60 Emory LJ251
60 Emory LJ251
60 Emory LJ251
Citations:
Please note: citations are provided as a general guideline. Users should consult their preferred
citation format's style manual for proper citation formatting.
-- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and
Conditions of the license agreement available at
https://heinonline.org/HOL/License
-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.
-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your license, please use:
Copyright Information
THE VULNERABLE SUBJECT AND THE RESPONSIVE STATE
Martha Albertson Fineman*
INTRODUCTION
Equal protection law under the United States Constitution requires that in
order to be treated equally, individuals must be treated the same. This
sameness-of-treatment version of equality ignores contexts, as well as
differences in circumstances and abilities on the part of those whose treatment
is compared. Most perplexing is the way in which the equal protection
doctrine ignores existing inequalities of circumstances and presumes an
equivalence of position and possibilities. Such a narrow approach to equality
cannot be employed to combat the growing inequality in wealth, position, and
power that we have experienced in the United States over the past few
decades.'
Profound inequalities are tolerated-even justified-by reference to
individual responsibility and the workings of an asserted meritocracy within a
free market. The state is not mandated to respond to those inequalities, nor
does it have to establish mechanisms to ensure more equitable distributions of
either social goods or responsibilities among individuals, groups, and
institutions.2 Quite the opposite: in the United States, the state is restrained
* Robert W. Woodruff Professor of Law, Emory University; Director of the Feminism and Legal Theory
Project. To access the webpage for the Vulnerability and the Human Condition Initiative at Emory University,
go to www.emory.edu/vulnerability.
1 The gap between the richest and poorest in the United States drastically increased from the late 1970s
until hitting a peak in 1993 and then decreased slightly. RICHARD WILKINSON & KATE PICKETT, THE SPIRIT
LEVEL 235 fig.16.2 (Bloomsbury Press 2010) (2009). Since 2000, however, the gap has seen a fairly
consistent increase. Id These levels are much higher than the country has seen for generations prior. Id. at
234. Currently, the incomes of the richest 20% are almost 9 times greater than the poorest individuals'
incomes. Id at 17 fig.2.1. From 1992 to 2007, the richest 10% of the population in the United States had
roughly 30% of the income. UNITED NATIONS DEV. PROGRAMME, HUMAN DEVELOPMENT REPORT 2009, at
195 tbl.m (2009).
2 In contrast, the United Kingdom recently passed the Equality Act, which requires public
decisionmakers to have "due regard" for the need to advance equality of opportunity. Sandra Fredman,
Positive Duties and Socio-Economic Disadvantage: Bringing Disadvantage onto the Equality Agenda, 2010
EUR. HUM. RTS. L. REV. 290, 295 (Eng.) (quoting Equality Act 2010, c. 15, § 149(1)).
252 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
See, e.g., Lyng v. Auto. Workers, 485 U.S. 360, 371 (1988) (holding that a law removing those
participating in labor strikes from the food stamp program did not violate the Equal Protection Clause of the
Fifth Amendment because it "is rationally related to the legitimate governmental objective of avoiding undue
favoritism to one side or the other in private labor disputes").
4 Passed in response to the Civil Rights Movement in the 1960s, the Fair Housing Act of 1968, Pub. L.
No. 90-284, tit. VIII, 82 Stat. 81 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 3601-3631 (2006)), which prohibited
discrimination in the sale or rental of housing, is an example of the United States recognizing a need to
interfere in the market and private contract making. See 42 U.S.C. § 3604 ("[I]t shall be unlawful--(a) To
refuse to sell or rent after the making of a bona fide offer, or to refuse to negotiate for the sale or rental of, or
otherwise make unavailable or deny, a dwelling to any person because of race, color, religion, sex, familial
status, or national origin.").
5 Originally, the Fair Housing Act prohibited only discrimination based on race, color, religion, and
national origin. Amendments added "sex" in 1974 and "familial status" in 1988. See Housing and
Community Development Act of 1974, Pub. L. No. 93-383, 88 Stat. 633, 728-29 (codified as amended at 42
U.S.C. §§ 3604-3606 (2006)); Fair Housing Amendments Act of 1988, Pub. L. No. 100-430, 102 Stat. 1619,
1620, 1622, 1623, 1635 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. §§ 3604-3606 (2006)).
6 See, e.g., San Antonio Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U.S. 1, 28-29 (1973) (finding that wealth
discrimination is not a basis for invoking strict scrutiny in an equal protection analysis because it does not have
the "traditional indicia of suspectness: the class is not saddled with such disabilities, or subjected to such a
history of purposeful unequal treatment, or relegated to such a position of political powerlessness as to
command extraordinary protection from the majoritarian political process"). In contrast, the Canadian Human
Rights Panel in 2000 recommended the inclusion of "social condition" as a ground of discrimination because
they recognized poverty as beyond the control of people for long periods of their lives and as associated with
"ongoing disadvantage." Fredman, supra note 2, at 294 (citing CANADIAN HUMAN RIGHTS ACT REVIEW
PANEL, PROMOTING EQUALITY: A NEW VISION 106-13 (2000), available at http:/dsp-
psd.pwgsc.gc.ca/Collection/J2-168-2000E.pdf).
See, e.g., Engquist v. Or. Dep't of Agric., 128 S. Ct. 2146, 2149 (2008) (holding that a public
employee could not bring "a claim under the Equal Protection Clause by alleging that she was arbitrarily
2010]1 THE VULNERABLE SUBJECT 253
This approach to inequality has set up a perverse dynamic that often results in
pitting one protected group against another, dividing those who may otherwise
be allies in a struggle for a more just society, as well as generating a politics of
resentment and backlash on the part of those who perceive they are not within
groups favored by this approach to equal protection.8 An additional perverse
consequence of the current grievance process arises from the required elements
of a legal claim for discrimination. In order to gain legal protection, claimants
must establish a history of proven discrimination against the group with which
they identify. Therefore, as a group-identity-based construct, inequality is only
confronted after it has accumulated a sufficiently lengthy history, and groups
are pressured to exclude or include people in order to protect a narrative of
long-standing discrimination. 9
This focus on individual and group characteristics and not on the
distribution of wealth, power, opportunity, or social goods has affected the
organization of interest groups in the United States, as well as the course of
legal protection. Legal and political battles revolve around the question of
whether a specific group seeking protection can be determined to constitute a
discrete and insular minority that has historically been discriminated against,
thus allowing an analogy to those groups currently protected based on
classifications such as race, gender, or ethnicity. This is what is now unfolding
with lesbians and gay men, who are fighting to enter existing societal
institutions, such as marriage or the military, using claims of impermissible
discrimination based on animus.10 Interest groups under existing equal
treated differently from other similarly situated employees, with no assertion that the different treatment was
based on the employee's membership in any particular class"). See Jonathan Fineman, The Inevitable Demise
of the Implied Employment Contract, 29 BERKELEY J. EMP. & LAB. L. 345 (2008), for a particularly succinct
explanation of this situation.
8 White citizens, for example, have raised claims of reverse discrimination, positing that equal
protection disadvantages them. See, e.g., Does Affirmative Action Punish Whites? Courts See a Growing
Number of Reverse Discrimination Cases, MSNBC.COM, Apr. 28, 2009, http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/
30462129.
9 See, e.g., Roy L. Brooks & Kirsten Widner, In Defense of the Black/White Binary: Reclaiming a
Tradition of Civil Rights Scholarship, 12 BERKELEY J. AFR.-AM. L. & POL'Y 107, 115 (2010) ("Critics argue
that, as a result of the Black/White paradigm, antidiscrimination laws and antidiscrimination efforts more
broadly do not always respond to racial harms Asian Americans, Latinas/os, and Native peoples experience."
(quoting Devon W. Carbado, Race to the Bottom, 49 UCLA L. REv. 1283, 1310 (2002)) (intemal quotation
mark omitted)).
1o See Witt v. Dep't of the Air Force, 527 F.3d 806, 823 (9th Cir. 2008) (Canby, J., concurring in part and
dissenting in part) ("[T]he right to engage in homosexual relationships and related private sexual conduct is a
personal right of a high constitutional order, and . .. the 'Don't Ask, Don't Tell' statute so penalizes that
relationship and conduct that it must be subjected to strict scrutiny."); Perry v. Schwarzenegger, 704 F. Supp.
2d 921, 997 (N.D. Cal. 2010) (finding that "evidence presented at trial shows that gays and lesbians are the
254 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
type of minority strict scrutiny was designed to protect" in response to plaintiffs argument that California's
Proposition 8 violated the Equal Protection Clause by discriminating based on sex and sexual orientation); cf
Don't Ask, Don't Tell Repeal Act of 2010, Pub. L. No. 111-321, 124 Stat. 3515.
11 In criticizing contemporary equality thinking in the United States, I am not suggesting that
discrimination based on race or gender is no longer a problem and should not be addressed by law. I focus on
the insufficiency of identity-focused equality to place in context my argument that we must not stop with the
incorporation of antidiscrimination measures, but move beyond them to a more robust ideal of equality.
Certainly one lamentable consequence of this equal protection doctrine is that it predominantly protects against
de jure discrimination (where laws facially disadvantage a protected class), rather than reaching situations of
de facto discrimination. Another objection is that entrenched and privileged interests are the ones that benefit
when political and legal organization around identity can effectively be manipulated to displace or eclipse
concern for the welfare of all members of American society. In fact, it seems that arguments about treatment
based on race or gender have become proxies in academic, political, and popular media discussions, displacing
exploration of inequalities that transcend those categories, such as poverty or lack of access to meaningful
work. They also reflect an underdeveloped sense of collective responsibility in a political system that fails to
ensure basic social goods that Europeans take for granted.
12 See, e.g., Plyler v. Doe, 457 U.S. 202, 221 (1982) (finding that education is not a fundamental right);
Alicia Ely Yamin, The Right to Health Under International Law and Its Relevance to the United States, 95
AM. J. PUB. HEALTH 1156, 1157 (2005) ("The United States is also the only industrialized country that does
not .. . [have] some kind of legal recognition of a right to care.").
13 See Organization of American States, American Convention on Human Rights, Nov. 22, 1969,
O.A.S.T.S. No. 36, 1144 U.N.T.S. 123 (signed but never ratified by the United States); International Covenant
on Civil and Political Rights, opened for signature Dec. 19, 1966, 6 I.L.M. 368, 999 U.N.T.S. 171 (entered
into force Mar. 23, 1976) (ratified by the United States but with five reservations, five understandings, and
four declarations that rendered it largely meaningless in the United States, including reserving the right to
subject children to the death penalty); International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights,
2010] THE VULNERABLE SUBJECT 255
opened for signature Dec. 19, 1966, 6 I.L.M. 360, 993 U.N.T.S. 3 (entered into force Jan. 3, 1976) (signed but
never ratified by the United States).
14 Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women, opened for signature
Mar. 1, 1980, 19 I.L.M. 33, 1249 U.N.T.S. 13 (signed but never ratified by the United States).
15 Convention on the Rights of the Child, opened for signature Nov. 20, 1989, 28 I.L.M. 1456, 1577
U.N.T.S. 13 (signed but never ratified by the United States).
16 See Roper v. Simmons, 543 U.S. 551, 624 (2005) (Scalia, J., dissenting, joined by Rehnquist, C.J. &
Thomas, J.) ("[T]he basic premise of the Court's argument-that American law should conform to the laws of
the rest of the world-ought to be rejected out of hand. In fact the Court itself does not believe it. In many
significant respects the laws of most other countries differ from our law-including not only such explicit
provisions of our Constitution as the right to jury trial and grand jury indictment, but even many interpretations
of the Constitution prescribed by this Court itself."); Lawrence v. Texas, 539 U.S. 558, 598 (2003) (Scalia, J.,
dissenting) ("The Court's discussion of these foreign views ... is therefore meaningless dicta. Dangerous
dicta, however, since 'this Court... should not impose foreign moods, fads, or fashions on Americans."'
(second alteration in original) (quoting Foster v. Florida, 537 U.S. 990, 990 n.* (2002) (Thomas, J., concurring
in denial of certiorari))); Thompson v. Oklahoma, 487 U.S. 815, 868 n.4 (1988) (Scalia, J., dissenting) ("The
plurality's reliance upon Amnesty International's account of what it pronounces to be civilized standards of
decency in other countries is totally inappropriate as a means of establishing the fundamental beliefs of this
Nation. That 40% of our States do not rule out capital punishment for 15-year-old felons is determinative of
the question before us here, even if that position contradicts the uniform view of the rest of the world. We
must never forget that it is a Constitution for the United States of America that we are expounding." (citation
omitted)).
256 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
I. EQUALITY OR AUTONOMY
20 Currently, the way we implement this state obligation is through an antidiscrimination paradigm. This
Essay's fundamental premise is that that approach is insufficient and actually has led to greater inequalities of
access and opportunity. Some more positive state action is required.
21 Despite the United States' provisions against discrimination, it ranks just below Singapore as one of
the most unequal countries out of the rich industrialized nations. WILKINSON & PICKETT, supra note 1, at 17
fig.2.1. Social mobility has also been limited. Data from the 1980s and 1990s show that about 36% of
children who were bom into the bottom fifth of wealth distribution will remain in that class as adults. Id. at
160. Studies of fathers' incomes when their sons were born and then their sons' incomes at age 30 show that
social mobility has declined rapidly since the 1980s. Id. at 159-61. The United Nations' Human Development
Report 2009 shows that the ratio of income or expenditure of the richest 10% to the poorest 10% in the United
States was 15.9 from 1992 to 2007, more than 6 points higher than the ratios in Canada, Ireland, Netherlands,
France, and Switzerland, and 9 points higher than Norway, Sweden, Finland, Austria, and Germany. UNITED
NATIONS DEV. PROGRAMME, supra note 1, at 195 tbl.m. It was also 2 points higher than the United Kingdom.
Id
22 See, e.g., Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-193, 110 Stat.
2105 (codified as amended in scattered sections of 8 and 42 U.S.C.) (effecting a major reform in welfare by
imposing work requirements on recipients and limiting the amount of time any person can receive assistance).
In signing the bill, President Clinton stated, "The new bill restores America's basic bargain of providing
opportunity and demanding, in return, responsibility," highlighting America's commitment to equal
opportunity that must be taken advantage of by individual autonomy while not addressing more systemic
inequalities. President Bill Clinton, Remarks on Signing the Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity
Reconciliation Act of 1996 and an Exchange with Reporters (Aug. 22, 1996), in 2 PUBLIC PAPERS OF THE
PRESIDENTS OF THE UNITED STATES: WILLIAM J. CLINTON 1996, at 1326 (1998).
23 In early American history, equality and liberty were consistently linked. Virginia's first state
constitution, one of the earliest state constitutions, began with the declaration, "[A]ll men are by nature equally
free and independent, and have certain inherent rights .... " VA. CONST. of 1776, § 1. Samuel Adams argued
that all colonists were entitled to "[j]ust and true liberty, equal and impartial liberty." Samuel Adams, The
Rights of the Colonists: Report of the Committee of Correspondence to the Boston Town Meeting, Nov. 20,
258 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
1772, reprinted in 7 OLD SOUTH LEAFLETS 417 (Edwin D. Mead et al. eds., 1917) (No. 173) (internal quotation
marks omitted). According to Gordon S. Wood, author of The Creationof the American Republic 1776-1787,
"No phrase except 'liberty' was invoked more often by the Revolutionaries than 'the public good."' WOOD,
supra note 18, at 55.
Wilkinson and Pickett, authors of The Spirit Level, argue that the American commitment to both
equality and liberty was shattered during the Cold War, when "the state-owned economics of Eastern Europe
and the Soviet Union seemed to show ... that greater equality could only be gained at the expense of
freedom." WILKINSON & PICKETT, supra note 1, at 256.
24 Early in American political history, dependency-one antonym for autonomy-was understood very
differently than it is today. The label of dependent was applied to a broad class of persons, forming the basis
for exclusion from political rights (voting), as well as providing justification for second-class citizenship more
generally. It is well known that dependency was used to define the position ofwomen and children, but it also
was the term applied to men who were mere wage earners and had no significant property or capital
accumulation. Dependency was the status of having to rely on others for your livelihood-working for wages.
On the evolving nature of the political meaning of dependency, see Nancy Fraser & Linda Gordon, A
Genealogy of Dependency: Tracing a Keyword of the US. Welfare State, 19 SIGNS: J. WOMEN CULTURE &
Soc'Y 309, 315-16 (1994) (describing how working-class men came to be considered independent). Of
course today we consider the wage earner, who has morphed into the "taxpayer," to be the exemplar of the
independent citizen. The point is that meanings behind potent political terms can change and such terms may
periodically need to be deconstructed and the assumptions behind them explored.
25 The new Tea Party movement, for example, has rallied around a position of limited government and
minimized government spending. In a May 2010 poll conducted by the University of Washington Institute for
the Study of Ethnicity, Race & Sexuality, 74% of the Tea Party "True Believers" (those who strongly agree
with the Tea Party) agreed with the following statement: "[W]hile equal opportunity for blacks and minorities
to succeed is important, it's not really the government's job to guarantee it." Matt Barreto & Christopher
Parker, May 2010 Washington Poll, WASH. POLL, http://www.washingtonpoll.org/results/Junel_teaparty.pdf
(last visited Dec. 21, 2010).
26 MARTHA ALBERTSON FINEMAN, THE AUTONOMY MYTH 10 (2004). The importance of the idea of
independence to the construction of an autonomous and equal individual may be traced to the fact that the very
existence of the United States begins with a document entitled "The Declaration of Independence." While it is
a declaration of freedom for a fledgling nation, it nonetheless sets forth as a "natural" principle that every
individual is endowed with inalienable rights, such as the right to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness.
THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 2 (U.S. 1776).
2010] THE VULNERABLE SUBJECT 259
27 It is only certain types of state support that are stigmatized. In fact, it is hard to think of any situation
where someone can act without having, or having had in the past, substantial support and subsidy from the
state and its institutions. See FINEMAN, supra note 26, at 49-54.
28 There is resistance on this basis to many social welfare programs, from public assistance or welfare, to
healthcare and affirmative action programs.
29 I think this explains why there has been so much discussion about who constitutes the "deserving" as
contrasted with the "undeserving" poor.
30 As noted above in this Part, state responsibility might extend to eliminating certain forms of
discrimination against certain classes of persons based on group characteristics. This elimination of
discrimination is seen as an impermissible distortion of the free market system and thus as justification for
state intervention and a permissible imposition on individual freedom to otherwise act without constraint.
Discrimination, if proven, can be addressed and remedied through the state processes, after which the system
can revert to its idealized free market, noninterventionist stance.
260 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
33 Studies examined in The Spirit Level suggest that higher inequality decreases levels of trust in a
society, and less trusting members of society are less willing to donate time and money to helping others.
wILKINSON & PICKETT, supra note 1, at 54-57. Levels of trust in the U.S. have dropped from 60% in the
1960s to 40% in 2004. Id. at 54. As an interesting anecdotal example, Josh Lauer suggests that the recent
obsession in the United States with sport utility vehicles demonstrates "an admiration for rugged individualism
and the importance of shutting oneself off from contact with others." Id. at 57-58 (citing Josh Lauer, Driven
to Extremes: Fear of Crime and the Rise of the Sport Utility Vehicle in the United States, 1 CRIME MEDIA
CULTURE 149 (2005)).
262 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
While I recognize the symbolic appeal of the claims for both autonomy and
equality and the desire to obscure any potential conflict, as well as the nature
of the relation between them, I argue that we must reverse the positioning of
equality as the dependant value in American politics, one that is shaped
through the dominant lens of autonomy. The perpetuation of such a hierarchy
has reduced the positive possibilities of a more substantive equality to a mere
individual entitlement to be treated the same as everyone else, regardless of
differences in material, social, historical, or other resources.
Unless confronted with the challenges presented by vulnerability and
dependency, equality is a rather hollow standard, safeguarding only the right to
strive for self-sufficiency and independence to abstract individuals shorn of
limiting human characteristics and potentially debilitating social and historical
inequities. Our subservient sense of equality cannot assess contexts and
conditions. Nor can it be used as a leveling notion, employed to even up the
playing field giving some more substantive content to the guarantees of access
and opportunity.
We should ask ourselves what distortions result from focusing societal
objectives through a lens of autonomy, as well as assess whose interests are
served by the current balance that privileges autonomy over a more substantive
equality frame.
34 See, e.g., Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Act of 1996, Pub. L. No. 104-193, sec. 103,
§ 407, 110 Stat. 2105, 2129 (codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. § 607 (2006)) (making welfare benefits
dependent upon mandatory work requirements); Michelle A. Travis, The PDA 's Causation Effect:
Observations of an Unreasonable Woman, 21 YALE J.L. & FEMINISM 51, 57-59 (2009) (discussing court
precedent prior to the Pregnancy Discrimination Act, Pub. L. No. 95-555, 92 Stat. 2076 (1978) (codified at 42
U.S.C. § 2000e(k) (2006)), that did not impose any responsibility on employers because the courts viewed
pregnancy as merely a choice made by the female volitional actor).
THE VULNERABLE SUBJECT 263
2010]
35
conceptualized as constituted through a social contract. Individual
transactions and interactions with the state and its institutions are posited to
involve autonomous and independent actors in processes of negotiation,
bargaining, and consent. Competence is assumed and differences in power,
circumstances, or actual ability are ignored. Thus constructed, this "liberal
36
subject" is at the heart of political and legal thought.
This Essay raises an important question: if our bodily fragility, material
needs, and the possibility of messy dependency they signify cannot be ignored
in life, how can they be absent in our theories about equality, society, politics,
and law? 3 7 Recognition of human dependency and vulnerability should
present the traditional political and legal theorist with a dilemma.
Unfortunately, dependency is not part of many approaches to theory in politics
or law. Instead, a structure and set of social orderings have been constructed in
which the family has been deemed the primary societal institution responsible
for dependency. The family is the mechanism by which we privatize, and
thus hide dependency and its implications. This allows simplistic assertions
39
3 The conception of government as a social contract was especially prevalent during the founding of the
United States. See WILLI PAUL ADAMS, THE FIRST AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONS 218-22 (Rita Kimber & Robert
Kimber trans., Univ. of N.C. Press 1980) (1973).
36 See FINEMAN, supra note 26, at 224-27, for a discussion of the misplaced reliance on the liberal
subject.
3 See Martha Albertson Fineman, The Vulnerable Subject: Anchoring Equality in the Human Condition,
20 YALE J.L. & FEMINISM 1, 12 (2008).
38 See generally MARTHA ALBERTSON FINEMAN, THE NEUTERED MOTHER, THE SEXUAL FAMILY, AND
the
OTHER TWENTIETH CENTURY TRAGEDIES (1995) (arguing that discussions of the family must include
concepts of dependency and caregiving).
3 See FINEMAN, supra note 26, at 57-59; Fineman, supra note 37, at I1.
40 Notions of what constitutes the "private," as contrasted with the "public," contribute to the vitality of
absent
this ideology by placing the family conceptually outside of state intervention or regulation
a
extraordinary abuses or major failings on the part of individual families. Of course, the "private" family is
myth comparable to that of individual autonomy. See generally FINEMAN, supra note 26 (postulating that the
idea of autonomy in American society is a constructed myth). The legal family is both constructed and
dissolved by law and legal processes. Through law, the state privileges certain social entities as family and
gives them both subsidies and protections not afforded to other entities. The family is also conceived as
having unique bonds of affiliation and responsibility to members that place intrafamily relationships on a
unique level, thus furthering the perception that it is a private space ideally free of state intervention.
264 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
41 Id
42 The reforms to Aid to Families with Dependent Children undertaken
in 1996 were less sympathetic to
children and more punitive toward their mostly single mothers. "Personal responsibility" rhetoric and a belief
in marriage and work were thought to be what was needed to end the "cycle of dependency" that made
subsequent generations welfare recipients. The reform was entitled the "Temporary Assistance for Needy
Families." See, e.g., Causes of Poverty, with a Focus on Out-of-Wedlock Births: Hearing Before the
Subcomm. on Human Res. of the H. Comm. on Ways & Means, 104th Cong. 16 (1996) (statement of Rep. Tim
Hutchinson) ("[I]nstead of lifting people out of poverty and despair we have developed a cycle of dependency
that is now entering its third generation. . . . [W]elfare reform legislation must also include strong work
requirements. We must restore to individuals the dignity of work.").
43 There are actually many different, though sometimes related, forms of dependency, such as economic,
psychological, or emotional dependency. I limit my discussion to inevitable and derivative dependency
inherent in the care work that takes place in the family and is essential to the reproduction of society and its
institutions. As I have argued elsewhere, it is family care labor that produces the workers, citizens, soldiers,
students, teachers, etc., that populate society. See FINEMAN, supra note 26, at 31-40, 47-49.
4 Martha Albertson Fineman, Evolving Images of Gender and Equality: A Feminist Journey, 43 NEW
ENG. L. REv. 437,447 (2009).
2010]1 THE VULNERABLE SUBJECT 265
45 Motherhood deepens the already-existing wage gap between men and women because women who are
mothers make less than women who are not. For example, a study of women who began working in the 1970s
showed a 3%penalty per child and 5/-7% penalty for two or more children, while another study of women
who began working in the 1980s showed a penalty of 7% per child. Sarah Avellar & Pamela J. Smock, Has
the Price ofMotherhood Declinedover Time? A Cross-CohortComparison of the Motherhood Wage Penalty,
65 J. MARRIAGE & FAM. 597, 598 (2003); see also Jane Waldfogel, The Effect of Children on Women's Wages,
62 AM. Soc. REv. 209, 216 (1997) (finding a 4% penalty for one child and a 12% penalty for two or more
children).
46 See FINEMAN, supra note 26, at 31-49.
47 See id.
48 This reaction reflects the traditional division between public and private that has allowed many
mainstream scholars to elude difficult and potentially disruptive issues in their theorizing. See, e.g., BARBARA
BENNETT WOODHOUSE, HIDDEN IN PLAIN SIGHT 7-11 (2008) (discussing the difficulties theorists and others
have in addressing children's rights and the tendency to view them as limited to the family arena); Martha
Albertson Fineman, Contract, Marriageand Background Rules, in ANALYZING LAW: NEW ESSAYS IN LEGAL
THEORY 183, 183-84 (Brian Bix ed., 1998) (discussing Professor Jules Coleman's failure to integrate the
family into his theories); Kerrie E. Maloney, Gender-Motivated Violence and the Commerce Clause: The Civil
Rights Provision of the Violence Against Women Act After Lopez, 96 COLUM. L. REv. 1876, 1898-99 (1996)
(explaining federal judges' reluctance to hear family issues as motivated by their belief that family matters are
"insignificant docket-clutter beneath the dignity of the federal judge" (quoting Ann Althouse, Federalism,
Untamed, 47 VAND. L. REv. 1207,1210 (1994)) (internal quotation mark omitted)).
266 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
49 See, e.g., Katherine M. Franke, Theorizing Yes: An Essay on Feminism, Law, and Desire, in FEMINIST
AND QUEER LEGAL THEORY 29, 31-35 (Martha Albertson Fineman et al. eds., 2009).
50 See, e.g., Ronald Dworkin, What Is Equality? Equality of Welfare (pt. 1), 10 PHIL. & PUB. AFF. 185
(1981) (differentiating inequality based on choices as permissible inequality).
51 Fineman, supra note 37, at 17-18 (explaining that such an approach allows us "to celebrate the
progress toward racial, ethnic, and gender equality that has been made under the anti-discrimination model"
while still questioning whether the system has given advantages to certain individuals). The structural focus of
the vulnerability analysis also brings institutions under scrutiny.
52 See, e.g., id at 8 nn.19-21; Who Are Vulnerable Populations?, CTR. FOR VULNERABLE POPULATIONS
RESEARCH, http://www.nursing.ucla.edu/orgs/cvpr/who-are-vulnerable.html (last visited Dec. 21, 2010) ("The
term 'vulnerable populations,' refers to social groups with increased relative risk (i.e. exposure to risk factors)
or susceptibility to health-related problems.... VPs are often discriminated against, marginalized and
disenfranchised from mainstream society. . . .").
53 The concept of vulnerability can act as a heuristic device, forcing us to examine hidden assumptions
and biases folded into legal, social, and cultural practices. See Fineman, supra note 37, at 8, 12 (describing
2010] THE VULNERABLE SUBJECT 267
this basic premise of a universal vulnerable subject forms the foundation for
the assertion that human vulnerability must be at the heart of our ideas of
social and state responsibility. 5 4 In addition to this concept of universal
vulnerability, several other theoretical characteristics further development of
the concept of vulnerability.
The second premise in defining vulnerability is that of constancy. Human
vulnerability arises from our embodiment, which carries with it the imminent
or ever-present possibility of harm, injury, and misfortune. Bodily harms can
take a variety of forms and range from those that are mildly annoying to those
that are catastrophically devastating and permanent in nature. Bodily harm can
55
result accidentally or be caused by intentional actions. Bodily harm can
result from the unleashing of forces of nature, from the mere passage of time,
or from the fact that we humans exist in a world full of often-unpredictable
material realities.56 While we can attempt to lessen risk or act to mitigate
possible manifestations of our vulnerability, the possibility of harm cannot be
eliminated.
It is also true that many harms are beyond individual or even human
control. The process of aging and death, for example, are clear, internal
biological processes that show the limitations of human ability to avoid the
ultimate consequences of our embodiment. There are also external threats to
our bodily well-being that are difficult to eliminate or even substantially
decrease. We may suffer or succumb to diseases that are random or the result
of pandemics or other biologically based catastrophes. In addition to viruses
and bacteria, our bodies are also vulnerable to environmental forces, such as
weather systems that produce floods or droughts accompanied by famine or
fire. These are "natural" disasters, certainly beyond our individual control to
prevent. More directly humanly manufactured disruptions in our environment,
such as pollution or chemical spills, may also cause us harm.
vulnerability as a "universal, inevitable" condition of humanity that recognizes that the human condition
includes a range of abilities over the span of a lifetime).
54 See generally FINEMAN, supra note 26.
55 It is important to recognize a range of vulnerabilities. Some manifestations of vulnerability are clearly
beyond individual or even societal control, while others can be cast as "self-induced." The liberal subject,
constructed in terms of individual autonomy, self-sufficiency, and personal responsibility, does not distinguish
among vulnerabilities, suggesting that individuals bear primary responsibility for their situation and
circumstances, regardless of their nature or cause.
56 See Fineman, supra note 37, at 9.
268 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
57 From 1993 to 1995, only 29.5% of low-income families exited low-income status each year. John
Schmitt & Ben Zipperer, Is the United States a Good Model for Reducing Social Exclusion in Europe?, 37
INT'L J. HEALTH SERVICES 15, 41 (2007). This was the lowest level of mobility among rich industrialized
nations, such as the United Kingdom and Canada. Id. at 41 tbl.1 1. In an intergenerational mobility analysis,
Canada, Finland, Germany, and Sweden had substantially greater economic mobility than the United States.
Id. at 42. These studies indicate that it would take, on average, more than three generations for descendants of
a poor family to close the income gap with an average family. Id. at 44. The United States does little to
ameliorate child poverty. It ranked 25th out of the 26 rich countries reporting data in the UNICEF child
poverty measures because other rich countries had reduced their child poverty rates by 101/5% through
social support systems, such as income supports, family allowances, and day care. Barbara Bennett
Woodhouse, Race, Culture, Class, and the Myth of Crisis: An Ecogenerist Perspective on Child Welfare, 81
ST. JOHN's L. REv. 519,521-22 (2007) (citing UNICEF INNOCENTI RESEARCH CTR., INNOCENTI REPORT CARD
6: CHILD POVERTY INRICH COUNTRIES 2005, at 4 fig. 1, 20 (2005)).
2010] THE VULNERABLE SUBJECT 269
58 In addition to specific programs that address bodily vulnerability, such as health care, programs that
create a more equal society help mitigate vulnerability at all levels of society. See WILKINSON & PICKETT,
supra note 1, at 81, 84 (suggesting that more equal societies have lower levels of health problems, including
heart disease and mental illnesses, at all levels of society, not just among the impoverished).
5 Fineman, supra note 37, at 12-13.
60 id.
270 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
66 Social support and networks have been linked with rates of cardiovascular disease and with recovery
from heart attacks. WILKINSON & PICKETT, supra note 1, at 76. One experiment showed that people with
friends were less likely to catch cold. Id.
67 See, e.g., David Pace, More Blacks Live with Pollution, ASSOCIATED PRESS, Dec. 13, 2005, available
at http://hosted.ap.org/specials/interactives/archive/pollution/partl.html ("Air pollution 'works with many
other factors, genetics and environment, to heighten one's risk of developing asthma and chronic lung
disease ... . Evidence suggests that not only do people get hospitalized but they die at higher rates in areas
with significant air pollution."' (quoting Dr. John Brofman, Director of Respiratory Intensive Care at MacNeal
Hospital)).
68 The Environmental Protection Agency (EPA), for example, was created in 1970 to monitor the
environment by writing and enforcing regulations. Reorganization Plan No. 3 of 1970, 3 C.F.R. § 199 (1970)
(reprinted as amended in 42 U.S.C. § 4321 (2006)).
69 Existential may be defined as: "[I]n the context of existentialism, involved in or vital to the shaping of
an individual's self-chosen mode of existence and moral stance with respect to the rest of the world...
MICROSOFr ENCARTA COLLEGE DICTIONARY 501 (Kathy Rooney et al. eds., 2001).
272 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
are labeled "private," but governments also subsidize religious and cultural
entities through tax policy and more direct means. 70
There is a link between these various types of resources and state
responsibility. Many of the institutions providing resources that give us
resilience can only be brought into legal existence through state mechanisms.71
Entities such as corporations, schools, workplaces, families, or churches are
legitimated and given a status that confers on them benefits and protections by
law. 72 Their very content and meaning is defined through state processes. The
dissolution of many of these entities is also accomplished only through state
processes. To the extent that these legally constituted institutions distribute
significant social goods, they should be monitored by the state. State
involvement in the creation and maintenance of these institutions requires that
the state be vigilant in ensuring that the distribution of such assets is
accomplished with attention to public values, including equality or justice, or
objectives beyond private or profit motivation. Instead, what we find in the
United States is that within these various asset-conferring systems individuals
are often positioned differently from one another. Specifically, some are
privileged by the structure and operation of these institutions, while others are
relatively disadvantaged and left to cope with their shared vulnerability on an
individual level.73 The responsibility to overcome existing systemic
inequalities is an individual, not a state responsibility.
70 See, e.g., 26 U.S.C. §501(c)(3) (2006) (granting churches and other religious organizations
tax-exempt
status).
71 Robert Dahl, a Yale professor, observed that "without the protection of a dense network of laws
enforced by public governments, the largest American corporation could not exist for a day." GAR
ALPEROVITZ & LEW DALY, UNJUST DESERTS 138 (2008) (quoting ROBERT DAHL, DILEMMAS OF PLURALIST
DEMOCRACY 183-85 (1982)). Dahl also noted that the view of economic institutions as "private" is an "ill fit"
for their "social and public" nature. Id. at 139 (quoting DAHL, supra).
72 Legal documents such as charters, documents of incorporation, licenses, or permits come to mind.
73 Studies in the 1990s and 2000 showed that blacks and poor people were far more likely to live near
hazardous waste disposal sites or other major pollution sources, such as power plants and industrial parks.
Pace, supra note 67. A study based on 2000 Census data showed that in nineteen states blacks were more than
twice as likely to live in areas where air pollution posed the greatest health danger. Id. The Bush
Administration, however, adhering to a very formal sense of equality, stated that the EPA's mission was not to
alleviate pollution among specific racial and income groups but rather "to get at those folks to make sure that
they are going to be breathing clean air, and that's regardless of their race, creed or color." Id. (quoting
Marcus Peacock, then-Deputy EPA Administrator) (intemal quotation mark omitted). In 2003, the EPA's
Inspector General reported that the agency had not integrated environmental equality concerns into its daily
operations, and in 2005 the U.S. General Accountability Office reported that the EPA had not considered
equality in developing rules for the Clean Air Act between 2000 and 2004. Id.; see also Marlen E. Koro et al.,
Microbial Quality of Food Available to Populations ofDiffering Socioeconomic Status, 38 AM. J. PREVENTIVE
MED. 478, 478 (2010) ("Public health research focusing on diet quality has demonstrated that low-SES
2010] THE VULNERABLE SUBJECT 273
It must be made clear that the choice is not one between an active state on
one hand versus an inactive state on the other. Rather, the choice is whether or
not the state is going to act to fulfill a well-defined responsibility to implement
populations have less access to high-quality (i.e., nutritious) produce, lean meat, and low-fat dairy products."
(citations omitted)).
74 See, e.g., David 1.Walker, Commentary, The Social Insurance Crisis and the Problem of Collective
Saving: A Commentary on Shaviro's Reckless Disregard, 45 B.C. L. REV. 1347, 1348-49 (2004) (discussing
the unsustainable nature of social security as a result of increased longevity, escalating healthcare costs, and
the impending retirement of the baby boomers); Nick Timiraos & James R. Hagerty, No Exit in Sight for U.S.
as Fannie, Freddie Flail, WALL ST. J., Feb. 9, 2010, at Al (explaining that Freddie Mac and Fannie Mae
suffered great losses as a result of the housing bust beginning in 2006 and continue to struggle).
75 See, e.g., David Cho, Banks 'Too Big to Fail' Have Grown Even Bigger; Behemoths Born of the
Bailout Reduce Consumer Choice, Tempt Corporate Moral Hazard, WASH. POST, Aug. 28, 2009, at A01
(discussing the tens of billions of dollars put into big banks by the federal government when the credit crisis
put them in danger).
274 EMORY LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 60
a comprehensive and just equality regime that ensures access and opportunity
for all consistent with a realistic conception of the human subject. Our present
insistence that the state need be constrained underestimates or even ignores the
many ways in which the state-through law-shapes institutions from their
inception to their dissolution, and the ways in which those institutions produce
and replicate inequalities. We must show how these institutions operate to
produce systems of privilege. To this end, it is imperative to recognize that no
one is an autonomous, independent individual.
We all benefit from society and its institutions, but some are relatively
advantaged and privileged in their relationships, while others are
disadvantaged. Under a vulnerability analysis, the inquiry would be into the
organization, operation, and outcomes of the institutions and structures through
which societal resources are channeled. The state is constituted for the general
and "common benefit," not for a select few. 76 Under a vulnerability analysis,
the state has an obligation not to tolerate a system that unduly privileges any
group of citizens over others. It has a responsibility to structure conditions in
which individuals can aspire to meaningfully realize their individual
capabilities as fully as possible.
While several prevailing American myths currently impede the
establishment of a state more responsive to the vulnerable subject, the
challenge is to think beyond current ideological constraints and consider the
possibility of an active state in nonauthoritarian terms. This theoretical task of
reconceptualizing the role of the state requires that we imagine responsive
structures whereby state involvement actually empowers a vulnerable subject
by addressing existing inequalities of circumstances that result from undue
privilege or institutional advantage. State mechanisms that ensure a more
equitable access to institutional assets by adjusting unjust distribution of
privilege and opportunity across society would also contribute to a more robust
democracy and greater public participation.77
76 The United States was formed on the idea that government was created for the common benefit and the
promise that all individuals had a right to receive benefits from it. Many of the constitutions created at the
time of the revolution explicitly mention "common benefit" or "common good" as the goal of government.
The constitutions of Pennsylvania, Vermont, and Virginia, for example, state: "[G]overnment is, or ought to
be, instituted for the common benefit, protection, and security of the people, nation or community." PA.
CONST. of 1776, art. V; VT. CONST. of 1777, ch. 1, art. VI; VA. CONST. of 1776, § 3.
7 A focus on the state and its institutions, as well as privilege and disadvantage, would certainly change
the nature of the legal inquiry in the United States. It would move courts beyond only assessing whether
individuals or groups with designated characteristics have been subjected to animus and discrimination. The
vulnerability paradigm calls on courts to be also receptive to claims that look beyond identity, and to assess the
2010] THE VULNERABLE SUBJECT 275
distribution of assets and the possibilities of resilience that suggest structural disadvantage and/or privilege.
Under a vulnerability approach, the task is not to explore the intent behind the actions of individual employees,
educators, landlords, and so on. Individual intention is not the issue, nor is discrimination. Because the
shared, universal nature of vulnerability draws the whole of society-not just a defined minority-under
scrutiny, the vulnerability approach might be deemed a "post-identity" analysis of what sorts of protection
society owes its members. By recognizing that privilege and disadvantage migrate across identity categories,
we are forced to focus not only on individuals, but also on institutions-the structures and arrangements that
can almost invisibly produce or exacerbate existing inequality.