[go: up one dir, main page]

Jump to content

R. M. Hare

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
(Redirected from Richard M. Hare)

R. M. Hare
Hare in 1957
Born
Richard Mervyn Hare

(1919-03-21)21 March 1919
Backwell, England
Died29 January 2002(2002-01-29) (aged 82)
Ewelme, England
Spouse
Catherine Verney
(m. 1947)
ChildrenJohn E. Hare et al.
Academic background
Alma materBalliol College, Oxford
ThesisBooks: "The Language of Morals" (1952)
Doctoral advisorGilbert Ryle
Other advisorsGilbert Ryle, H.H. Price
Influences
Academic work
DisciplinePhilosophy
Sub-discipline
School or traditionAnalytic philosophy
Institutions
Doctoral studentsDenys Turner
Notable students
Main interests
Notable ideas
Influenced

Richard Mervyn Hare[a] FBA (21 March 1919 – 29 January 2002), usually cited as R. M. Hare, was a British moral philosopher who held the post of White's Professor of Moral Philosophy at the University of Oxford from 1966 until 1983. He subsequently taught for a number of years at the University of Florida. His meta-ethical theories were influential during the second half of the twentieth century.

Hare is best known for his development of prescriptivism as a meta-ethical theory, which he argues is supported by analysis of formal features of moral discourse, and for his defence of preference utilitarianism based on his prescriptivism.

Some of Hare's students, such as Brian McGuinness,[1] John Lucas,[2] and Bernard Williams[3] went on to become well-known philosophers.[4] Hare's son, John E. Hare, also became a philosopher. Peter Singer, known for his involvement with the animal liberation movement (who studied Hare's work as an honours student at the University of Melbourne and came to know Hare personally while he was an Oxford BPhil graduate student),[5] has explicitly adopted some elements of Hare's thought, though not his doctrine of universal prescriptivism.

Life and career

[edit]

Richard Hare was born on 21 March 1919 in Backwell, Somerset. He attended Rugby School in Warwickshire, followed in 1937 by Balliol College, Oxford, where he read greats (classics). Having joined the officer training corps whist still at Rugby, on the outbreak of World War II, he volunteered to serve with the Royal Artillery.[6]

Hare was taken as a prisoner of war by the Japanese from the fall of Singapore in 1942 to the end of the Second World War.[7] Hare's wartime experience had a lasting impact on his philosophical views, particularly his view that moral philosophy has an obligation to help people live their lives as moral beings. His earliest work in philosophy, which has never been published, dates from this period, and in it,[8][9][10] he tried to develop a system that might "serve as a guide to life in the harshest conditions", according to C. C. W. Taylor.[4]

He returned to Oxford after the war, and in 1947, married Catherine Verney, a marriage that produced a son and three daughters. (Hare's son, John E. Hare, is also a philosopher.) He was elected fellow and tutor in philosophy at Balliol from 1947 to 1966; honorary fellow at Balliol from 1974 to 2002; and was appointed Wilde Lecturer in Natural Religion, 1963–66; and White's Professor of Moral Philosophy, 1966–1983, which accompanied a move to Corpus Christi. He was president of the Aristotelian Society from 1972 to 1973. He left Oxford in 1983 to become Graduate Research Professor of Philosophy at the University of Florida at Gainesville, a post he held until 1994.[4][7]

After suffering a series of strokes, R. M. Hare died in Ewelme, Oxfordshire, on 29 January 2002.[11]

At his memorial service held at St Mary's Church, Oxford, in May of that year, Peter Singer delivered (as he felt Hare would have wished) a lecture on Hare's "Achievements in Moral Philosophy" which concluded by giving three "major, lasting" ones, namely, "restoring reason to moral argument, distinguishing intuitive and critical levels of moral thinking, and pioneering the development of ... applied ethics".[5]

Influences

[edit]

Hare was greatly influenced by the emotivism of A. J. Ayer and Charles L. Stevenson,[12] the ordinary language philosophy of J. L. Austin, a certain reading of the later philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein,[4] utilitarianism, and Immanuel Kant.

Hare held that ethical rules should not be based on a principle of utility, though he took into account utilitarian considerations. His hybrid approach to meta-ethics distinguishes him from classical utilitarians like Jeremy Bentham. His book Sorting Out Ethics might be interpreted as saying that Hare is as much a Kantian as he is a utilitarian, but other sources[13] disagree with this assessment. Although Hare used many concepts from Kant, especially the idea of universalisability, he was still a consequentialist, rather than a deontologist, in his normative ethical views. Hare himself addressed the possibility that Kant was a utilitarian like himself, in his "Could Kant Have Been a Utilitarian?"[14]

Universal prescriptivism

[edit]

In a series of books, especially The Language of Morals (1952), Freedom and Reason (1963), and Moral Thinking (1981), Hare gave shape to a theory that he called universal prescriptivism. According to this, moral terms such as 'good', 'ought' and 'right' have two logical or semantic properties: universalizability and prescriptivity. By the former, he meant that moral judgments must identify the situation they describe according to a finite set of universal terms, excluding proper names, but not definite descriptions. By the latter, he meant that moral agents must perform those acts they consider themselves to have an obligation to perform whenever they are physically and psychologically able to do so. In other words, he argued that it made no sense for someone to say, sincerely: "I ought to do X", and then fail to do X. This was identified by Frankena, Nobis and others as a major flaw in Hare's system, as it appeared to take no account of akrasia, or weakness of the will.[15][16][17]

Hare argued that the combination of universalizability and prescriptivity leads to a certain form of consequentialism, namely, preference utilitarianism. In brief, this means that we should act in such a way as to maximise the satisfaction of people's preferences.

Importance of specificity

[edit]

Hare departs from Kant's view that only the most general maxims of conduct be used (for example, "do not steal"), but the consequences ignored, when applying the categorical imperative. To ignore consequences leads to absurdity: for example, that it would be wrong to steal a terrorist's plans to blow up a nuclear facility. All the specific facts of a circumstance must be considered, and these include probable consequences. They also include the relevant, universal properties of the facts: for example, the psychological states of those involved.

Applied ethics and political philosophy

[edit]

While Hare was primarily interested in meta-ethics, he also made some important contributions to the fields of political philosophy and applied ethics. Among his essays within these fields those on the morality of slavery, abortion[18] and the Golden Rule, and on demi-vegetarianism have received the most attention. Hare's most important work in political philosophy and applied ethics is collected in the two volumes Essays on Political Morality (1989) and Essays on Bioethics (1993), both published by Oxford University Press.

Select works

[edit]
  • Hare, R. M. (1952). The Language of Morals. Oxford: Clarendon Press. OCLC 1034413.
  • Hare, R. M. (1972). Essays on Philosophical Method. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. ISBN 9780520323346.
  • Hare, R. M. (1977). Freedom and Reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 9780198810926.
  • Hare, R. M. (1981). Moral Thinking: its levels, method, and point. Oxford New York: Clarendon Press Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198246602.
  • Hare, R. M. (1982). "Ethical theory and Utilitarianism". In Sen, Amartya; Williams, Bernard (eds.). Utilitarianism and beyond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 22–38. ISBN 9780511611964.
  • Hare, R. M. (1983). Plato. Oxford New York: Clarendon Press Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780192875853.
  • Hare, R. M. (1989). Essays in Ethical Theory. Oxford England New York: Clarendon Press Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198240716.
  • Hare, R. M. (1989). Essays on Political Morality. Oxford New York: Clarendon Press Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198249955.
  • Hare, R. M. (1992). Essays on Religion and Education. Oxford, New York: Clarendon Press Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198249962.
  • Hare, R. M. (1993). Essays on Bioethics. Clarendon Press. ISBN 9780198236788.

*For a more complete list of publications see the annotated bibliography by Keith Burgess-Jackson.[19]

See also

[edit]

Notes

[edit]
  1. ^ Pronounced /hɛər/.

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Obituaries, Telegraph (9 January 2020). "Brian McGuinness, world-renowned expert on Ludwig Wittgenstein – obituary". The Telegraph. ISSN 0307-1235. Retrieved 13 March 2021.
  2. ^ Lucas, John Randloph (23 December 2002). "Balliol College – History – Past Members – Richard Hare – A Memoir". Archived from the original on 23 December 2002. Retrieved 8 May 2019.
  3. ^ McMahan, Jeff (2013). "Bernard Williams: A Reminiscence". The Moral Philosophy of Bernard Williams. Perry, Alexandra; Herrera, C. D. (Christopher D.). Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing. p. 21. ISBN 9781443866002. OCLC 887508392. Archived from the original on 6 August 2020. Retrieved 8 May 2019.
  4. ^ a b c d Taylor, C. C. W. (5 February 2002). "Professor R. M. Hare". The Independent. Archived from the original on 23 April 2021. Retrieved 6 December 2016.
  5. ^ a b Singer, Peter (2002). "R. M. Hare's Achievements in Moral Philosophy" (PDF). Utilitas. 14 (3): 309–317. doi:10.1017/S0953820800003629. ISSN 1741-6183. S2CID 145757614. Archived from the original (PDF) on 8 September 2006.
  6. ^ Price, A. W. (2009). "Hare, Richard Mervyn (1919–2002), philosopher". Oxford Dictionary of National Biography (online ed.). Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/ref:odnb/76706. Archived from the original on 11 March 2021. Retrieved 5 May 2021.{{cite encyclopedia}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link) (Subscription or UK public library membership required.)
  7. ^ a b O'Grady, Jane (1 February 2002). "Richard Hare". The Guardian. Retrieved 6 December 2016.
  8. ^ "OUP: R. M. Hare in Conversation ..." 11 December 2004. Archived from the original on 11 December 2004. Retrieved 8 May 2019. Once, on leave from the Army, I sat down at home and wrote an essay of some twenty pages on 'My Philosophy' – a very pretentious thing to do, but pardonable, since we all thought we would be killed in the War, and I wanted to put it on record. ... When I was taken prisoner at the fall of Singapore, I looted a beautiful ledger from the office in Changi jail, and used it to expand the essay into a book of some 150 pages, written a few pages at a time in manuscript when I had the leisure during my three and a half years in prison. ... This book travelled with me on my back almost all the way to the Thai–Burma frontier.
  9. ^ Price, Anthony. "Richard Mervyn Hare > Hare's "An Essay in Monism" (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)". plato.stanford.edu. Retrieved 8 May 2019. When Singapore fell, he looted a ledger from Changi jail, and started writing a monograph called "An Essay in Monism". He carried this on his back during the march, and completed it just before being released. He typed it out, making multiple copies, once he was free ... It remains very little known ... and is of interest both in itself, and for points of connection with his mature thinking. As it is only accessible within the archives of Balliol College, Oxford: it may be apt to supply a density of quotation. ...
  10. ^ Singer, Peter (2002). "R. M. Hare's Achievements in Moral Philosophy" (PDF). Utilitas. 14 (3): 309–317. doi:10.1017/S0953820800003629. ISSN 1741-6183. S2CID 145757614. Archived from the original (PDF) on 8 September 2006. he [Hare] was never afraid to ask the most controversial questions, such as What is Wrong with Slavery? and his answers were always enlightening. (Indeed, that particular paper is one that he was able to write with an authority that few others could possess, since, as he notes, he had in a manner of speaking been a slave, when as a prisoner of the Japanese he worked on the Burma railway.)
  11. ^ Fox, Margalit (17 February 2002). "R. M. Hare, British Philosopher, Dies at 82; Looked for Logic in Morals". The New York Times. Retrieved 6 December 2016.
  12. ^ Benn, Piers. "R. M. Hare (1919–2002) | Issue 35 | Philosophy Now". philosophynow.org. Retrieved 9 May 2019. The theory of emotivism, defended in different ways by C. L. Stevenson and the young A. J. Ayer, formed the background to Hare's early work, and he was concerned both to acknowledge its insights and correct its inadequacies. ... Hare didn't entirely reject emotivism, but ... He was consistently opposed to the 'descriptivism' that held that the meaning of moral predicates – good, bad, right, wrong, ought etc. – was exhaustively descriptive of moral features of reality.
  13. ^ Curtler, Hugh Mercer (1971). "What Kant Might Say to Hare" (PDF). Mind. 80 (318): 295–297. doi:10.1093/mind/LXXX.318.295. ISSN 0026-4423. Archived from the original (PDF) on 23 January 2020.
  14. ^ Hare, R. M. (1993). "Could Kant Have Been a Utilitarian?". In Dancy, R. M. (ed.). Kant and Critique: New Essays in Honor of W.H. Werkmeister. Synthese Library. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands. pp. 91–113. doi:10.1007/978-94-015-8179-0_4. ISBN 978-94-015-8179-0. S2CID 145446053. Retrieved 6 May 2021.
  15. ^ Nobis, Nathan. "CHAPTER 4: Hare's Universal Rational Prescriptivism". Morehouse College. Archived from the original on 13 October 2014. Retrieved 18 January 2014.
  16. ^ Frankena, William (July 1988). "Hare on moral weakness and the definition of morality" (PDF). Ethics. 98 (4): 779–792. doi:10.1086/293005. S2CID 144508385. Archived from the original (PDF) on 9 November 2013.
  17. ^ Hare, R. M. (1991). "Universal Prescriptivism". A Companion to ethics. Peter Singer (ed.). Oxford, UK: Blackwell Reference. ISBN 0-631-16211-9. OCLC 22762715.
  18. ^ Hare, R. M. (Spring 1975). "Abortion and the Golden Rule" (PDF). Philosophy and Public Affairs. 4 (3): 201–222. PMID 11661183.
  19. ^ Burgess-Jackson, Keith. "(Richard Mervyn Hare) An Annotated Bibliography" (PDF). Archived from the original on 4 May 2006. Retrieved 12 December 2023.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: unfit URL (link)

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]
Academic offices
Preceded by White's Professor of Moral Philosophy
1966–1983
Vacant
Title next held by
Bernard Williams
Preceded by Hägerström Lecturer
1991
Succeeded by
Professional and academic associations
Preceded by President of the Aristotelian Society
1972–1973
Succeeded by