfoundland and a specialist in the phil... moreedit
In Western philosophy, the notion of the unity of the personality is as old as Plato, who distinguished three potentially conflicting parts of the soul. The three parts of the self are only fully functional when they are hierarchically... more
In Western philosophy, the notion of the unity of the personality is as old as Plato, who distinguished three potentially conflicting parts of the soul. The three parts of the self are only fully functional when they are hierarchically ordered, with the rational part governing and directing the two irrational parts. 2 The corresponding political ideal is an absolute dictatorship, where the only one fit to rule—the philosopher king (i.e., reason)—is granted absolute power over the other members of the state. On the basis of such canonical Western texts, the integrity or wholeness of the self is often presumed to be the same as psychological homogeneity. A " healthy " self, like a totalitarian state, is a not a dynamic ordering of disparate entities but an organic whole composed of parts. All of the impulses, values, and attitudes present in the self must contribute to the unity of the self, just as the parts of an organism contribute to the life of the organism. Where there is a plurality of values and attitudes in a personality, a psychological heterogeneity, we are inclined to speak of an " unintegrated " self, a sick self, schizophrenic, dysfunctional, etc. The aim of this paper is to present a different historical model of the self, no less Western, but essentially opposed to the foregoing. The healthy self in this other view does not disallow plurality, e.g., contradictory desires, incompatible values, but presumes it, much like parliamentary systems in Western democracies presume multiple political parties. This self is never a homogenous whole. On the contrary, it is a federation of disparate, often contradictory tendencies, desires and ideals. We will call this the dissociative self. 3 It was first thematized by medical theorists in the early 19 th century, as psychiatry evolved from demonology into animal magnetism. The most articulate exponent of the view was F.W.J. Schelling. 4 After an overview of the notion of multiple personality as it emerged from animal magnetism, I will finish the paper with a formal account of why the self according to Schelling must be dissociative. The short answer is, because it lives and develops in time. mean to distinguish Schellingian psychology from traditions based upon a conception of the self as constitutively repressive. In earlier versions of this argument I have hastily identified the repressive self with the Freudian tradition, but it seems to me now that the latter is too pluralistic to be so described. Freud could and perhaps should be read as a proponent of productive dissociation. This has not, however, been the predominant interpretation. I will leave aside then, the complex question of Freud's relationship to the 19 th century psychiatric tradition with which I am here primarily concerned. 4 The middle and late Schelling are most important in this regard, especially the celebrated Freedom essay, and its companion, The Ages of the World drafts. See F.W. J. Schelling, Philosophical Inquiries into the Essence of Human Freedom, (tr.) J. Love and J. Schmidt (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2006); Schelling, The Ages of the World, third draft, (tr.) J. Wirth (Albany: State University of New York Press, 2000), hereafter cited parenthetically in the text as AW. The Schellingian notion of the dissociative self seems to have had little direct influence on the development of Viennese (Freudian) psychoanalysis. On the other hand, its impact on French psychiatry was significant. Schelling played a role in the thought of Bergson and Janet, and through them influenced the dissociationism of Jung and Deleuze. On French dissociationism, see Christian Kerslake, Deleuze and the Unconscious (New York: Continuum, 2007).
Th e early Schelling and the romantics constructed the unconscious in order to overcome the modern split between subjectivity and nature, mind and body, a split legislated by Cartesian representationalism. Infl uenced by Boehme and... more
Th e early Schelling and the romantics constructed the unconscious in order to overcome the modern split between subjectivity and nature, mind and body, a split legislated by Cartesian representationalism. Infl uenced by Boehme and Kabbalah, the later Schelling modifi ed his notion of the unconscious to include the decision to be oneself, which must sink beneath consciousness so that it might serve as the ground of one's creative and personal acts. Slavoj Zizek has read the later Schelling's unconscious as a prototype of Lacan's reactive unconscious, an unconscious that only exists as the excluded other of consciousness. Th is reading, though close to the text of Schelling, misses something essential: the unconscious for Schelling is not a repression but a condition of the possibility of life and love.
Research Interests:
In Western philosophy, the notion of the unity of the personality is as old as Plato, who distinguished three potentially conflicting parts of the soul. The three parts of the self are only fully functional when they are hierarchically... more
In Western philosophy, the notion of the unity of the personality is as old as Plato, who distinguished three potentially conflicting parts of the soul. The three parts of the self are only fully functional when they are hierarchically ordered, with the rational part governing and directing the two irrational parts. 1 The corresponding political ideal is an absolute dictatorship, where the only one fit to rule—the philosopher king (i.e., reason)—is granted absolute power over the other members of the state. On the basis of such canonical Western texts, the integrity or wholeness of the self is often presumed to be the same as psychological homogeneity. A " healthy " self, like a totalitarian state, is a not a sum of disparate entities but an organic whole composed of parts. All of the impulses, values, and attitudes present in the self must contribute to the unity of the self, just as the parts of an organism contribute to the life of the organism. Where there is a plurality of values and attitudes in a personality, a psychological heterogeneity, we are inclined to speak of an " unintegrated " self, a sick self, schizophrenic, dysfunctional, etc. The aim of this paper is to deploy a different historical model of the self, no less Western, but essentially opposed to the foregoing, to rough out the outline of an alternative practice of psychoanalysis. The healthy self in this other view does not disallow plurality, e.g., contradictory desires, incompatible values, but presumes it, much like parliamentary systems in Western democracies presume multiple political parties. This self is never a homogenous whole. On the contrary, it is a federation of disparate, often contradictory tendencies, desires and ideals. We will call this the dissociative self. It was first thematized by medical theorists in the early 19 th century, as psychiatry evolved from demonology into animal magnetism. The dissociative self features prominently in the thought of several 19 th century thinkers (James and Pierce for example), but its most articulate exponent was F.W.J. Schelling. 2 After an overview of the notion of multiple personality as it emerged from animal magnetism, I will provide a formal account of why the self according to Schelling must be dissociative. The short answer is, because it lives and develops in time. I will conclude with a programmatic statement outlining seven principles that could govern a dissociative psychoanalytical practice, one foregrounded in Schelling's philosophy. But to begin it will be necessary to sharpen the idea of a dissociative self by contrasting it with its better known Freudian alternative, the repressive self.
Research Interests:
Research Interests:
Research Interests:
The landscape of contemporary religious ecology is presented as a variety of responses to disenchantment and what Lynn White Jr. identified as the theological roots of environmental ruin (Biblical divine transcendence and human... more
The landscape of contemporary religious ecology is presented as a variety of responses to disenchantment and what Lynn White Jr. identified as the theological roots of environmental ruin (Biblical divine transcendence and human exceptionality). The various positions are mapped in terms of those who deny divine transcendence and make nature, either as actually or potentially infinite, the highest (pantheists); those who deny divine unicity and return to a pre-Christian, “enchanted” nature (neo-pagans), and those who defend in various ways the ecology implicit in the Biblical account of creation (Jewish, Muslim, and Christian monotheists).
Chapter Two of Thinking Nature: An Essay in Negative Ecology.
Thinking Nature tracks the history of the concept of nature from the Hebrew Bible, through Renaissance philosophy and science, to dark ecology. Critical of the post-humanist trend in contemporary eco-criticism, Sean McGrath makes a... more
Thinking Nature tracks the history of the concept of nature from the Hebrew Bible, through Renaissance philosophy and science, to dark ecology. Critical of the post-humanist trend in contemporary eco-criticism, Sean McGrath makes a compelling case for a new anthropocenic humanism-a humanism that is not at the expense of nature, and a naturalism that is not at the expense of the human. Sean McGrath brilliantly deploys the resources of apophatic wisdom in response to the acute ecological challenge of our time. He taps the distinct eco-anxiety of contemporary culture while endorsing a radical contemplative attunement to the call of deep nature. A passionate, timely and audacious book.-Richard Kearney, Boston College Sean J. McGrath Save 30% when you order direct • If you're ordering from Europe, Asia, Africa or Oceania, please visit edinburghuniversitypress.com and enter the discount code NEW30 • If you're ordering from the Americas, visit oup.com/us and use the code ADISTA5 Offer valid until 31st May 2019; does not include postage and packaging.
Against the prevalent trend in eco-criticism which is to deny the human difference, I summon a set of untimely tropes from metaphysics in the interest of advancing an ecological humanism: the difference in kind between human consciousness... more
Against the prevalent trend in eco-criticism which is to deny the human difference, I summon a set of untimely tropes from metaphysics in the interest of advancing an ecological humanism: the difference in kind between human consciousness and animal sensibility; the uniquely human capacity for moral discernment; and the human being's peculiar freedom from the material conditions of existence. While I agree with eco-critics who argue that anthropocenic nature is not only finite, but sick: sickened by our abuse and neglect, I disagree that this abuse is simply a result of insisting on the human difference (" anthropocentrism "), nor is species egalitarian-ism the way forward. On the contrary, the eco-collapse, referred to as the sixth great extinction event is the consequence of a general disavowal of the human's special call to take responsibility for the relation between the human and the non-human, and only a reawakening of this responsibility can restore health to anthropocenic nature. The non-human cannot effect this restoration, for that is not its vocation. A difference in vocation is not necessarily a difference in moral worth, and so the human difference does not justify denying the " intrinsic value " of the non-human. Humanity is uniquely responsible both for the mess we are in and for cleaning it up.
Research Interests:
The history of modern Western thinking about nature devolves into a stalemate between anthropocentrism and cosmocentrism. For the former, nature is there for our use; it is resource, and we, as lords and masters of nature, can do with it... more
The history of modern Western thinking about nature devolves into a stalemate between anthropocentrism and cosmocentrism. For the former, nature is there for our use; it is resource, and we, as lords and masters of nature, can do with it what we wish. For the latter, nature is a balanced order, regulated by its laws, and directed by its own agenda. It is does not belong to us, we belong to it. Failure to recognize this basic fact of earthly existence, cosmocentric thinkers maintain, has got us into the pickle we are in today. Applied to the sea, we get two alternative models: the sea as resource for human need and development; and the sea as world unto itself, as agent,  with an agenda of its own. We can describe the two alternatives as the sea for us, or the sea for itself. It is important to recognize that these two obviously contradictory positions are rooted in ethico-religious assumptions about the human being and its place in the universe. Anthropocentrism is rooted in a certain form of monotheism; cosmocentrism is rooted in modern pantheism. The former is humanistic, the latter is post-human. The Anthropocene, the recognition of the human species as a geological force, and the convergence of deep geological time with human history, now makes it increasingly impossible to maintain either of these alternatives.
Without doubt, the piece of the late Schelling that has received the least amount of scholarly attention is the conclusion of the Philosophy of Revelation. 1 In the two concluding lectures, which take up a mere forty pages of Schelling's... more
Without doubt, the piece of the late Schelling that has received the least amount of scholarly attention is the conclusion of the Philosophy of Revelation. 1 In the two concluding lectures, which take up a mere forty pages of Schelling's Sämtliche Werke, Schelling offers a theory of three ages of revelation, materialized in three historical forms of will bring the strife between churches, states, and world religions to an end. While Schelling does not reference it, his theory echoes the traditional theological trope of the two resurrections, which are separated by the thousand years of peace prophesied in the Book of Revelation, to occur before the Parousia and the end of time. 2 Each of the three forms of ecclesia actualise one of three historical possibilities for resolving the internal diversity under the coercive rule of a single external authority; the second, the Pauline theory is not entirely original-it is a version of the 12 th century prophet Joachim of Fiore's trinitarian philosophy of history. 3 But the way Schelling underwrites the schema, through a theological-political is certainly unique to him. There is no question in my mind that Schelling regarded this philosophy of history as the centerpiece of his last, positive philosophy. In what follows, I wish to modestly counteract the scholarly silence on Schelling's theory of the three ages of revelation by giving 1 F.W.J. Schelling, Philosophie der Offenbarung, zweiter Theil, Vorlesungen 36-37, in Schellings Sämtliche
A critical analysis of the early Heidegger's relation to the theology of Luther.
A post-Heideggerian account of the internalized eschatology of medieval Christian thought.
A summary and assessment of the early Heidegger's interpretation of early Christianity.
Research Interests:
Research Interests:
Research Interests:
Research Interests:
Liberal secularism, and its economic shadow, consumer-capitalism, I will argue, are theologically saturated structures: they emerge out of Jewish-Christian religiosity and are made possible by certain attitudes unique to these traditions.... more
Liberal secularism, and its economic shadow, consumer-capitalism, I will argue, are theologically saturated structures: they emerge out of Jewish-Christian religiosity and are made possible by certain attitudes unique to these traditions. In abstraction from the Jewish-Christian belief in theological transcendence, liberal secularism produces a monster: the consumer-capitalist juggernaut with its threefold tyranny: consumerism, the tyranny over desire; scientism, the tyranny over knowledge; and corporate capitalism, the tyranny over community.
The Philosophical Foundations of the Late Schelling is now available in paperback. 30% discount if you order direct from EUP using the code PAPER30.
On page 89 of the hardback edition of Thinking Nature: An Essay in Negative Ecology (Edinburgh, 2019), a reference purported to be from Schelling appears. It is in fact from Franz von Baader. Please see "erratum" for details.
Martin Heidegger is one of the greatest conundrums in the philosophical world, alternately incredibly inspiring and mind-bogglingly frustrating. S. J. McGrath acknowledges the impossibility of trying to encapsulate Heidegger in a... more
Martin Heidegger is one of the greatest conundrums in the philosophical world, alternately incredibly inspiring and mind-bogglingly frustrating. S. J. McGrath acknowledges the impossibility of trying to encapsulate Heidegger in a nutshell, and refuses to present him here in summary, thereby absolving the audience of the task of reading the philosopher. Instead, this introduction is truly that; leading readers to Heidegger where they can then begin or continue their own relationship with him
Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling is widely regarded as one of the most difficult and influential of German philosophers. In this book, S. J. McGrath not only makes Schelling's ideas accessible to a general audience, he uncovers the... more
Friedrich Wilhelm Joseph Schelling is widely regarded as one of the most difficult and influential of German philosophers. In this book, S. J. McGrath not only makes Schelling's ideas accessible to a general audience, he uncovers the romantic philosopher's seminal role as the creator of a concept which shaped and defined late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century psychology: the concept of the unconscious.
Research Interests:
The Early Heidegger and Medieval Philosophy is a major interpretive study of Heidegger's complex relationship to medieval philosophy. S. J. McGrath's contribution is historical and biographical as well as philosophical, examining how the... more
The Early Heidegger and Medieval Philosophy is a major interpretive study of Heidegger's complex relationship to medieval philosophy. S. J. McGrath's contribution is historical and biographical as well as philosophical, examining how the enthusiastic defender of the Aristotelian-Scholastic tradition became the great destroyer of metaphysical theology.
Research Interests:
Video of talk given at Harvard Divinity School 15 November 2021
Research Interests:
Concluding remarks on Schelling's Historical Critical Introduction and some thought on its relation to philosophical religion.
Some reflections on the relation between nationalism and mythology in Schelling's Historical Critical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mythology.
A brief summary of the aim of Schelling's Historical Critical Introduction to the Philosophy of Mythology.
A talk given at the University of St. Michael's College on the 27th of March, 2019.
Research Interests:
Research Interests:
A panel discussion at Queen's College, St. John's, NL, 1 May 2017, featuring Sean McGrath, David Bell, Michelle Rebidoux, and Ian Wishart.
Research Interests:
Lecture at Memorial University of Newfoundland, Philosophy Colloquium, 22/10/2015
Research Interests:
Lecture given at the philosophy colloquium of Jawaharlal Nehru University of New Delhi 17 May 2014.
Research Interests:
Lecture on the anthropocene and the future of nature given to graduate students in Coastal Marine Management at the University Centre of the West Fjords, Ísafjörður, Iceland, 18 May 2015.
Research Interests:
An introduction to the themes and political significance of Pope Francis's encyclical on climate change.
Research Interests:
Outline of a paper given at the University of Tokyo, 6 July 2019
Research Interests:
DESCRIPTION As the sequential stages of the 2020 COVID-19 pandemic have unfolded, so have its complexities. What initially presented as a health emergency, has revealed itself to be a phenomenon of many facets. It has demonstrated human... more
DESCRIPTION As the sequential stages of the 2020 COVID-19 pandemic have unfolded, so have its complexities. What initially presented as a health emergency, has revealed itself to be a phenomenon of many facets. It has demonstrated human creativity, the oft neglected presence of nature, and the resilience of communities. Equally, it has exposed deep social inequities, conceptual inadequacies, and structural deficiencies about the way we organize our civilization and our knowledge. As the situation continues to advance, the question is whether the crisis will be grasped as an opportunity to address the deep structural, ecological and social challenges that we brought with us into the second decade of the new millennium. This volume addresses the collective sense that the pandemic is more than a problem to manage our way out of. Rather, it is a moment to consider our broken relationship with the natural world, and our alienation from a deeper sense of purpose and meaning. The contributors, though differing in their diagnoses and recommendations, share the belief that this moment, with its transformative possibility, not be forfeit. Equally, they share the conviction that the chief ground of any such reorientation ineluctably involves our collective engagement with both ecology and theology. INFORMATION
The following paper takes Pope Francis’ Encyclical on Climate Change as an opportunity to re-open the debate, begun in 1967 by Lynn White Jr., on the theological origins of the environmental crisis. I note that the Pope’s critique of... more
The following paper takes Pope Francis’ Encyclical on Climate Change as an opportunity to re-open the debate, begun in 1967 by Lynn White Jr., on the theological origins of the environmental crisis. I note that the Pope’s critique of consumerist modernity is strong, but his lack of a genealogical account of modernity remains a weakness of the text. I argue, with White, that the technological revolution which has caused climate change would not have been possible without Christian assumptions. The original disenchantment of the world was the Abrahamic revelation which disjoined divinity and nature, and contra to appearances, the disjunction was only exacerbated by the doctrine of the incarnation. With climate change, modernity is returning to this revelation in the form of the sobering experience of the precarity of the planet. Nature is now experienced as finite once again, and it includes us. Modernity, however, cannot be disavowed any more than disenchantment can easily be forgott...
Virtually all the German Idealists, from Fichte to Feuerbach, envisioned a future in which the distinction between church and state would disappear and the truth of Christianity would be realized as the truth of humanity. The... more
Virtually all the German Idealists, from Fichte to Feuerbach, envisioned a future in which the distinction between church and state would disappear and the truth of Christianity would be realized as the truth of humanity. The secularization of the Christian phenomenon is one of the basic themes of German Idealism. Secularization in this context does not mean the emancipation of Western societies from traditional religion (pace Hans Blumenburg): quite to the contrary, for Hegel and Schelling, secularization is the destiny or end of Christianity, even as it signals the demise of the theological and institutional means through which this tradition evolved. Not surprising, Hegel and Schelling developed diametrically opposed versions of the secularization thesis. The conflict between them stems from an ambiguity in the word, “end” (German, das Ende): for with respect to Christianity, “end” can mean telos or final cause (das Ziel des Christentums), e.g., the flowering of the plant that ac...
Revelation according to Schelling is not the possession of any institutional form of Christianity; it is not even bound to faith or confession. Rather, revelation disseminates itself freely and universally throughout history. It now... more
Revelation according to Schelling is not the possession of any institutional form of Christianity; it is not even bound to faith or confession. Rather, revelation disseminates itself freely and universally throughout history. It now inextricably permeates modernity. Schelling’s Philosophy of Revelation does not look backwards to an event in the first century of the common era, it looks forward to the genuine singularity, the moment when humanity will become adequate to the divine subjectivity which lives in it, that is, the penultimate eschaton proclaimed by Paul and the author or the Book of Revelation, the age of righteousness prior to the general resurrection.1 By bringing mythological consciousness to an end and drawing real limits to rationalism (idealism), revelation first establishes a free relation of the human being to the divine. At the same time, revelation liberates philosophy and culture from religion and inaugurates secular consciousness. History, according to the late...