Emergence Explained Entities 08.01
Emergence Explained Entities 08.01
Emergence Explained Entities 08.01
1 Introduction
In [1] we characterized emergent phenomena as phenomena that may be described inde-
pendently of their implementations. We distinguished between static emergence (emer-
gence that is implemented by energy wells) and dynamic emergence (emergence that is
implemented by energy flows). We argued that emergence (of both forms) produces ob-
jectively real phenomena (because they are distinguishable by their entropy and mass
characteristics) but that interaction among emergent phenomena is epiphenomenal and
can always be reduced to the fundamental forces of physics. Our focus in that paper was
on the phenomenon of emergence itself. In this paper we explore the two types of emer-
gence, focusing especially on dynamic emergence.
1.1 Entities
As human beings we naturally seem to think in terms of entities—things or objects. Yet
the question of how one might characterize what should and should not be considered an
entity is still unresolved as a philosophical issue. (See [Boyd], [Laylock], [Miller],
[Rosen], [Varzi Fall ‘04].)
We propose to define a physically based entity as an instance of emergence. This corres-
pond to our intuitive sense for how we think about entities in a great many cases. Physic-
al entities (such as an atom, a molecule, a pencil, a table, a solar system, a galaxy) are all
instances of static emergence. These entities are held together in energy wells of various
sorts. Biological entities (such as you and I) and social entities (such as a social club, a
corporation, or a country) are instances of dynamic emergence. These entities all exist as
a result of energy flows of various sorts. (We examine many of the preceding examples in
more detail below.)
On the other hand, what might be considered conceptual (or Platonic) entities such as
numbers, mathematical sets (and other mathematical constructs), properties, relations,
propositions, categories named by common nouns (such as “cat”), and ideas in general
are not instances of emergence. Nor are literary products such as poems and novels, sci-
entific papers, or computer programs (when considered as texts). Time instances (e.g.,
midnight 31 December 1999), durations (e.g., a minute), and segments (e.g., the 20 th cen-
tury) are also not instances of emergence. Neither are the comparable constructs with re-
spect to space and distance. An entity as we define it always consists at least in part of
matter—which is arranged to implement some independently describable abstraction.
Since none of the preceding conceptual entities involve matter, none of them are physical
entities according to our definition.1
2 Static entities
Statically emergent entities (static entities for short) are created when the fundamental
forces of nature bind matter together. The nucleus of any atom (other than simple Hydro-
gen, whose nucleus consist of a single proton) is a static entity. It results from the applica-
tion of the strong nuclear force, which binds the nucleons together in the nucleus. Simil-
arly any atom (the nucleus along with the atom’s electrons) is also a static entity. An atom
is a consequence of the electromagnetic force, which binds the atom’s electrons to its
nucleus. Molecules are also bound together by the electromagnetic force. On a much lar-
ger scale, astronomical bodies, e.g., the earth, are bound together by gravity, as are solar
systems and galaxies.
Like all entities, static entities have properties which may be described independently of
how they are constructed. As Weinberg [W] points out, “a diamond [may be described in
terms of its hardness even though] it doesn't make sense to talk about the hardness … of
individual ‘elementary’ particles.” The hardness of a diamond may be characterized and
measured independently of how diamonds achieve that property—which as Weinberg
also points out is a consequence of how diamonds are implemented, namely, their “car-
bon atoms … can fit together neatly.”
A distinguishing feature of static entities (as with static emergence in general) is that the
mass of any one of them is strictly smaller than the sum of the masses of its components.
This may be seen most clearly in nuclear fission and fusion, in which one starts and ends
with the same number of atomic components—electrons, protons, and neutrons—but
1
We explore the relationship between ideas and computation in [If a Tree].
2
Recall Weinberg characterization of petty reductionism as the “doctrine that things behave the way they
do because of the properties of their constituents.”
which nevertheless converts mass into energy. This raises the obvious question: which
mass was converted to energy? The answer has to do with the strong nuclear force, which
implements what is called the “binding energy” of nucleons within a nucleus. For ex-
ample, a helium nucleus (also known as an alpha particle, two protons and two neutrons
bound together), which is one of the products of hydrogen fusion, has less mass than the
sum of the masses of the protons and neutrons that make it up.3 The missing mass is re-
leased as energy.
The same entity-mass relationship holds for all static entities. An atom or molecule has
less mass (by a negligible but real amount) than the sum of the masses of its components
taken separately. The solar system has less mass (by a negligible but real amount) than
the mass of the sun and the planets taken separately. Thus the entropy of these entities is
lower than the entropy of the components as an unorganized collection. In other words, a
static entity is distinguishable by the fact that it has lower mass and lower entropy than its
components taken separately. Static entities exist in what is often called an energy well;
they require energy to pull their components apart. Static entities are also at an energy
equilibrium.
Manufactured or constructed artifacts exhibit static emergence. The binding force that
holds manufactured static entities together is typically the electromagnetic force, which
we exploit when we use nails, glue, screws, etc. to bind static entities together into new
static entities. A house, for example, has the statically emergent property number-of-bed-
rooms, which is a property of (a way of describing) the house from the entity perspective.
A house implements the property of having a certain number of bedrooms by the way in
which it is constructed from its components.
A static entity consists of a fixed collection of components over which it supervenes. By
specifying the states and conditions of its components, one fixes the properties of the en-
tity. But static entities that undergo repair and maintenance, such as houses, no longer
consist of a fixed collection of component elements thereby raising the question of
whether such entities really do supervene over their components. We resolve this issue
when we discuss Theseus’ ship.
3 Dynamic entities
Dynamic entities are instances of dynamic emergence. Dynamic emergence occurs when
energy flows through and modifies an open system. As in the case with all emergence,
dynamic emergence results in the organization of matter in a way that differs from how it
would be organized without the energy flowing through it. That is, dynamic entities have
properties as entities that may be described independently of how those properties are im-
plemented. Dynamic entities include dissipative, biological, and social entities—and as
we discuss below, hurricanes. In many but not necessarily all cases, the very existence of
the dynamic entity as an entity—its reduced entropy and its increased mass—depends on
the flow of energy. In the case of dissipative entities, the entity would exist as a static en-
tity even when energy is not flowing through it.
3
It turns out that iron nuclei lack the most mass. Energy from fusion is possible for elements lighter than
iron; energy from fission is possible for elements heavier than iron.
4
Another common example of a dissipative structure is the Belousov-Zhabotinsky (BZ) reaction, which in
some ways is a chemical watch. We designed digital clocks to tell time. We didn’t design BZ reactions to tell time.
Yet in some sense they both do. That one surprises us and the other doesn’t shouldn’t mislead us into putting them
into different categories of phenomena.
5
In all our examples, the form in which energy is delivered also matters. An electric current will produce
different effects from a thermal energy source when introduced into a digital clock and a Rayleigh-Bénard device.
atmospheric and oceanic currents, will change disastrously. When energy is flowing
through it, a dissipative entity is by definition far from equilibrium. So a dissipative entity
is a static entity that is maintained in a far-from-equilibrium state.
6
A characterization of a hurricane as a vertical heat engine may be found in Wikipedia. (URL as of
9/1/2005: http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hurricane.) The hurricane description is paraphrased from NASA, “Hur-
ricanes: The Greatest Storms on Earth,” (URL as of 3/2005 http://earthobservatory.nasa.gov/Library/Hurricanes/.)
7
Recall that a set of higher level predicates is said to supervene over a set of lower level predicates if a
configuration of truth values for the lower level predicates determines the truth values for the higher level predic-
ates. We are using the term supervene loosely to say that an entity supervenes over its components.
Furthermore, the longer a hurricane persists, the larger its supervenience base. Much of
the matter in a hurricane’s supervenience base is likely also to be included in the super-
venience bases of other hurricanes. Like Weinberg’s example of quarks being composed
(at least momentarily) of protons, hurricanes are at least partially composed of each other.
Thus petty reductionism is not particularly useful for macro-level dynamic entities which
cycle matter through themselves—as most dynamic entities do.
lead to their weakening or destruction. Social entities are more vulnerable still. Some of
their components (people) are simultaneously components of other social entities—often
resulting it divided loyalties.
[Sidebar] Autonomy
The notion of an autonomy seems central to how we look at the world. Most people will
acknowledge that the kinds of entities that the biological and social sciences deal with
seem somehow different from those of physics and chemistry. A major part of that differ-
ence is the apparent ability of those entities to act on their own, i.e., their autonomy.
For millennia we have found it convenient to partition the world into two realms: the an-
imate and the inanimate. Elements of the inanimate world are ruled by, are subject to, and
are often victims of external forces. Elements of the animate world are capable of
autonomous action and seem to have some control over their fate. Recall that this is why
Brownian motion posed such a problem: how can inanimate particles look so much like
they are moving autonomously?
For the past half-millennium civilization has pursued, with significant success, the dream
of creating autonomous sources of action. We have built machines about which it can be
said that to varying degrees they act on their own. We do not yet confuse our machines
with biological life, and we have not yet managed to construct biological life “from
scratch.” But the boundaries between human artifacts, natural biological life, and hybrids
of the two are becoming more and more subtle—and they are likely to disappear within
the lifetimes of many of us.
So, what do we mean by autonomy? In non-political contexts, the term autonomous is
taken to mean something like not controlled by outside forces. But any material entity is
subject to outside, i.e., physical, forces. Nothing is free from the laws of physics. Instead
of defining autonomy to require imperviousness to outside forces, it makes more sense to
understand autonomy to imply the ability to control—at least to some extent—how an en-
tity is affected by outside forces. Thus we suggest that an entity is autonomous to the ex-
tent that it shapes the way it is affected by outside forces.
But this is another way of looking at how we have defined a dynamic entity. Every dy-
namic entity is autonomous to some degree since they shape how the energy that flows
through them is used. Most biological and social entities do more than just shape the
“raw” energy flows that they encounter. Most biological and social entities are able to ac-
quire energy in some “frozen” form (such as food or money8) and to convert it to energy
as needed. Also, these entities often have an ability to seek out energy in their environ-
ments rather than just waiting for energy to be pumped into them. Furthermore, many of
these entities are capable of using many forms of energy and energy supplied at many
levels of intensity.
Thus the notion of autonomy seems to depend on the flexibility with which a dynamic
entity is able to deal with energy. It seems appropriate that autonomy should be tied to a
notion as fundamental as energy. In the previous article we noted that causality is always
reducible to the primitive forces of physics. An entity’s autonomy is therefore a measure
of the extent to which it is able to direct and control those fundamental forces—and
hence the extent to which it can influence causal relationships.
Software in general runs for free. Even agents in agent-based models run for free. 9. Al-
though that may be a useful abstraction, we should recognize that we are leaving out
something important. In the real world one needs energy to drive processes. To run real
software in the real world requires a real computer, which uses real energy. A theory of
thermodynamic computation is needed to integrate the notions of energy, entities, and
computing. The problem is that the real energy that drives software is not visible to the
software itself. Software does not have to pay its own energy bill. Until we find a way to
integrate the real energy cost of running software into the software itself, we are unlikely
to build a successful artificial life model.
4 The environment
Consider the following from Weinberg.
[A]part from historical accidents that by definition cannot be ex-
plained, the [human] nervous system [has] evolved to what [it is] en-
tirely because of the principles of macroscopic physics and chemistry,
which in turn are what they are entirely because of the principles of
the standard model of elementary particles.
Note Weinberg’s reference to historical accidents—which we also saw earlier, in his
definition of grand reductionism.
Grand reductionism is … the view that all of nature is the way it is
(with certain qualifications about initial conditions and historical acci-
dents) because of simple universal laws, to which all other scientific
laws may in some sense be reduced.
Even though Weinberg gives historical accidents as important a role in shaping the world
as he does the principles of physics, he does so grudgingly, seemingly attempting to dis-
miss them in a throw-away subordinate clause. This is misleading, especially given Wein-
berg’s example—evolution. Contrary to his implication, the human nervous system (and
the designs of biological organisms in general) evolved as they did not primarily because
of the principles of physics and chemistry but primarily because of the environment in
which that evolution took place.
9
Many agent-based and artificial life models acknowledge the importance of energy by imposing an artifi-
cial price for persistence, but we are not aware of any in which the cost of persistence is fully integrated into the
functioning of the entity.
10
Eric Jakobsson at the Understanding Complex Systems Symposium, University of Illinois, Champagne-
Urbana, Ill, May 2006.
This really is not so foreign to elementary particle physics. The Pauli exclusion principle,
which prevents two fermions from occupying the same quantum state, formalizes a con-
straint the environment imposes on elementary particles.11
Functionalism too has an environmental focus. By definition functionality is a relation-
ship between something and its environment. As Fodor points out,
references to can openers, mousetraps, camshafts, calculators and
the like bestrew the pages of functionalist philosophy. To make a bet-
ter mousetrap is to devise a new kind of mechanism whose behavior
is reliable with respect to the high-level regularity “live mouse in,
dead mouse out.”
Thus although neither Weinberg nor Fodor focuses on this issue explicitly—in fact, they
both tend to downplay it—they both apparently agree that the environment within which
something exists is important.
4.3 Stigmergy
Once one has autonomous entities (or agents) that persist in their environment, the ways
in which complexity can develop grows explosively. Prior to agents, to get something
new, one had to build it as a layer on top of some existing substrate. As we have seen,
nature has found a number of amazing abstractions along with some often surprising
ways to implement them. Nonetheless, this construction mechanism is relatively ponder-
ous. Layered hierarchies of abstractions are powerful, but they are not what one might
characterize as lightweight or responsive to change. Agents change all that.
Half a century ago, Pierre-Paul Grasse invented [Grasse] the term stigmergy to help de-
scribe how social insect societies function. The basic insight is that when the behavior of
an entity depends to at least some extent on the state of its environment, it is possible to
modify that entity’s behavior by changing the state of the environment. Grasse used the
term “stigmergy” for this sort of indirect communication and control. This sort of inter-
play between agents and their environment often produces epiphenomenal effects that are
useful to the agents. Often those effects may be understood in terms of formal abstrac-
tions. Sometimes it is easier to understand them less formally.
Two of the most widely cited examples of stigmergic interaction are ant foraging and bird
flocking. In ant foraging, ants that have found a food source leave pheromone markers
that other ants use to make their way to that food source. In bird flocking, each bird de-
termines how it will move at least in part by noting the positions and velocities of its
neighboring birds.
The resulting epiphenomena are that food is gathered and flocks form. Presumably these
epiphenomena could be formalized in terms of abstract effects that obeyed a formal set of
rules—in the same way that the rules for gliders and Turing Machines can abstracted
11
This was pointed out to me by Eshel Ben-Jacob [private communication].
away from their implementation by Game of Life rules. But often the effort required to
generate such abstract theories doesn’t seem worth the effort—as long as the results are
what one wants.
Here are some additional examples of stigmergy.
• When buyers and sellers interact in a market, one gets market epiphenomena. Eco-
nomics attempts to formalize how those interactions may be abstracted into theories.
• We often find that laws, rules, and regulations have both intended and unintended
consequences. In this case the laws, rules, and regulations serve as the environment
within which agents act. As the environment changes, so does the behavior of the
agents.
• Both sides of the evo-devo (evolution-development) synthesis [Carroll] exhibit stig-
mergic emergence. On the “evo” side, species create environmental effects for each
other as do sexes within species.
• The “devo” side is even more stigmergic. Genes, the switches that control gene ex-
pression, and the proteins that genes produce when expressed all have environmental
effects on each other.
• Interestingly enough, the existence of gene switches was discovered in the investiga-
tion of another stigmergic phenomenon. Certain bacteria generate an enzyme to digest
lactose, but they do it only when lactose is present. How do the bacteria “know” when
to generate the enzyme?
It turns out to be simple. The gene for the enzyme exists in the bacteria, but its expres-
sion is normally blocked by a protein that is attached to the DNA sequence just before
the enzyme gene. This is called a gene expression switch.
When lactose is in the environment, it infuses into the body of the bacteria and binds to
the protein that blocks the expression of the gene. This causes the protein to detach
from the DNA thereby “turning on” the gene and allowing it to be expressed.
The lactose enzyme switch is a lovely illustration of stigmergic design. As we described
the mechanism above, it seems that lactose itself turns on the switch that causes the
lactose-digesting enzyme to be produced. If one were thinking about the design of such
a system, one might imagine that the lactose had been designed so that it would bind to
that switch. But of course, lactose wasn’t “designed” to do that. It existed prior to the
switch. The bacteria evolved a switch that lactose would bind to. So the lactose must be
understood as being part of the environment to which the bacteria adapted by evolving
a switch to which lactose would bind. How clever; how simple; how stigmergic!
• Cellular automata operate stigmergically. Each cell serves as an environment for its
neighbors. As we have seen, epiphenomena may include gliders and Turing Ma-
chines.
• Even the operation of the Turing Machine as an abstraction may be understood stig-
mergically. The head of a Turing Machine (the equivalent of an autonomous agent)
consults the tape, which serves as its environment, to determine how to act. By writ-
ing on the tape, it leaves markers in its environment to which it may return—not un-
like the way foraging ants leave pheromone markers in their environment. When the
head returns to a marker, that marker helps the head determine how to act at that later
time.
• In fact, one may understand all computations as being stigmergic with respect to a
computer’s instruction execution cycle. Consider the following familiar code frag-
ment.
temp:= x;
x := y;
y := temp;
The epiphenomenal result is that x and y are exchanged. But this result is not a con-
sequence of any one statement. It is an epiphenomenon of the three statements being
executed in sequence by a computer’s instruction execution cycle.
Just as there in nothing in the rules of the Game of Life about gliders, there is nothing
in a computer’s instruction execution cycle about exchanging the values of x and y—or
about any other algorithm that software implements. Those effects are all epiphenomen-
al.
• The instruction execution cycle itself is epiphenomenal over the flow of electrons
through gates—which knows no more about the instruction execution cycle than the
instruction execution cycle knows about algorithms.
In all of the preceding examples it is relatively easy to identify the agent(s), the environ-
ment, and the resulting epiphenomena.
Our notion is closer to that of bricolage, a notion that originated with the structuralism
movement of the early 20th century [Wiener] and which is now used in both biology and
the social sciences. Bricolage means the act or result of tinkering, improvising, or build-
ing something out of what is at hand.
In genetics bricolage refers to the evolutionary process as one that tinkers with an exist-
ing genome to produce something new. [Church].
John Seely Brown, former chief scientist for the Xerox Corporation and former director
of the Xerox Palo Alto Research Center captured its sense in a recent talk.
[W]ith bricolage you appropriate something. That means you bring it
into your space, you tinker with it, and you repurpose it and reposi-
tion it. When you repurpose something, it is yours.12
Ciborra [Ciborra] uses bricolage to characterize the way that organizations tailor their in-
formation systems to their changing needs through continual tinkering.
This notion of building one thing upon another applies to our framework in that anything
that persists in an environment changes that environment for everything else. The Internet
provides many interesting illustrations.
• Because the Internet exists at all, access to a very large pool of people is available.
This enabled the development of websites such as eBay.
• The establishment of eBay as a persistent feature of the Internet environment enabled
the development of enterprises whose only sales outlet was eBay. These are enter-
prises with neither brick and mortar nor web storefronts. The only place they sell is
on eBay. This is a nice example of ecological succession.
• At the same time—and again because the Internet provides access to a very large
number of people—other organizations were able to establish what are known as
massively multi-player online games. Each of these games is a simulated world in
which participants interact with the game environment and with each other. In most of
these games, participants seek to acquire virtual game resources, such as magic
swords. Often it takes a fair amount of time, effort, and skill to acquire such re-
sources.
• The existence of all of these factors resulted, though a creative leap, in an eBay mar-
ket in which players sold virtual game assets for real money. This market has become
so large that there are now websites dedicated exclusively to trading in virtual game
assets. [Wallace]
• BBC News reported [BBC] that there are companies that hire low-wage Mexican and
Chinese teenagers to earn virtual assets, which are then sold in these markets. How
long will it be before a full-fledged economy develops around these assets? There
may be brokers and retailers who buy and sell these assets for their own accounts
12
In passing, Brown claims that this is how most new technology develops.
[T]hat is the way we build almost all technology today, even though my lawyers don't want
to hear about it. We borrow things; we tinker with them; we modify them; we join them; we
build stuff.
even though they do not intend to play the game. (Perhaps they already exist.)
Someone may develop a service that tracks the prices of these assets. Perhaps futures
and options markets will develop along with the inevitable investment advisors.
The point is that once something fits well enough into its environment to persist it adds it-
self to the environment for everything else. This creates additional possibilities and a
world with ever increasing complexity.
In each of the examples mentioned above, one can identify what we have been calling an
autonomous entity. In most cases, these entities are self-perpetuating in that the amount
of money they extract from the environment (by selling either products, services, or ad-
vertising) is more than enough to pay for the resources needed to keep it in existence.
In other cases, some Internet entities run on time and effort contributed by volunteers.
But the effect is the same. As long as an entity is self-perpetuating, it becomes part of the
environment and can serve as the basis for the development of additional entities.
To be clear about this point, when we say that the functionality of a designed element is
logically independent of some lower level domain we are not saying that the higher level
functionality is completely unconstrained by the lower level framework. Of course a Tur-
ing Machine emulation is constrained by the rules of the Game of Life, and the function-
ing of a mouse trap is constrained by the laws of physics. But in both cases, other than
those constraints, the functionality of the designed artifact is logically independent of the
laws governing the underlying phenomena. Typically, the functionality of the designed
artifact is expressed in terms that are not even a present in the ontological framework of
the lower level elements.
The question we pose in this subsection (and answer in the next) is whether such logic-
ally independent functionality occurs “in nature” at an intermediate level, at the level of
individual things. Or does this sort of phenomenon occur only in human (or chimpanzee)
artifacts?
Given the current debate (at least in the United States) about evolution, one might take
this as asking whether the existence of a design always implies the existence of a (pre-
sumably intelligent) designer.
The evocative term stovepipe is intended to distinguish the existing situation—in which
the DoD finds that it has acquired and deployed a large number of functionally isolated
systems (the “stovepipes”)—from the more desirable situation in which all DoD systems
are available to each other as an infrastructure of services.
On the other hand, perhaps our growing realization that catastrophic failures may occur
along with our ability to factor out commonly needed services will help us solve this
problem as well. We now see increasing number of disaster planning services being
offered.
7 Observations
Our fundamental existence depends on taking energy and other resources from the envir-
onment. We must all do it to stay in existence. Raises fundamental ethical questions: how
can taking be condemned? Supports stewardship notions since we are all dependent on
environment.
Dynamic entities are composed of static and dynamic entities (bodies and societies).
That’s what makes them solid. But those static entity components are frequently replaced.
Competition for energy and other resources justifies picture of evolution as survival of
the meanest. Also justifies group selection since groups can ensure access to resources
better than individuals.
8 Concluding remarks
For most of its history, science has pursued the goal of explaining existing phenomena in
terms of simpler phenomena. That’s the reductionist agenda.
The approach we have taken is to ask how new phenomena may be constructed from and
implemented in terms of existing phenomena. That’s the creative impulse of artists, com-
puter scientists, engineers—and of nature. It is these new phenomena that are often
thought of as emergent.
When thinking in the constructive direction, a question arises that is often under-appreci-
ated: what allows one to put existing things together to get something new—and
something new that will persist in the world? What binding forces and binding strategies
do we (and nature) have at our disposal?
Our answer has been that there are two sorts of binding strategies: energy wells and en-
ergy-consuming processes. Energy wells are reasonably well understood—although it is
astonishing how many different epiphenomena nature and technology have produced
through the use of energy wells.
We have not even begun to catalog the ways in which energy-consuming processes may
be used to construct stable, self-perpetuating, autonomous entities.
Earlier we wrote that science does not consider it within its realm to ask constructivist
questions. That is not completely true. Science asks about how we got here from the big
bang, and science asks about biological evolution. These are both constructivist ques-
tions. Since science is an attempt to understand nature, and since constructive processes
occur in nature, it is quite consistent with the overall goals of science to ask how these
constructive processes work. As far as we can determine, there is no sub-discipline of sci-
ence that asks, in general, how the new arises from the existing.
Science has produced some specialized answers to this question. The biological evolu-
tionary explanation involves random mutation and crossover of design records. The cos-
mological explanation involves falling into energy wells of various sorts. Is there any
more to say about how nature finds and then explores new possibilities? If as Dennett ar-
gues in [Dennett ‘96] this process may be fully explicated as generalized Darwinian evo-
lution, questions still remain. Is there any useful way to characterize the search space that
nature is exploring? What search strategies does nature use to explore that space? Clearly
one strategy is human inventiveness.
9 Acknowledgement
We are grateful for numerous enjoyable and insightful discussions with Debora Shuger
during which many of the ideas in this paper were developed and refined.
References
Abbott, R., “Emergence, Entities, Entropy, and Binding Forces,” The Agent 2004 Confer-
ence on: Social Dynamics: Interaction, Reflexivity, and Emergence, Argonne National
Labs and University of Chicago, October 2004. URL as of 4/2005: http://abbott.cal-
statela.edu/PapersAndTalks/abbott_agent_2004.pdf.
American Heritage, The American Heritage® Dictionary of the English Language, 2000.
URL as of 9/7/2005: http://www.bartleby.com/61/67/S0146700.html.
Anderson, P.W., “More is Different,” Science, 177 393-396, 1972.
BBC News, “Gamer buys $26,500 virtual land,” BBC News, Dec. 17, 2004. URL as of
2/2005: http://news.bbc.co.uk/1/hi/technology/4104731.stm.
Bedau, M.A., “Downward causation and the autonomy of weak emergence”. Principia 6
(2002): 5-50. URL as of 11/2004: http://www.reed.edu/~mab/papers/principia.pdf.
Boyd, Richard, "Scientific Realism", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer
2002 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL as of 9/01/2005:
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2002/entries/scientific-realism/.
Brown, J.S., Talk at San Diego State University, January 18, 2005. URL as of 6/2005:
http://ctl.sdsu.edu/pict/jsb_lecture18jan05.pdf
Carroll, S.B., Endless Forms Most Beautiful: The New Science of Evo Devo and the Mak-
ing of the Animal Kingdom, W. W. Norton, 2005.
Chaitin, G. Algorithmic Information Theory, reprinted 2003. URL as of Sept. 6, 2005:
http://www.cs.auckland.ac.nz/CDMTCS/chaitin/cup.pdf.
CFCS, Committee on the Fundamentals of Computer Science: Challenges and Opportun-
ities, National Research Council, Computer Science: Reflections on the Field, Reflections
from the Field, 2004. URL as of 9/9/2005:
http://www.nap.edu/books/0309093015/html/65.html.
Church, G. M., “From systems biology to synthetic biology,” Molecular Systems
Biology, March, 29, 2005. URL as of 6/2005:
http://www.nature.com/msb/journal/v1/n1/full/msb4100007.html.
Ciborra, C. "From Thinking to Tinkering: The Grassroots of Strategic Information
Systems", The Information Society 8, 297-309, 1992.
Clarke, A. C., "Hazards of Prophecy: The Failure of Imagination,” Profiles of The Future,
Bantam Books, 1961.
Cockshott, P. and G. Michaelson, “Are There New Models of Computation: Reply to
Wegner and Eberbach.” URL as of Oct. 10, 2005:
http://www.dcs.gla.ac.uk/~wpc/reports/wegner25aug.pdf.
Colbaugh, R. and Kristen Glass, “Low Cognition Agents: A Complex Networks Perspect-
ive,” 3rd Lake Arrowhead Conference on Human Complex Systems, 2005.
Collins, Steven, Martijn Wisse, and Andy Ruina, “A Three-Dimensional Passive-Dynam-
ic Walking Robot with Two Legs and Knees,” The International Journal of Robotics Re-
search Vol. 20, No. 7, July 2001, pp. 607-615, URL as of 2/2005: http://ruina.tam.cor-
nell.edu/research/topics/locomotion_and_robotics/papers/3d_passive_dynamic/3d_pass-
ive_dynamic.pdf
Comm Tech Lab and the Center for Microbial Ecology, The Microbe Zoo, URL as of Oct
10, 2005: http://commtechlab.msu.edu/sites/dlc-me/zoo/microbes/riftiasym.html
Comte, A. “Positive Philosophy,” translated by Harriet Martineau, NY: Calvin Blanchard,
1855. URL: as of 7/2005:
http://www.d.umn.edu/cla/faculty/jhamlin/2111/ComteSimon/Comtefpintro.html.
Cowan, R., “A spacecraft breaks open a comet's secrets,” Science News Online, Vol. 168,
No. 11 , p. 168, Sept. 10, 2005. URL as of 9/9/2005:
http://www.sciencenews.org/articles/20050910/bob9.asp.
Dennett, D. C., The Intentional Stance, MIT Press/Bradford Books, 1987.
Dennett, D. C. “Real Patterns,” The Journal of Philosophy, (88, 1), 1991.
Dennett, D. C., Darwin's Dangerous Idea: Evolution and the Meanings of Life, V, 1996.
Dick, D., et. al., “C2 Policy Evolution at the U.S. Department of Defense,” 10th Interna-
tional Command and Control Research and Technology Symposium, Office of the Assist-
ant Secretary of Defense, Networks and Information Integration (OASD-NII), June 2005.
URL as of 6/2005: http://www.dodccrp.org/events/2005/10th/CD/papers/177.pdf.
Einstein, A., Sidelights on Relativity, An address delivered at the University of Leyden,
May 5th, 1920. URL as of 6/2005:
http://www.gutenberg.org/catalog/world/readfile?fk_files=27030.
Emmeche, C, S. Køppe and F. Stjernfelt, “Levels, Emergence, and Three Versions of
Downward Causation,” in Andersen, P.B., Emmeche, C., N. O. Finnemann and P. V.
Christiansen, eds. (2000): Downward Causation. Minds, Bodies and Matter. Århus: Aar-
hus University Press. URL as of 11/2004:
http://www.nbi.dk/~emmeche/coPubl/2000d.le3DC.v4b.html.
Fodor, J. A., “Special Sciences (or the disunity of science as a working hypothesis),” Syn-
these 28: 97-115. 1974.
Fodor, J.A., “Special Sciences; Still Autonomous after All These Years,” Philosophical
Perspectives, 11, Mind, Causation, and World, pp 149-163, 1998.
Nave, C. R., “Nuclear Binding Energy”, Hyperphysics, Department of Physics and As-
tronomy, Georgia State University. URL as of 6/2005: http://hyperphysics.phy-as-
tr.gsu.edu/hbase/nucene/nucbin.html.
NOAA, Glossary of Terminology, URL as of 9/7/2005:
http://www8.nos.noaa.gov/coris_glossary/index.aspx?letter=s.
O'Connor, Timothy, Wong, Hong Yu "Emergent Properties", The Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy (Summer 2005 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), forthcoming URL:
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2005/entries/properties-emergent/.
Prigogine, Ilya and Dilip Kondepudi, Modern Thermodynamics: from Heat Engines to
Dissipative Structures, John Wiley & Sons, N.Y., 1997.
Ray, T. S. 1991. “An approach to the synthesis of life,” Artificial Life II, Santa Fe Insti-
tute Studies in the Sciences of Complexity, vol. XI, Eds. C. Langton, C. Taylor, J. D.
Farmer, & S. Rasmussen, Redwood City, CA: Addison-Wesley, 371--408. URL page for
Tierra as of 4/2005: http://www.his.atr.jp/~ray/tierra/.
Rendell, Paul, “Turing Universality in the Game of Life,” in Adamatzky, Andrew (ed.),
Collision-Based Computing, Springer, 2002. URL as of 4/2005: http://rendell.server.or-
g.uk/gol/tmdetails.htm, http://www.cs.ualberta.ca/~bulitko/F02/papers/rendell.d3.pdf, and
http://www.cs.ualberta.ca/~bulitko/F02/papers/tm_words.pdf
Rosen, Gideon, "Abstract Objects", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2001
Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL as of 9/1/05:
http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2001/entries/abstract-objects/.
Sachdev, S, “Quantum Phase Transitions,” in The New Physics, (ed G. Fraser), Cam-
bridge University Press, (to appear 2006). URL as of 9/11/2005: http://silver.physics.har-
vard.edu/newphysics_sachdev.pdf.
Shalizi, C., Causal Architecture, Complexity and Self-Organization in Time Series and
Cellular Automata, PhD. Dissertation, Physics Department, University of Wisconsin-
Madison, 2001. URL as of 6/2005: http://cscs.umich.edu/~crshalizi/thesis/single-spaced-
thesis.pdf
Shalizi, C., “Review of Emergence from Chaos to Order,” The Bactra Review, URL as of
6/2005: http://cscs.umich.edu/~crshalizi/reviews/holland-on-emergence/
Shalizi, C., “Emergent Properties,” Notebooks, URL as of 6/2005:
http://cscs.umich.edu/~crshalizi/notebooks/emergent-properties.html.
Smithsonian Museum, “Chimpanzee Tool Use,” URL as of 6/2005: http://national-
zoo.si.edu/Animals/ThinkTank/ToolUse/ChimpToolUse/default.cfm.
Summers, J. “Jason’s Life Page,” URL as of 6/2005: http://entropymine.com/jason/life/.
Trani, M. et. al., “Patterns and trends of early successional forest in the eastern United
States,” Wildlife Society Bulletin, 29(2), 413-424, 2001. URL as of 6/2005:
http://www.srs.fs.usda.gov/pubs/rpc/2002-01/rpc_02january_31.pdf.
University of Delaware, Graduate College of Marine Studies, Chemosynthesis, URL as of
Oct 10, 2005: http://www.ocean.udel.edu/deepsea/level-2/chemistry/chemo.html