Vidler Anthony 1977 1998 The Third Typology
Vidler Anthony 1977 1998 The Third Typology
Vidler Anthony 1977 1998 The Third Typology
critique of science, we invite scientists to move beyond bick- include a review of realism and constructivism (Putnam
ering and explore the literature of science studies for them- 1987, Sismondo 1996, Hacking 1999); we simply want to
selves (see Biagioli 1999 for a recently edited volume on sci- point out that there are many middle-ground alternatives to
ence studies, Kleinman 1998 on the social relevance of science objectivism and the more extreme forms of relativism and
studies, Hacking 1999 for a discussion on social construction, subjectivism.
Natoli 1997 for a humorous introduction to postmodernism, Beyond a need to seek a moderate position so as to escape
and Pickering 1995 for a postmodern case study in physics). naive realism, there are the added problems when values ex-
Denying the Enlightenment project may seem pessimistic, but plicitly enter scientific discourse. Because the arena where sci-
we have seen the man behind the curtain and objectivist re- ence and policy interface is inherently value laden, there is an
alism is now compromised. urgent need for concern about qualified access to reality and
A belief that good data give direct access to the truth of the the material world. Science must adapt by using high-
material situation is an extreme form of realism, but there are quality data to make high-quality challenges to prevailing be-
many other realist positions that are entirely respectable and liefs honestly. Science also needs to be conscious that the
rather more philosophically sophisticated. Indeed, there is a currency of communication is always some sort of narrative.
plurality of notions of “realism” that occupy what is gener- The postmodern world may be a nightmare for Joe Friday and
ally considered an intuitive and commonsense middle ground. normal science (Kuhn 1962), but science still deserves to be
in systems ecology suggest that scientists should provide de- Under the modern rubric, the tension shifts to one between
scriptive narratives (rather than singular predictions). They reality and quality. The reason Pablo Picasso’s cubist portraits
recommend a style of adaptive management that ties multi- have distorted noses and eyes is that the artist is aware of the
ple possible system descriptions to issues of human prefer- profile that is the alternative point of view to full face. Mod-
ences. Our goal in this article is to elaborate on the concepts ern art, as well as modern science, goes beyond mere repre-
of quality (Pirsig 1974) and narrative as they relate to scien- sentation to capture various “essences” of reality. Picasso said
tific privilege in argumentation and society. We will differ- that by the age of 14 he could paint like Leonardo, but it took
entiate the process of complication from complexification, another 30 years for him to learn to paint like a child. Naive
and distinguish high-gain resources from low-gain resources external spectators often cannot distinguish a high-quality Pi-
because making such distinctions will give us new ways to de- casso from a child’s scribbles (see Figure 2); nor do they
scribe system organization and behavior. We will conclude by know how a cyclotron works or why it is important. Thus,
suggesting that science should not retreat defensively from privilege in the modern style of art and science is in the
postmodernism, but instead should reinvent and adapt itself hands of an “expert” audience of cultural connoisseurs or peer
in a rapidly changing postmodern age. scientists who are committed to a particular shared reality, the
external referent of quality. Privilege is conferred by the wider
Quality and narrative audience upon the experts because the experts claim that
image but also allows for near-instantaneous global distrib- Whereas in a modern world there is a belief in an ultimate
ution. Which is the original? In the hip-hop music scene, the true reference, in a postmodern world there is no such belief.
practice of “sampling” previous recordings has created a new In a postmodern world there are only narratives, and you must
frontier for copyright. take responsibility for the narratives you tell. It is inadequate
All of these examples show that the original, along with its to pretend some direct connection to truth and ontological
external referent to a shared reality, is denied privilege over reality when the scientist dons the white coat of authority. Re-
copies. Quality shifts away from the realism of the message in member the line in the 1984 movie Ghostbusters, “Back off,
the merely modern world to the technical achievements nec- man, I’m a scientist.” Instead of falling back on this out-
essary to maintain hyper-reality under postmodernism. Thus, moded authority, scientists must see their work as creating nar-
the maintenance of quality in a postmodern world becomes ratives. Narratives always have a narrator, who chooses when
problematic: If one tears down the elite high culture of crit- was “once upon a time,” and when “they all lived happily
ics and does not base standards on easily identified “originals,” ever after.” The beauty of narrative is that it is a powerful de-
how will standards and quality be maintained? For Funtowicz vice that normalizes across scales. Narrative deals with se-
and Ravetz, high standards lie in defining and practicing quences of events, and although events may be time depen-
“post-normal science” (1992, 1993, Ravetz 1999), which con- dent, they are also rate independent, and so possess a structural
fronts this contradiction of our time with an explicit emphasis quality that makes events into static things. It is possible to link
the minds of Bonnifield and Worster, or no narrative be- degree of continuous change. Therefore, truth in assumptions
yond the end of Plenty-coup’s story? is a moot point, and the scientist is not trying to ascertain
The critical point is that scientists always use narrative, and which assumptions are true. While confirmatory science
thus benefit from being self-conscious narrators. Science makes reasonable assumptions and gets reasonable results, nor-
cannot make an infinite number of observations, and so se- mal science’s refutation is more powerful. Unreasonable re-
lects, just like a narrator (Feyerabend 1962, Tainter and Lu- sults are helpful in that they point to a flaw in logic or an as-
cas 1983). Narrative is always selective and gains significance sumption one cannot afford to make. Counterintuitively, it
from how events are signified, as does good science when it is often particularly useful to make unreasonable assumptions.
gives reasons for its interpretations. As Cronon (1992) shows, Of course, a combination of unreasonable assumptions and
two historians (they could have been scientists) with the unreasonable results invites the comment “What did you ex-
same “facts” in front of them can construct two entirely dif- pect?” However, the combination of unreasonable assump-
ferent scenarios simply by changing the narrative. The full tions and reasonable results is cause for celebration (see Fig-
chronicle helps not a bit, because not only is a full account- ure 3). For instance, the primitive individual-based models for
ing of everything an impossibility, it is not a narrative, because forest simulation, such as the FORET models of Shugart and
no narrator has decided what mattered. Neither is attempt- West (1977), make grotesque assumptions about the arrange-
ing to make science account for everything a proper narra- ment of trees on the ground. Yet the models give remarkably
to institutionalize high-gain energy, but comes to rely on there is no history without nuance.” He preferred to report a
high-sulfur coal, tar sands, and oil shale. Environmental rich picture of what it was like to be there at the 1968
degradation would occur as extensions of the present-day Democratic convention police riot in Mayor Richard
problems of sulfur and global warming. Eventually, these Daley’s Chicago. We need new myths for new times, and the
dirty and difficult sources of carbon become too expensive, myth of the fair-minded, evenhanded journalist is as inap-
but the period over which they are used allows time for a move propriate as the myth of science finding the truth.
to low-gain sources of energy, such as wave, wind, or solar, but The postmodern world denies science the privilege of be-
in a centralized fashion. While many advocate a future that ing objective. But that does not and should not mean science
relies on renewable energy, its full implementation would has lost its privilege as something that should be taken more
not make good environmental news: Entire coastlines would seriously than most other human endeavors. It is important
be modified to capture wave power, while deserts would be that much science should continue to be conducted in a nar-
covered with arsenic-containing solar panels. The century or rowly focused arena of discourse, so that we scientists get high-
so of dirty carbon use would provide the massive infrastruc- quality models of how various small bits of scientific mod-
ture, and the central distribution system would remain use- els and their corresponding materiality work. We need to
ful before, during, and after the transition to renewable, low- continue to be meticulous and quantitative. But more than
gain energy. this, we need scientific models that can inform policy and ac-
Acknowledgments Lee RB. 1968. What hunters do for a living, or, how to make out on scarce
Marty Burd suggested to us that Attoid ants pass from low gain resources. Pages 30–48 in Lee RB, DeVore I, eds. Man the Hunter.
to high gain, and that the primitive species use caterpillar fe- Chicago: Aldine.
ces. Tom Brandner, Tanya Havlicek, Ron McCormick, Linda ———. 1972. Population growth and the beginnings of sedentary life
Puth, Mark Stevens, and the noontime sandbox group helped among the !Kung bushmen. Pages 329–342 in Spooner B, ed. Population
in developing many ideas in this paper. This research was sup- Growth: Anthropological Implications. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press.
ported by National Science Foundation Biocomplexity Grants Linderman F. 1962. Plenty-coups, Chief of the Crows. Lincoln: University of
DEB 008 3545 and SGER DEB 9703908 through the Univer- Nebraska Press.
Mailer N. 1968. Miami and the Siege of Chicago: An Informal History of the
sity of Wisconsin–Madison.
Republican and Democratic Conventions of 1968. New York: World.
Meir E, Karieva PM. 1997. Contributions of spatially explicit landscapes to
References cited conservation biology. Pages 497–507 in Fiedler PL, Karieva PM, eds. Con-
Ahl V, Allen TFH. 1996. Hierarchy Theory: A Vision, Vocabulary, and Epis-
servation Biology for the Coming Decade. New York: Chapman and Hall.
temology. New York: Columbia University Press.
Mooij WM, DeAngelis D. 1999. Error propagation in spatially explicit mod-
Allen TFH. 2001. The nature of the scale issue in experimentation. Pages
93–116 in Gardner R, Kennedy V, Kemp M, Petersen J, eds. Scaling Re- els: A reassessment. Conservation Biology 13: 930–933.
lations in Experimental Ecology. New York: Columbia University Press. Natoli J. 1997. A Primer to Postmodernity. Oxford (UK): Blackwell.
Allen TFH, Tainter JA, Hoekstra TW. 1999. Supply-side sustainability. Sys- Pattee HH. 1979. The complementarity principle in biological and social struc-