Modenity of Frankenstein
Modenity of Frankenstein
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Studies in English
Literature, 1500-1900
Responsible Crea
and the "Moderni
Mary Shelley's Pr
HARRIET HUSTIS
creation of a huma
a great hindrance t
a gigantic stature"
nitude and comple
sible creativity, Fr
parts" in an attem
the grandeur of h
ative precision for
purely theoretical
life with blatant d
Ultimately, this at
the moral complex
concrete manifesta
sistently extols th
as it narrates the s
his family and fri
actions are ironica
cantly, Frankenste
the disasters he he
as "Chance" or an "
Interestingly, Car
cal Theory and Wo
of this tendency t
thetical terms wit
Frankenstein, nam
creativity. Such ph
"useful for the dis
of justice and for m
procity."'5 Howeve
appeals to an ethic
application of a "for
dilemma may ultim
consequence which
It is precisely thi
sequence" which el
insistent claims th
his misfortunes. E
ernization of the P
when responsible cr
and a purportedly
the most crucial el
Pity and the willin
(regardless of whe
stein dreams of c
unprecedented m
me as its creator
would owe their b
his child so comp
emphasis). Frankenstein similarly remembers that the
"fulfill[ment]" of his own parents' "duties" was carried out "[w]ith
[a] deep consciousness of what they owed towards the being to
which they had given life" (pp. 291-2, my emphasis).
Thus, the moral conflict between Frankenstein and his mon-
ster exposes a fundamental shortcoming of objective principles
of justice: they cannot adequately (i.e., "sympathetically") assess
the responsibilities of a creator for the life he creates. The moral-
ity of Prometheus's actions stems, not from his abstract assess-
ment of what is "right" or "due" to human beings, but from an
overtly sympathetic response to their abandoned and helpless
condition. In effect, Shelley's modernization of the Prometheus
legend suggests that (male) participants in a moral conflict may
invoke "justice" and insist on theoretical objectivity simply to avoid
acknowledging responsibility for the dilemmas they have created,
conflicts which, when neglected, take on a life of their own. The
modernity of Shelley's Prometheus figure is illustrative of how,
when Promethean pity is overlooked in favor of appeals to jus-
tice, "fairness" can become little more than a means of denying
involvement in the problems of others, even when those "others"
are a creator's own progeny.16
Not surprisingly, therefore, Frankenstein's "measurements"
of reciprocity, his determination of what is "right" and what he
"owes" his monster, are exposed as inherently equivocal, subject
to the whims of his ever changing perception of the creature's
dilemma. Frankenstein initially admits the "justice" of the
monster's demand for a mate and eventually concludes that "the
justice due both to him and my fellow creatures demanded of me
that I should comply with his request" (p. 415, my emphasis).
After reconsidering his creature's demands, however, Franken-
stein ultimately refuses to create a companion for the monster:
"'Had I right, for my own benefit, to inflict this curse upon ever-
lasting generations? I had before been moved by the sophisms of
the being I had created; I had been struck senseless by his fiend-
ish threats; but now, for the first time, the wickedness of my
promise burst upon me; I shuddered to think that future ages
might curse me as their pest, whose selfishness had not hesi-
tated to buy its own peace at the price, perhaps, of the existence
The "modernity"
traced to Victor F
that "[t]he willin
judgment stems f
indirect action, t
Responsibility for
injunction not to
tains the ideal of
It is this failure t
action, to self and
leaves Frankenstein
Moritz and the murders of William, Elizabeth, and Clerval: he
can only retrospectively curse the injustice of his fate, a gesture
which tragically suggests that such moral recognition ultimately
eludes him.
The myth of Prometheus thus serves as a particularly reso
nant example of the necessity of assuming "responsibility for judg
ment," particularly when it involves the creative act. Wherea
Prometheus dares to pity an abandoned creation (the human ra
at great personal cost, and despite the fact that he is not its physi
cal creator, his "modernized" counterpart, Frankenstein, fails t
exercise such moral responsibility for the single life he creat
because he regards creativity as an abstraction. Mary Shelley's
reconfiguration of the legend of Prometheus emphasizes the f
that the responsibilities of a creator for his progeny cannot b
conceived of as a debt to be paid or an obligation (or "duty") to
fulfilled; to do so is to misunderstand the creative act in a pot
tially disastrous manner. Ultimately, this mistake is one whic
Mary Shelley herself will carefully avoid when she accounts f
the creation of her own "hideous progeny" in the 1831 preface
Frankenstein.
The explanatory preface that Mary Shelley added to her no
in 1831 has remained a site of extensive critical discord; perh
no other preface in literary history has been so frequently e
ployed to detract from the significance of the text that it preced
or to diminish the genius and self-conscious artistry of its a
thor. For example, George Levine and U. C. Knoepflmacher int
duce their anthology of critical essays on Frankenstein by
questioning the purposiveness of the novel's textual "energies
"How much of the book's complexity is actually the result of M
Shelley's self-conscious art and how much is merely the prod
of the happy circumstances of subject, moment, milieu? The no
intimates that it knows little about its implications (although
NOTES