[go: up one dir, main page]

In algebra and number theory, Euclid's lemma is a lemma that captures a fundamental property of prime numbers:[note 1]

Euclid's lemma — If a prime p divides the product ab of two integers a and b, then p must divide at least one of those integers a or b.

For example, if p = 19, a = 133, b = 143, then ab = 133 × 143 = 19019, and since this is divisible by 19, the lemma implies that one or both of 133 or 143 must be as well. In fact, 133 = 19 × 7.

The lemma first appeared in Euclid's Elements, and is a fundamental result in elementary number theory.

If the premise of the lemma does not hold, that is, if p is a composite number, its consequent may be either true or false. For example, in the case of p = 10, a = 4, b = 15, composite number 10 divides ab = 4 × 15 = 60, but 10 divides neither 4 nor 15.

This property is the key in the proof of the fundamental theorem of arithmetic.[note 2] It is used to define prime elements, a generalization of prime numbers to arbitrary commutative rings. Euclid's lemma shows that in the integers irreducible elements are also prime elements. The proof uses induction so it does not apply to all integral domains.

Formulations

edit

Euclid's lemma is commonly used in the following equivalent form:

Theorem — If   is a prime number that divides the product   and does not divide   then it divides  

Euclid's lemma can be generalized as follows from prime numbers to any integers.

Theorem — If an integer n divides the product ab of two integers, and is coprime with a, then n divides b.

This is a generalization because a prime number p is coprime with an integer a if and only if p does not divide a.

History

edit

The lemma first appears as proposition 30 in Book VII of Euclid's Elements. It is included in practically every book that covers elementary number theory.[4][5][6][7][8]

The generalization of the lemma to integers appeared in Jean Prestet's textbook Nouveaux Elémens de Mathématiques in 1681.[9]

In Carl Friedrich Gauss's treatise Disquisitiones Arithmeticae, the statement of the lemma is Euclid's Proposition 14 (Section 2), which he uses to prove the uniqueness of the decomposition product of prime factors of an integer (Theorem 16), admitting the existence as "obvious". From this existence and uniqueness he then deduces the generalization of prime numbers to integers.[10] For this reason, the generalization of Euclid's lemma is sometimes referred to as Gauss's lemma, but some believe this usage is incorrect[11] due to confusion with Gauss's lemma on quadratic residues.

Proofs

edit

The two first subsections, are proofs of the generalized version of Euclid's lemma, namely that: if n divides ab and is coprime with a then it divides b.

The original Euclid's lemma follows immediately, since, if n is prime then it divides a or does not divide a in which case it is coprime with a so per the generalized version it divides b.

Using Bézout's identity

edit

In modern mathematics, a common proof involves Bézout's identity, which was unknown at Euclid's time.[12] Bézout's identity states that if x and y are coprime integers (i.e. they share no common divisors other than 1 and −1) there exist integers r and s such that

 

Let a and n be coprime, and assume that n|ab. By Bézout's identity, there are r and s such that

 

Multiply both sides by b:

 

The first term on the left is divisible by n, and the second term is divisible by ab, which by hypothesis is divisible by n. Therefore their sum, b, is also divisible by n.

By induction

edit

The following proof is inspired by Euclid's version of Euclidean algorithm, which proceeds by using only subtractions.

Suppose that   and that n and a are coprime (that is, their greatest common divisor is 1). One has to prove that n divides b. Since   there is an integer q such that   Without loss of generality, one can suppose that n, q, a, and b are positive, since the divisibility relation is independent from the signs of the involved integers.

For proving this by strong induction, we suppose that the result has been proved for all positive lower values of ab.

There are three cases:

If n = a, coprimality implies n = 1, and n divides b trivially.

If n < a, one has

 

The positive integers an and n are coprime: their greatest common divisor d must divide their sum, and thus divides both n and a. It results that d = 1, by the coprimality hypothesis. So, the conclusion follows from the induction hypothesis, since 0 < (an) b < ab.

Similarly, if n > a one has

 

and the same argument shows that na and a are coprime. Therefore, one has 0 < a (bq) < ab, and the induction hypothesis implies that na divides bq; that is,   for some integer. So,   and, by dividing by na, one has   Therefore,   and by dividing by a, one gets   the desired result.

Proof of Elements

edit

Euclid's lemma is proved at the Proposition 30 in Book VII of Euclid's Elements. The original proof is difficult to understand as is, so we quote the commentary from Euclid (1956, pp. 319–332).

Proposition 19
If four numbers be proportional, the number produced from the first and fourth is equal to the number produced from the second and third; and, if the number produced from the first and fourth be equal to that produced from the second and third, the four numbers are proportional.[note 3]
Proposition 20
The least numbers of those that have the same ratio with them measures those that have the same ratio the same number of times—the greater the greater and the less the less.[note 4]
Proposition 21
Numbers prime to one another are the least of those that have the same ratio with them.[note 5]
Proposition 29
Any prime number is prime to any number it does not measure.[note 6]
Proposition 30
If two numbers, by multiplying one another, make the same number, and any prime number measures the product, it also measures one of the original numbers.[note 7]
Proof of 30
If c, a prime number, measure ab, c measures either a or b.
Suppose c does not measure a.
Therefore c, a are prime to one another. VII. 29
Suppose abmc.
Therefore c : ab : m. VII. 19
Hence [VII. 20, 21bnc, where n is some integer.
Therefore c measures b.
Similarly, if c does not measure b, c measures a.
Therefore c measures one or other of the two numbers a, b.
Q.E.D.[18]

See also

edit

Footnotes

edit

Notes

edit
  1. ^ It is also called Euclid's first theorem[1][2] although that name more properly belongs to the side-angle-side condition for showing that triangles are congruent.[3]
  2. ^ In general, to show that a domain is a unique factorization domain, it suffices to prove Euclid's lemma and the ascending chain condition on principal ideals.
  3. ^ If abcd, then adbc; and conversely.[13]
  4. ^ If abcd, and a, b are the least numbers among those that have the same ratio, then cna, dnb, where n is some integer.[14]
  5. ^ If abcd, and a, b are prime to one another, then a, b are the least numbers among those that have the same ratio.[15]
  6. ^ If a is prime and does not measure b, then a, b are prime to one another.[16]
  7. ^ If c, a prime number, measure ab, c measures either a or b.[17]

Citations

edit
  1. ^ Bajnok 2013, Theorem 14.5
  2. ^ Joyner, Kreminski & Turisco 2004, Proposition 1.5.8, p. 25
  3. ^ Martin 2012, p. 125
  4. ^ Gauss 2001, p. 14
  5. ^ Hardy, Wright & Wiles 2008, Theorem 3
  6. ^ Ireland & Rosen 2010, Proposition 1.1.1
  7. ^ Landau 1999, Theorem 15
  8. ^ Riesel 1994, Theorem A2.1
  9. ^ Euclid 1994, pp. 338–339
  10. ^ Gauss 2001, Article 19
  11. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Euclid's Lemma". MathWorld.
  12. ^ Hardy, Wright & Wiles 2008, §2.10
  13. ^ Euclid 1956, p. 319
  14. ^ Euclid 1956, p. 321
  15. ^ Euclid 1956, p. 323
  16. ^ Euclid 1956, p. 331
  17. ^ Euclid 1956, p. 332
  18. ^ Euclid 1956, pp. 331−332

References

edit
edit