Bernard-Minimalist_Aesthetic_Plastic_Arts_Music
Bernard-Minimalist_Aesthetic_Plastic_Arts_Music
Bernard-Minimalist_Aesthetic_Plastic_Arts_Music
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/833043?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Perspectives of New Music is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
THE MINIMALIST AESTHETIC
IN THE PLASTIC ARTS
AND IN MUSIC
JONATHAN W. BERNARD
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 87
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I B~~~~~~~~
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Photoeraph ? 1993 Willem de Kooning/ARS, New York
EXAMPLE 2: WILLEM DE KOONING, Black and White Rme (Double-Sided Single L) (1959).
OIL ON PAPER, 28" X 40"
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
90 Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 91
After living with this painting and studying it intensely now and then,
I picked up on an attitude about making something that was absolutely
unique to me.... the Black Painting... was like Rauschenberg's dis-
covery that he wanted "neither life nor art, but something in
between." I then began to compose a music dealing precisely with "in-
betweenness": creating a confusion of material and construction, and
a fusion of method and application, by concentrating on how they
could be directed toward "that which is difficult to categorize."9
This "confusion of material and its construction," this intrusion of life into
art so that what resulted was neither wholly one nor the other is exactly
what one would expect from an aesthetic in which explicit incorporation of
the creator's personality was held to be of utmost importance.
As the fifties progressed, and increasingly as they drew to an end, some
signs of rebellion against abstract expressionism became evident. In art,
two particularly significant figures were Barnett Newman and Ad
Reinhardt. Newman, in his so-called "stripe" paintings, put forth the idea,
not only of a drastic simplification or reduction, but also of a literalism
about the artwork that would become absolutely crucial to minimalism
later on. Newman spoke of the object as object, of his works as "declaring
the space" in which they operate.10 A painting, he said, "is nothing more
than a slice of space, a 'space vehicle,' which a painter gets into, and then
has to get out of."ll This statement bespeaks clearly an intention on
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
92 Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 93
Newman's part that nothing be left of himself in the painting once the
painting is done. Reinhardt, for his part, took a more uncompromising
tone: one of his Six Canons or "Noes" insists upon "No Expressionism or
Surrealism" and that "'the laying bare of oneself,' autobiographically or
socially, is obscene."12 Further: "No accidents or automatism" and "Every-
thing, where to begin and where to end, should be worked out in the mind
beforehand."13 Reinhardt's near-monochromatic canvases certainly do
seem to have anticipated the minimalist painters' use of solid fields of color
(Example 5).
On the musical side, the activities of the Fluxus group were probably the
most significant in the transition to minimalism. In his excellent treatment
of the subject in Experimental Music: Cage and Beyond, Michael Nyman
points out that the Fluxus composers "reviewed multiplicity, found its
deficiencies, and chose to reduce their focus of attention to singularity."'14
This was very much an issue of control: the performance pieces which
George Brecht called "events" bore only a superficial resemblance to the
mixed-media "happenings" pioneered by Cage as early as 1952. As is well
known, the happening was designed to promote spontaneity and unpre-
dictable outcomes from the random intersections and collisions of simul-
taneously, independently executed activities. The austerity of Brecht's events
stands in stark contrast to such abundance (Example 6).15
The reader will notice that these compositions do not by any means
exclude variability from their realization or remove all powers of decision-
making from their performers. However, the sheer range of possible out-
comes has been severely reduced--and it has been done without retreating
from the "wide-open" nature of aleatory, for these pieces continue to
stretch the boundaries of what can be considered music. Further, these
events have a curiously anonymous, or impersonal, aspect, as if anyone
could have planned them-something which is really not true of Cage's
pieces, despite his supposedly having removed himself from the proceed-
ings. Is there anything, really, that categorically distinguishes Brecht's
Fluxus pieces from La Monte Young's of about the same time? This
impersonal quality is noticeable even as one recognizes the vigorously,
almost aggressively distinct and original aesthetic that underlies them as
their common ground.
As the sixties began, the definitive break from abstract expressionism in
the plastic arts came at the hands of such younger artists as sculptor Donald
Judd and painter Frank Stella, who had reached a point of intense dissatis-
faction with this tendency of the personality to attract attention to itself.
Stella recalls:
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
94 Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 95
G. Brecht
(1959-62)
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
96 Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 97
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
98 Perspectives or New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 99
fact, such as Robert Morris, the impression given by art objects that they
had been manufactured-whether literally true or not-was crucial to
breaking "the tedious ring of'artiness' circumscribing each new phase of art
since the Renaissance" and helping to remove the accompanying interposi-
tion of artist's personality between artwork and viewer.28
The simplification of musical materials that accompanies the suppression
of chance procedures also results in the equivalent of a "shiny" or "nonpain-
terly" presence. This is manifest in several features. One is the limited
repertoire of sound sources, whether they be taped or live; in the latter
case, the harmonies favored are preponderantly consonances and "mild"
dissonances. (The old tonal criteria are invoked here only for the sake of
convenience; the music itself, by definition, need not have anything to do
with common-practice harmony.) Another notable feature is the extensive
use of repetition, whether or not in the service of gradually induced, barely
perceptible change over time. Recourse to such a device, especially when
combined, as is so often the case, with the projection of a constant, uniform
pulse and a busy, bustling, or "buzzing" character, seems calculated to
evoke a sense of flatness, to deny that there is anything but surface to
engage the listener's attention.29 Of course, if there really were nothing but
surface to this music, one could only conclude that it was nonhierarchically
based. Such a basis is evidently not an impossible one for visual art-to
judge from the historical evidence-so perhaps it is not for music either.
The possibility is worth pointing out, if only to suggest that it may account
for the difficulties experienced by theorists in particular in accepting this
music as worthwhile art. For now, it will suffice to keep in mind Morris's
dictum that "Simplicity of shape does not necessarily equate with simplicity
of experience."30
(3) The shift in emphasis from composition to arrangement in minimal
art, or from parts to whole, seems to have come about as an attempt to
communicate more directly and clearly. One way of doing this was to
reduce the number of parts. Among the sculptors, Judd, Morris, and Carl
Andre are particularly significant for the ways in which their work
embodies this idea. Judd has been bluntly eloquent on the subject: "When
you start relating parts, in the first place, you're assuming that you have a
vague whole-the rectangle of the canvas-and definite parts, which is all
screwed up, because you should have a definite whole and maybe no parts,
or very few."31 Andre got around the problem of relations between parts
by using bricks of a fixed size, arranged (unmortared) in various ways:
these came across as "regimented, interchangeable units" which "did not
lend themselves to relational structures" because "any part could replace
any other part" (Example 8).32 Arrangement is taken here to imply "a
preconceived notion of the whole," as opposed to composition, which "usu-
ally means the adjustment of the parts, that is, their size, shape, color, or
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
100 Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 101
placement, to arrive at the finished work, whose exact nature is not known
beforehand."33 The work illustrated in Example 9 is one of Andre's
arrangements, a series entitled Equivalents I-VIII, in which the same
number of bricks (120) is placed to form each of eight larger blocks, all two
bricks high but varying in their other two dimensions. Still another solu-
tion was proposed by Morris:
... Certain forms do exist that, if they do not negate the numerous
relative sensations of color to texture, scale to mass, etc., do not
present clearly separated parts for these kinds of relations to be estab-
lished in terms of shapes. Such are the simpler forms that create strong
gestalt sensations. Their parts are bound together in such a way that
they offer a maximum resistance to perceptual separation.34
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Photograph courtesy of Paula Cooper Gallery
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 103
x
X
U~
-4
-o ri
(O
.0
0
(I
0
c
0t
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
EXAMPLE 11: ROBERT MOR
FOUR PIECES, EACH 28" x 28" x 28"
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 105
13 [151
I nL- :777 ri r-r :77 ri rrrn r 7
M16 17
18rdfrf^ ^
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
106 Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 107
opposite corners were lopped off or other alterations were made to get
away from the standard rectangular format, producing a shape which
became identical in dimensions to the image (Example 13). Similarly in
sculpture, Judd's and Morris's "elementary, geometrical forms... depend
for their art quality on some sort of presence or concrete there-
ness.... There is no wish to transcend the physical for either the meta-
physical or the metaphoric. The thing, then, is presumably not sup-
posed... to be suggestive of anything other than itself."47 Judd himself
preferred to call work that exhibited such qualities "three-dimensional
art"--neither painting nor sculpture but "related, closely or distantly, to
one or the other"-or, even better, "specific objects."48
The desirability of directness of image is certainly evident in the artistic
credos of minimalist composers, notably Reich's essay, "Music as a Gradual
Process," in which the author begins by explaining his title: "I do not mean
the process of composition, but rather pieces of music that are, literally,
processes.... I am interested in perceptible processes; I want to be able to
hear the process happening throughout the sounding music." Further, says
Reich of his method, "once the process is set up and loaded it runs by
itself"--a feature which acts to remove its inventor from the scene actually
unfolded in the music.49 Reich is also careful to point out the distinction
between Cage's use of process and his own: "The processes he used were
compositional ones that could not be heard when the piece was per-
formed."50 Again with reference to Indeterminacy, it would seem that
although the experience of listening to such a piece is intended to parallel
the process of creating it-in that one follows the accumulation of the
result, moment by moment-one is provided with nothing to go on con-
cerning the basis on which the creative decisions were actually made.
Unable to determine what the larger plan might be-or even whether there
is a larger plan-listeners are far more likely to focus their attention on what
might be called the "eternal present" of the individual stories, less likely to
attempt to make sense of the whole. Thus a kind of stasis is established-
apparently much like the stasis that Feldman claims to have brought to his
own work by studying the paintings of such abstract expressionists as Mark
Rothko and Philip Guston, for he sees in his compositional aims a denial of
process-in fact, an explicit opposition to it.51
Reich's idea of process is especially interesting in light of the fact that
minimalist artists sought to introduce a kind of temporality into their
work. Morris notes: "Only one aspect of the work is immediate: the
apprehension of the gestalt. The experience of the work necessarily exists in
time."52 As Maurice Berger comments:
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
108 Perspectives of New Music
oO
00
0
rv
I
oo
r-
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 109
In painting, the thick stretcher became a vehicle for this sort of temporal
quality as well-as for example in the work of Baer, whose entirely flat
banded paintings of the sixties (Example 14) evolved into C'Wraparound"
works in the seventies (Example 15). Thus the artist effectively "demands
that the viewer abandon a static position and physically move around to see
the work."54
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
110 Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
EXAMPLE 16: DAN FLAVIN, Greens Crossing Greens (forPietMondrian Who Lacked Green)
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
112 Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 113
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
114 Perspectives of New Music
o
I if X
[ x
91
1-1
-c
0
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 115
without completing the cube). A similar sort of principle operates, not only
in Reich's phase-shifting pieces, but also in works such as his Music for
Eighteen Musicians (1974-76), in which each of a series of eleven chords
given in the relatively brief opening serves in turn as the basis of a section;
this "composing out" accounts for almost the entire duration of the piece,
excepting only the opening and the conclusion which is its exact duplicate.
The wide applicability of this serial principle, in fact, suggests that it is
entirely appropriate to continue to apply the term minimal to the more
recent work of Glass, Riley, and Reich, despite attempts on the part of some
critics (and composers) to brand it "Post-Minimal."
It is for this very quality of temporality, however-instilled at least partly
for the sake of rendering the work clearer and more accessible and making
of it "something that everyone can understand," in the words of sculptor
Tony Smith58-that minimal art is perhaps most open to criticism. A
difficulty arises from the fact that the basis for the governing decisions
noted above is rarely (if ever) justified in any larger terms. In an influential
and provocative essay entitled "Art and Objecthood," Michael Fried noted
the consequences of this lack: "The actual number of modular units in a
given piece is felt to be arbitrary, and the piece itself... is seen as a
fragment of, or cut into, something infinitely larger." Curiously, this
impression lends a sense of "endless, or indefinite, duration" to the work
itself.59 Environmental artist Robert Smithson has drawn attention to
these very qualities in the works he calls "nonsites," which he developed as
a way of containing an "oceanic" site and its "disruption." In his words,
"The container is in a sense a fragment itself, something that could be
called a three-dimensional map.... It actually exists as a fragment of a
greater fragmentation. It is a three-dimensional perspective that has broken
away from the whole, while containing the lack of its own containment.
There are no mysteries in these vestiges, no traces of an end or a begin-
ning."60 As Example 20 shows, Smithson often incorporated photographs
or maps into such works, showing the place from which the material for the
nonsite was taken.
Numerous critics in the sixties quickly came to realize that this new art,
through its fixation upon literal appearance- Stella's "what you see is what
you see"-guaranteed that the work would include the beholder. Not in the
sense simply of drawing viewers in, of involving them or fascinating them,
but rather in the sense that the act of looking at the work of art would
become part of that work's meaning: "An earmark of minimalist art is the
tendency to locate content outside the art object, in its physical setting or in
viewers' responses, rather than 'inside' it, in the literary or psychological
import of an image, for example."70 This quality amounts in part to a
critique of earlier art and its implicit assumption that what is located strictly
within the work could wholly define the artistic experience--that a work of
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
EXAMPLE 20: RoBERT smITHsoN, A Nonsite, Frankldin, N.J (1968)
PART 1: WOOD, LIMESTONE. 16'/2" x 82" x 110"
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 117
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
118 Perspectives of New Music
art could in fact mean anything without someone around to look at it. But
this dependence upon the beholder turned out to be a coin with an
opposite side: being included also meant being controlled, coerced. Barbara
Rose has noted this quality in Judd's work (Example 21); what he is trying
to do, she says,
The sheer, vast size of many works of minimal sculpture, besides precluding
one from taking them in all at once,72 may also serve to menace the viewer.
Richard Serra's Circuit, for example (Example 22), has been described as a
work that makes one feel unguarded at every side to stand at its center-in
the end, it is "an assault upon our vanity of feeling that we govern the
figure we cut in the eyes of the world."73 In her forceful indictment of this
and other aspects of minimal art, Anna Chave notes that the evident desire
to dominate the viewer goes hand in hand with the tendency to favor large,
even overwhelming scale (especially in sculpture) as a way of seizing
control of an area or a space. In some sculptors' work, this aim has been
carried to such extremes as to have literally endangered life and property.74
Painters as well have adopted techniques that seem, among other things,
calculated to annoy or frustrate the viewer. In particular, Kenneth Noland
has produced canvases that are extremely narrow (vertically) but so long
(horizontally) that one cannot stand far enough away from them in any
normal exhibition space to get them entirely within one's field of vision all
at once. The experience of looking at his diamond-shaped canvases has
been characterized as "basically unsatisfying and unstable," because "one's
eye, in trying to focus on the colors and gauge their relative hues, is always
slipping off the edge of the canvas, propelled there by the tilt of the
bands."75 Writing about some of Noland's work from around 1967, this
same critic found that either the viewer must give into
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 119
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Photograph ? 1993 Richard Serra/ARS, Ne-w York
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 121
And Stella has been quite candid about the aspect of coercion in his own
work:
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
122 Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 123
deny the viewer access to anything beyond a single, carefully controlled and
circumscribed experience of the work. Stella, discussing in 1970 his metal-
lic pinstripe paintings of a decade earlier, recalled his interest in presenting
"a real aggressive kind of controlling surface, something that ... would also
be fairly repellent. I liked the idea, thinking about flatness and depth, that
these would be very hard paintings to penetrate."78 The second, more
general aim has to do with minimalists' sense of their own historical
importance: in dictating to viewers the terms in which their work would be
experienced, minimalists were emboldened to form "the terse, but
veracious last word in a narrowly framed argument about what modern art
is or should be."79 And their exercise of power over their viewers came to
seem, to some critics, not so much a critique as a reflection of the repressive
applications of political, social, and economic power in the "real world" of
the 1960s.
Similar issues arise on the musical side. "I am wildly interested in
repetition," Young said in 1967, "because I think it demonstrates con-
trol."80 And Mertens has (seemingly inadvertently) identified a paradox:
that on the one hand the minimal piece cannot be regarded as finished until
the listener "actively participates in its construction"; but on the other, that
this same listener "is reduced to a passive role, merely submitting to the
process."81 In their elevation to supremacy of the perception of process on
the part of the listener, composers such as Reich certainly do imply that
there is only one valid way to hear their music. One detects in some of
Reich's statements an attempt to deny the existence of this problem:
Even when all the cards are on the table and everyone hears what
is gradually happening in a musical process, there are still enough mys-
teries to satisfy all. These mysteries are the impersonal, unintend-
ed, psycho-acoustic by-products of the intended process. These might
include sub-melodies heard within repeated melodic patterns, stereo-
phonic effects due to listener location, slight irregularities in perform-
ance, harmonics, difference tones, etc.82
Such assurances, however, come across as more than slightly arrogant. "You
ought to be satisfied," Reich seems to be saying to the listener, "with the
extremely limited options I've given you, and you ought to accept them as
the new standard of sufficiently interesting complexity." Would it be more
useful to think of Reich's processes as analogous to Morris's gestalts, which
cannot account for one's complete experience of a work of art even though
they do control it? Most likely not, because there is nothing "unintended"
about the eventual divergence of perception from the immediate, initial
impression made by Morris's gestalts. The minimalist aesthetic, as noted,
really does not permit accidentally produced effects to have any substantial
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
124 Perspectives of New Music
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 125
people who will wander right out of the hall in the middle of a perform-
ance.90 Perhaps this constitutes a liberation of sorts, but clearly not every-
one thinks so. Mertens, for example, points out that "Since each moment
may be the beginning or the end, the listener can choose how long he
wants to listen for, but he will never miss anything by not listening."91
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
126 Perspectives of New Music
NOTES
3. These were sculptors Richard Serra and Bruce Nauman, and film-
maker Michael Snow; the fourth performer was composer James
Tenney.
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 127
14. Michael Nyman, Experimental Music: Cage and Beyond (New York
Schirmer Books, 1972), 119.
17. Bruce Glaser, "Questions to Stella and Judd" [interview], Art New
September 1966; repr. in Battcock, MinimalArt, 156.
18. Peter Gena, "Freedom in Experimental Music: The New York Revol
tion," Tri-Quarterly 52 (1981): 223-43.
19. In fact, the performance of The Well-Tuned Piano recorded at 6 Har-
rison Street in New York on 25 October 1981 is just over five hours in
duration (New York: Gramavision Records 18-8701-2 [5 CDs
1987). Edward Strickland, in a personal communication, reports that a
performance of this work in May 1987 lasted six hours, twenty-four
minutes.
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
128 Perspectives of New Music
22. See, for example, Glass's comments on serialism in Music by Philip Glass
(New York: Harper & Row, 1987), 12-13, and the remark: "[Cage,
Feldman, and Brown] were men whose work struck me [in the
mid-1960s] as far less doctrinaire and much more adventurous than
that of their European contemporaries" (13).
24. Kenneth Noland, "The Thing in Painting Is Color," New York Times,
25 August 1968; quoted in Art since Mid-Century vol. 1, 293.
25. Glaser, "Questions to Stella and Judd," 157.
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 129
31. Glaser, "Questions to Stella and Judd," 151, 154. The allusion to
painting in this statement not only reveals that it was abstract expres-
sionism to which Judd was primarily reacting, but also confirms that it
was a dissatisfaction with painting in general that turned Judd to
sculpture in the first place.
32. David Bourdon, "The Razed Sites of Carl Andre," Artforum, October
1966; reprinted in Battcock, MinimalArt, 104.
33. Mel Bochner, "Serial Art, Systems, Solipsism," Arts Magazine, Sum-
mer 1967; reprinted in Battcock, MinimalArt, 94.
36. I use the word "improvised" here only to signify that, while the sounds
supplied by Tudor were not in themselves invented on the spur of the
moment (the electronic material was prerecorded, the piano material
written out in full), their occurrence in relation to Cage's spoken texts
was not planned ahead of time. In fact, this would have been imposs-
ible to do, since Cage and Tudor recorded this piece in real time while
occupying different rooms, out of earshot of each other.
37. For Lucier's score, which is simply a set of verbal directions, see Scores:
An Anthology, 199, or Alvin Lucier and Douglas Simon, Chambers
(Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1980), 30-31.
38. Philip Glass, Music by Philip Glass, 17.
40. This phrase is actually taken from Glass's commentary on his Music in
Twelve Parts, though it could just as well apply here. (Quoted in
Mertens, 79.)
41. Dore Ashton speaks of Martin as "a meditative painter" in her essay
"Agnes Martin and..." in Agnes Martin Paintings and Drawings
1957-1975 (Arts Council of Great Britain, 1977), 7-14; Baer's work
of the sixties is termed "contemplative" by David Elliott in his "Intro-
duction" to Jo Baer: Paintings 1962-1974 (Oxford: Museum of Mod-
ern Art, 1977), 3-11.
42. Martin, "We Are in the Midst of Reality Responding to Joy" (lecture,
Yale University, 5 April 1976), in Agnes Martin, 17-39.
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
130 Perspectives of New Music
43. Such is evidently the view of Elaine Broad, for example, who in her
article, "A New X? An Examination of the Aesthetic Foundations of
Early Minimalism" (Music Research Forum 5 [1990]: 51-62), refers to
minimal music as "non-time-directed" (59). In this regard, she echoes
Mertens, who speaks of the "mere duration and stasis" of Young's work
(American Minimal Music, 89). Nyman, too, comes perilously close to
equating the formal stasis attributed by Cage in 1948 to new music
(including his own) with the qualities of Young's music ("Against
Intellectual Complexity in Music," 88-89).
44. Hitchcock, "Minimal Art and Music"; John Rahn, "What Is Valuable
in Art, and Can Music Still Achieve It?," Perspectives of New Music 27,
no. 2 (Summer 1989): 6-17.
45. Glaser, "Questions to Stella and Judd," 158.
50. Ibid., 10. He refers, in all likelihood, to the methods used for Changes,
Imaginary Landscape No. 4, and Music for Piano 21-52, all documented
in John Cage, Silence (Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press,
1973), 57-61.
51. Feldman, "Crippled Symmetry," 137; "Some Elementary Questions,"
67-70. Discussing his TriadicMemories, Feldman notes that each of the
chords in slow tempo is repeated a number of times depending on
"how long I felt it should go on," and reports finding that "Quite soon
into a new chord I would forget the reiterated chord before it."
Working with this phenomenon, he aimed for a "disorientation of
memory," under which the repetition without discernible pattern
would suggest "that what we hear is functional and directional, but we
soon realize that this is an illusion" ("Crippled Symmetry," 127). The
idea of an eternal present could not be more clearly projected than it is
here.
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
The Minimalist Aesthetic 131
53. Maurice Berger, Labyrinths: Robert Morris Minimalism, and the 1960s
(New York: Harper & Row, 1989), 53.
54. Barbara Haskell, Jo Baer (New York: Whitney Museum of Modern
Art, 1975), [6]. Baer, it seems, undertook these wraparound works in
part as a response to Judd's and others' increasingly harsh criticism of
the medium of painting itself towards the end of the sixties.
62. Mertens, 71; Andre quoted in Bourdon, "The Razed Sites of Carl
Andre," 104.
67. Dan Warburton, however, claims that Rzewski now prefers performers
to play Les Moutons with the score completely written out, in order
to prevent the previously inevitable dissolution of the unison/octave
presentation (see "A Working Terminology for Minimal Music," 146).
This information, if true, would seem to indicate that Rzewski is now
interested in exerting greater control than formerly over the sounding
result-reflecting a tendency not at all foreign to minimalism-
although many of Kramer's observations about the piece would still
hold true under this interpretation.
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
132 Perspectives of New Music
72. Lucy R. Lippard notes this quality in many of Tony Smith's sculptures
(Tony Smith [New York: Harry N. Abrams, 1972], 19).
73. Baker, Minimalism, 121.
74. Anna C. Chave, "Minimalism and the Rhetoric of Power," The Arts
Magazine 64, no. 5 (January 1990): 44-63.
75. Jane Harrison Cone, "Kenneth Noland's New Paintings," in The Great
Decade ofAmerican Abstraction, 75.
76. Ibid., 74.
78. Stella, quoted in Chave, "Minimalism and the Rhetoric of Power," 50-
51.
83. Sol LeWitt, "Sentences on Conceptual Art," in Sol LeWitt, ed. and
introd. Alicia Legg (New York: Museum of Modern Art, 1978), 168.
89. Marc Wilkinson, "An Introduction to the Music of Edgar Varese," The
Score and I.MA. Magazine 19 (1957): 5.
This content downloaded from 164.41.4.26 on Fri, 15 Sep 2017 13:50:35 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms