Our Knowledge of The External World As A Field For Scientific Method in Philosophy
Our Knowledge of The External World As A Field For Scientific Method in Philosophy
Our Knowledge of The External World As A Field For Scientific Method in Philosophy
By
Bertrand Russell
1
PREFACE
analysis can claim to reach, but unfortunately these results have always
systems of the past serve a very useful purpose, and are abundantly
problem of the relation between the crude data of sense and the space,
2
time, and matter of mathematical physics. I have been made aware of the
to whom are due almost all the differences between the views advocated
instants and "things," and the whole conception of the world of physics
topics here is, in fact, a rough preliminary account of the more precise
their problem.
[3] The first volume was published at Cambridge in 1910, the second in
been removed by the work of Georg Cantor. But the positive and detailed
upon sensible objects as data has only been rendered possible by the
3
growth of mathematical logic, without which it is practically impossible
Wittgenstein.
claimed for the theories suggested; but I believe that where they are
the same method as that which at present makes them appear probable, and
incompleteness.
Cambridge,
June 1914.
4
CONTENTS
LECTURE
I. Current Tendencies
5
LECTURE I
CURRENT TENDENCIES
Philosophy, from the earliest times, has made greater claims, and
achieved fewer results, than any other branch of learning. Ever since
Thales said that all is water, philosophers have been ready with glib
assertions about the sum-total of things; and equally glib denials have
Anaximander. I believe that the time has now arrived when this
philosophers have been excessive, and why their achievements have not
been greater. The problems and the method of philosophy have, I believe,
insoluble with our means of knowledge, while other more neglected but
not less important problems can, by a more patient and more adequate
method, be solved with all the precision and certainty to which the most
but in essence and tendency distinct. The first of these, which I shall
call the classical tradition, descends in the main from Kant and Hegel;
6
it represents the attempt to adapt to present needs the methods and
from Darwin, and must be reckoned as having had Herbert Spencer for its
chiefly through William James and M. Bergson, far bolder and far more
Spencer. The third type, which may be called "logical atomism" for want
adherents, but the "new realism" which owes its inception to Harvard is
new philosophy, we must briefly examine and criticise the other two
7
losing ground, many of the most prominent teachers still adhere to it.
failed to adapt itself to the temper of the age. Its advocates are, in
than those who have felt the inspiration of science. There are, apart
it--the same general forces which are breaking down the other great
syntheses of the past, and making our age one of bewildered groping
certainty.
The original impulse out of which the classical tradition developed was
would prove, for instance, that all reality is one, that there is no
vital impulse of the early philosophers died away, its place was taken
8
our own day, by systematic theology. Modern philosophy, from Descartes
onwards, though not bound by authority like that of the Middle Ages,
two parts, the first called Appearance, the second Reality. The
first part examines and condemns almost all that makes up our everyday
causation, activity, the self. All these, though in some sense facts
which qualify reality, are not real as they appear. What is real is one
some sense spiritual, but does not consist of souls, or of thought and
9
kind of Absolute which is finally affirmed to be real.
other--right and left, before and after, father and son, and so on. But
there are relations, there must be qualities between which they hold.
This part of his argument need not detain us. He then proceeds:
"But how the relation can stand to the qualities is, on the other side,
relation hardly can be the mere adjective of one or both of its terms;
again we are hurried off into the eddy of a hopeless process, since we
are forced to go on finding new relations without end. The links are
united by a link, and this bond of union is a link which also has two
ends; and these require each a fresh link to connect them with the old.
The problem is to find how the relation can stand to its qualities, and
10
[4] Appearance and Reality, pp. 32-33.
the things in the world. To the early Greeks, to whom geometry was
with assent even when it led to the strangest conclusions. But to us,
discover the exact nature of the error when it exists. But there is no
doubt that what we may call the empirical outlook has become part of
most educated people's habit of mind; and it is this, rather than any
generally.
11
constructive through negation. Where a number of alternatives seem, at
them except one, and that one is then pronounced to be realised in the
world may be, it refuses to legislate as to what the world is. This
even for those whose faith in logic is greatest; while to the many who
rise do not seem worthy even of refutation. Thus on all sides these
systems have ceased to attract, and even the philosophical world tends
art. By this it means, roughly speaking, that all the different parts
fit together and co-operate, and are what they are because of their
12
is true, every part of the universe is a microcosm, a miniature
object that there are people--say in China--with whom our relations are
them from any fact about ourselves. If there are living beings in Mars
or in more distant parts of the universe, the same argument becomes even
stronger. But further, perhaps the whole contents of the space and time
in which we live form only one of many universes, each seeming to itself
complete. And thus the conception of the necessary unity of all that is
Another very important doctrine held by most, though not all, of the
dependent for its existence upon what is mental. This view is often
particularised into the form which states that the relation of knower
and known is fundamental, and that nothing can exist unless it either
fallacious, and a better logic will show that no limits can be set to
the extent and nature of the unknown. And when I speak of the unknown, I
do not mean merely what we personally do not know, but what is not known
13
to any mind. Here as elsewhere, while the older logic shut out
familiar, the newer logic shows rather what may happen, and refuses to
very diverse parents: the Greek belief in reason, and the mediæval
belief in the tidiness of the universe. To the schoolmen, who lived amid
safety and order. In their idealising dreams, it was safety and order
and neat as a Dutch interior. To us, to whom safety has become monotony,
very different from what it was amid the wars of Guelf and Ghibelline.
Hence William James's protest against what he calls the "block universe"
it is this, rather than formal argument, that has thrust aside the
B. Evolutionism
14
Evolutionism, in one form or another, is the prevailing creed of our
time. It dominates our politics, our literature, and not least our
seem useless to raise a protest; and with much of its spirit every
must be combined with the new spirit before it can emerge from the
that biology is neither the only science, nor yet the model to which all
something more arduous and more aloof, appealing to less mundane hopes,
15
kinds, which had rendered classification easy and definite, which was
necessity for orthodox dogma, was suddenly swept away for ever out of
the biological world. The difference between man and the lower animals,
be placed either within or without the human family. The sun and planets
landmarks became wavering and indistinct, and all sharp outlines were
blurred. Things and species lost their boundaries, and none could say
But if human conceit was staggered for a moment by its kinship with the
ape, it soon found a way to reassert itself, and that way is the
the amoeba would agree with this opinion is not known. Hence the cycle
in the actual. But such a view, though it might satisfy Spencer and
the world continuously approaches is, to these minds, too dead and
static to be inspiring. Not only the aspirations, but the ideal too,
16
must change and develop with the course of evolution; there must be no
Ever since the seventeenth century, those whom William James described
the mechanical view of the course of nature which physical science seems
was due to the partial escape from mechanism which it provided. But now,
physics, but the whole apparently immutable apparatus of logic, with its
fixed concepts, its general principles, and its reasonings which seem
able to compel even the most unwilling assent. The older kind of
proceeds:[5]
"But radical finalism is quite as unacceptable, and for the same reason.
for example, implies that things and beings merely realise a programme
17
understood is only inverted mechanism. It springs from the same
postulate, with this sole difference, that in the movement of our finite
of the future for the impulsion of the past. But succession remains none
dust, by straying from the path foreseen by mechanics, should show the
pure mechanism. The theory we shall put forward in this book will
18
in his philosophy, is a continuous stream, in which all divisions are
artificial and unreal. Separate things, beginnings and endings, are mere
beliefs of to-day may count as true to-day, if they carry us along the
stream; but to-morrow they will be false, and must be replaced by new
will be better than the past or the present: the reader is like the
child who expects a sweet because it has been told to open its mouth and
because they are too "static"; what is real is an impulse and movement
towards a goal which, like the rainbow, recedes as we advance, and makes
distance.
it--first, that its truth does not follow from what science has rendered
the problems with which it deals are so special, that it can hardly be
19
(1) What biology has rendered probable is that the diverse species arose
if the changes on the earth's surface during the last few millions of
law of the universe. Except under the influence of desire, no one would
of facts. What does result, not specially from biology, but from all the
sciences which deal with what exists, is that we cannot understand the
world unless we can understand change and continuity. This is even more
20
thus consists of two parts: one not philosophical, but only a hasty
morality and happiness than in knowledge for its own sake. It must be
admitted that the same may be said of many other philosophies, and that
a desire for the kind of knowledge which philosophy really can give is
enlarged with the progress of science. But what is evident is that any
it must have a province of its own, and aim at results which the other
21
The consideration that philosophy, if there is such a study, must
one which has very far-reaching consequences. All the questions which
mundane desires. What it can do, when it is purified from all practical
to any except those who have the wish to understand, to escape from
satisfaction which the other sciences offer. But it does not offer, or
22
therefore, of its appeal to detailed results in various sciences, it
try to show first by examples of certain achieved results, and then more
space and time and matter, which, as we have seen, are challenged by the
must take more account of change and the universal flux than is done in
lines, nor do I think that his rejection of logic can be anything but
owing to the fact that no two philosophers ever understand one another,
the first, has been developed by the union or the conflict of these two
attitudes. Among the earliest Greek philosophers, the Ionians were more
scientific and the Sicilians more mystical.[6] But among the latter,
23
Pythagoras, for example, was in himself a curious mixture of the two
wicked to eat beans. Naturally enough, his followers divided into two
but the former sect died out, leaving, however, a haunting flavour of
the two, and secures ultimate victory whenever the conflict is sharp.
Plato, moreover, adopted from the Eleatics the device of using logic to
defeat common sense, and thus to leave the field clear for mysticism--a
device still employed in our own day by the adherents of the classical
tradition.
evidence. In all who seek passionately for the fugitive and difficult
24
goods, the conviction is almost irresistible that there is in the world
moments, therefore, is to them the way of wisdom, rather than, like the
accept without question the equal reality of the trivial and the
important.
no wish to deny it, nor even to declare that the insight which reveals
spite of the fact that much of the most important truth is first
instinct and reason; in the eighteenth century, the opposition was drawn
romantic movement instinct was given the preference, first by those who
which they associated with a spiritual outlook on life and the world.
25
position of sole arbiter of metaphysical truth. But in fact the
rather than a creative one. Even in the most purely logical realms, it
error on the one side and on the other. In this there is no opposition
26
to instinct as a whole, but only to blind reliance upon some one
implies that we move round the object; the second that we enter into it.
The first depends on the point of view at which we are placed and on the
point of view nor relies on any symbol. The first kind of knowledge may
27
This procedure, since it takes sides in a conflict of instinctive
interprets it.
know of the struggle for survival and of the biological ancestry of man:
it is not only intellect, but all our faculties, that have been
for existence than, for example, capacity for pure mathematics. Yet the
with his life; whereas even in the most civilised societies men are not
28
put to death for mathematical incompetence. All the most striking of his
fact is, of course, that both intuition and intellect have been
developed because they are useful, and that, speaking broadly, they are
useful when they give truth and become harmful when they give falsehood.
wild in the woods, dyeing themselves with woad and living on hips and
haws.
as Bergson claims for it. The best instance of it, according to him, is
and difficult. Most men, for example, have in their nature meannesses,
vanities, and envies of which they are quite unconscious, though even
their best friends can perceive them without any difficulty. It is true
29
notable examples of intuition is the knowledge people believe themselves
to possess of those with whom they are in love: the wall between
they see into another soul as into their own. Yet deception in such
supposed insight was illusory, and that the slower, more groping methods
Bergson maintains that intellect can only deal with things in so far as
they resemble what has been experienced in the past, while intuition has
the power of apprehending the uniqueness and novelty that always belong
to each fresh moment. That there is something unique and new at every
can give knowledge of what is unique and new. But direct acquaintance of
this kind is given fully in sensation, and does not require, so far as I
neither intellect nor intuition, but sensation, that supplies new data;
but when the data are new in any remarkable manner, intellect is much
more capable of dealing with them than intuition would be. The hen with
inside them, and not merely to know them analytically; but when the
illusory, and the hen is left helpless on the shore. Intuition, in fact,
30
admirable in those customary surroundings which have moulded the habits
of action.
love, intuition will act sometimes (though not always) with a swiftness
philosophy is not one of the pursuits which illustrate our affinity with
for its success, a certain liberation from the life of instinct, and
even, at times, a certain aloofness from all mundane hopes and fears. It
its best. On the contrary, since the true objects of philosophy, and the
and remote, it is here, more almost than anywhere else, that intellect
31
Before embarking upon the somewhat difficult and abstract discussions
which lie before us, it will be well to take a survey of the hopes we
may retain and the hopes we must abandon. The hope of satisfaction to
our more human desires--the hope of demonstrating that the world has
philosophy; but the difference between love and hate is not a difference
some kind of ethical interest may inspire the whole study, but none must
sought.
that a similar change has been found necessary in all the other
32
pre-scientific ages this was not the case. Astronomy, for example, was
movements of the planets had the most direct and important bearing upon
the lives of human beings. Presumably, when this belief decayed and the
part of its purpose to show that the earth is worthy of admiration. The
even more recent and more difficult than in the physical sciences: it is
success.
hardly ever achieved. Men have remembered their wishes, and have judged
sciences, the belief that the notions of good and evil must afford a key
33
even from this last refuge, if philosophy is not to remain a set of
that happiness is not best achieved by those who seek it directly; and
it would seem that the same is true of the good. In thought, at any
rate, those who forget good and evil and seek only to know the facts are
more likely to achieve good than those who view the world through the
The immense extension of our knowledge of facts in recent times has had,
outlook. On the one hand, it has made men distrustful of the truth of
wide, ambitious systems: theories come and go swiftly, each serving, for
a moment, to classify known facts and promote the search for new ones,
but each in turn proving inadequate to deal with the new facts when they
have been found. Even those who invent the theories do not, in science,
have attained, recedes further and further beyond the limits of what
seems worth while except the discovery of more and more facts, each in
On the other hand, the new facts have brought new powers; man's physical
34
assignable limits. Thus alongside of despair as regards ultimate theory
seems almost boundless. The old fixed limits of human power, such as
are forgotten, and no hard facts are allowed to break in upon the dream
capacity of gratifying his wishes; and thus the very despair of theory
the Greek feeling for beauty in the abstract world of logic and for the
scientific spirit, must deal with somewhat dry and abstract matters, and
35
must not hope to find an answer to the practical problems of life. To
those who wish to understand much of what has in the past been most
and as important in the long run, for the moulding of our mental habits.
always does--a sense of power and a hope of progress more reliable and
other hopes, more purely intellectual, it can satisfy more fully than
36
LECTURE II
The topics we discussed in our first lecture, and the topics we shall
using the word, logical. But as the word "logic" is never used in the
Logic, in the Middle Ages, and down to the present day in teaching,
humbler men merely to repeat the lesson after him. The trivial nonsense
those habits of solemn humbug which are so great a help in later life.
But it is not this that I mean to praise in saying that all philosophy
abandoned the mediæval tradition, and in one way or other have widened
37
the scope of logic.
modern physics and astronomy. This is probably the only extension of the
old logic which has become familiar to the general educated public. But
investigation, does not seem to remain when its work is done: in the
question as, "Will the sun rise to-morrow?" Our first instinctive
feeling is that we have abundant reason for saying that it will, because
that it does. The question which then arises is: What is the principle
38
answer given by Mill is that the inference depends upon the law of
causation. Let us suppose this to be true; then what is the reason for
instances in which it has been found to hold. The theory that causation
very unplausible by the mere process of formulating the law exactly, and
from what has been observed to what has not been observed, which can
only be done by means of some known relation of the observed and the
this subject.
39
fallible process called "induction by simple enumeration." This process,
unscientific method becomes less and less liable to mislead; and the
most universal class of truths, the law of causation for instance, and
proved by that method alone, nor are they susceptible of any other
proof."[9]
In the above statement, there are two obvious lacunæ: (1) How is the
principle, if any, covers the same ground as this method, without being
40
Thus, if simple enumeration is to be rendered valid, it must not be
stated as Mill states it. We shall have to say, at most, that the data
the instances are very numerous, then, we shall say, it becomes very
This is not refuted by the fact that what we declare to be probable does
not always happen, for an event may be probable on the data and yet not
more exact statement. We shall have to say something like this: that
But this brings us to our other question, namely, how is our principle
41
data, it cannot be proved by them alone; since it is required to justify
all inferences from empirical data to what goes beyond them, it cannot
experience. I do not say that any such principle is known: I only say
empirically.[11]
Lecture VIII.
Hegel and his followers widened the scope of logic in quite a different
42
characteristics would be impossible and self-contradictory. Thus what he
far as this can be inferred merely from the principle that the universe
the existing universe. But, however that may be, I should not regard
The way in which, as it seems to me, Hegel's system assumes the ordinary
43
whole; and this theory is derived from Hegel. Now the traditional logic
this it easily follows that there can be only one subject, the Absolute,
for if there were two, the proposition that there were two would not
appear at first sight such as to establish its truth. This is the most
they are different, he does not infer, as others would, that there is
44
says, since Socrates is mortal, it follows that the particular is the
This is an example of how, for want of care at the start, vast and
confusions, which, but for the almost incredible fact that they are
which Leibniz cherished throughout his life, and pursued with all the
subject has been published recently, since his discoveries have been
remade by others; but none was published by him, because his results
the syllogism. We now know that on these points the traditional doctrine
45
[13] Cf. Couturat, La Logique de Leibniz, pp. 361, 386.
Thought (1854). But in him and his successors, before Peano and Frege,
the only thing really achieved, apart from certain details, was the
premisses which the newer methods shared with those of Aristotle. This
mathematics, but it has very little to do with real logic. The first
serious advance in real logic since the time of the Greeks was made
logic regarded the two propositions, "Socrates is mortal" and "All men
are mortal," as being of the same form;[14] Peano and Frege showed that
world of sense to the world of Platonic ideas. Peano and Frege, who
pointed out the error, did so for technical reasons, and applied their
[14] It was often recognised that there was some difference between
46
them, but it was not recognised that the difference is fundamental,
constructed. Not only Frege's theory of number, which we shall deal with
in Lecture VII., but the whole theory of physical concepts which will be
could hardly have been proved or practically used without its help. The
principle will be explained in our fourth lecture, but its use may be
47
briefly indicated in advance. When a group of objects have that kind of
will serve all the purposes of the supposed common quality, and that
which need not be assumed to exist. In this and other ways, the indirect
uses of even the later parts of mathematical logic are very great; but
propositions I enunciate, but they have diverse forms. If, on the other
hand, I take any one of these propositions and replace its constituents,
this series, but all the constituents are altered. Thus form is not
48
another constituent, but is the way the constituents are put together.
logic.
the hemlock" is not an existing thing like Socrates or the hemlock, nor
does it even have that close relation to existing things that drinking
the form. We may also have knowledge of the form without having
those among you who have never heard of Rorarius (supposing there are
any) will understand the form, without having knowledge of all the
known form. Thus some kind of knowledge of logical forms, though with
pure.
49
In all inference, form alone is essential: the particular subject-matter
reason for the great importance of logical form. When I say, "Socrates
was a man, all men are mortal, therefore Socrates was mortal," the
connection of premisses and conclusion does not in any way depend upon
its being Socrates and man and mortality that I am mentioning. The
general form of the inference may be expressed in some such words as,
"If a thing has a certain property, and whatever has this property has a
certain other property, then the thing in question also has that other
truth of the premisses, that is because the premisses have not been all
sciences to discover when the hypotheses are verified and when they are
not.
But the forms of propositions giving rise to inferences are not the
50
proposition not stating a relation between two or more other
thing--we may say "this thing is round, and red, and so on." Grammar
it is not even very common. If we say "this thing is bigger than that,"
and "that." We might express the same fact by saying "that thing is
perceive this difference or to allow for it has been the source of many
giving any account of the world of science and daily life. If they had
been honestly anxious to give such an account, they would probably have
discovered their error very quickly; but most of them were less anxious
basis, but are none the less powerfully persuasive. The conviction born
51
When the emotional intensity of such a mood subsides, a man who is in
the habit of reasoning will search for logical reasons in favour of the
belief which he finds in himself. But since the belief already exists,
mysticism, and are the goal which he feels his logic must reach if it is
Plato, Spinoza, and Hegel. But since they usually took for granted the
world of science and common sense. It is only so that we can account for
of their doctrines with all the common and scientific facts which seem
need of logic is not felt; as the mood fades, the impulse to logic
52
daily world to which it is to be applied. Such an attitude naturally
does not tend to the best results. Everyone knows that to read an author
simply in order to refute him is not the way to understand him; and to
metaphysicians.
related terms. There are many ways of refuting this opinion; one of the
Some relations, when they hold between A and B, also hold between B and
53
All relations that are not symmetrical are called non-symmetrical.
above, to the right of, etc. All the relations that give rise to
and B and also between B and C, it holds between A and C. Thus before,
series are transitive, but so are many others. The transitive relations
54
A relation is said to be intransitive when, if A has the relation to
as before and after, greater and less, etc., the attempt to reduce them
greater, we may say that the inequality results from their having
to say that when one thing is greater than another, and not merely
formally incapable of explaining the facts. For if the other thing had
been greater than the one, the magnitudes would also have been
different, though the fact to be explained would not have been the same.
55
since, if it were, there would be no difference between one thing being
greater than another, and the other being greater than the one. We shall
have to say that the one magnitude is greater than the other, and thus
greater and less, whole and part, and many others of the most important
his insight, we must continue to study the everyday world with which we
are familiar. But when he contends that our world is impossible, then
our logic is ready to repel his attack. And the first step in creating
56
reality of relations.
Relations which have two terms are only one kind of relations. A
relation may have three terms, or four, or any number. Relations of two
terms, being the simplest, have received more attention than the others,
and have generally been alone considered by philosophers, both those who
accepted and those who denied the reality of relations. But other
wife: "My dear, I wish you could induce Angelina to accept Edwin," his
rare. But in order to explain exactly how they differ from relations of
facts, which is the first business of logic, and the business in which
The existing world consists of many things with many qualities and
not only a catalogue of the things, but also a mention of all their
qualities and relations. We should have to know not only this, that, and
the other thing, but also which was red, which yellow, which was earlier
57
than which, which was between which two others, and so on. When I speak
of a "fact," I do not mean one of the simple things in the world; I mean
that a certain thing has a certain quality, or that certain things have
a thing, it has only two constituents, the thing and the quality. When
facts, in the sense in which we are using the word "fact," are not other
facts, but are things and qualities or relations. When we say that there
are relations of more than two terms, we mean that there are single
facts consisting of a single relation and more than two things. I do not
mean that one relation of two terms may hold between A and B, and also
between A and C, as, for example, a man is the son of his father and
also the son of his mother. This constitutes two distinct facts: if we
choose to treat it as one fact, it is a fact which has facts for its
people; there are not two instances of jealousy, but only one. It is in
such cases that I speak of a relation of three terms, where the simplest
possible fact in which the relation occurs is one involving three things
58
terms or five or any other number. All such relations must be admitted
in our inventory of the logical forms of facts: two facts involving the
same number of things have the same form, and two which involve
Given any fact, there is an assertion which expresses the fact. The fact
but the assertion is something which involves thought, and may be either
that Charles I. was executed, or that he did not die in his bed. A
bed," we may either assert or deny this form of words: in the one case
propositions, although, like facts, they may have any one of an infinite
number of forms, are only one kind of propositions. All other kinds are
regards facts and propositions, we shall give the name "atomic facts" to
59
the facts we have hitherto been considering. Thus atomic facts are what
Perhaps one atomic fact may sometimes be capable of being inferred from
another, though this seems very doubtful; but in any case it cannot be
known without inference. The atomic facts which we come to know in this
know in this way. If we knew all atomic facts, and also knew that there
infer all truths of whatever form.[16] Thus logic would then supply us
with the whole of the apparatus required. But in the first acquisition
without asking ourselves what objects can fill the forms. Thus pure
sense, independent of logic. Pure logic and atomic facts are the two
poles, the wholly a priori and the wholly empirical. But between the
two lies a vast intermediate region, which we must now briefly explore.
60
propositions as components. Such facts, though not strictly atomic,
either of the two separately. It does not require for its truth that it
brought my umbrella if the weather had been different. Thus we have here
they are to be asserted or denied, but only upon the second being
umbrella, and if you see that there is a steady downpour, you can infer
61
that I shall bring my umbrella. There can be no inference except where
propositions are connected in some such way, so that from the truth or
the other. It seems to be the case that we can sometimes know molecular
know whether the component atomic propositions are true or false. The
are equiangular." And with these belong propositions in which the word
are not wise." These are the denials of general propositions, namely (in
text-books. But their peculiarity and complexity are not known to the
text-books, and the problems which they raise are only discussed in the
facts and also knew that there were no other atomic facts besides those
we knew. The knowledge that there are no other atomic facts is positive
62
general knowledge; it is the knowledge that "all atomic facts are known
from atomic facts alone. If we could know each individual man, and know
that he was mortal, that would not enable us to know that all men are
mortal, unless we knew that those were all the men there are, which is
the universe, and knew that each separate thing was not an immortal man,
that would not give us our result unless we knew that we had explored
the whole universe, i.e. unless we knew "all things belong to this
independent of empirical evidence, i.e. does not depend upon the data
of sense.
older empiricists. They believed that all our knowledge is derived from
the senses and dependent upon them. We see that, if this view is to be
63
case, but it does not appear to be so in fact, and indeed no one would
derived from sense, and that some of this knowledge is not obtained by
such knowledge not derived from logic, I do not know; but in logic, at
from pure logic such propositions as, "Socrates is a man, all men are
has a certain property, and whatever has this property has a certain
other property, then the thing in question has the other property." This
were in search.
A proposition such as, "If Socrates is a man, and all men are mortal,
truth, in this hypothetical form, does not depend upon whether Socrates
actually is a man, nor upon whether in fact all men are mortal; thus it
is equally true when we substitute other terms for Socrates and man
64
formal, and belongs to logic. Since it does not mention any particular
Logic, we may say, consists of two parts. The first part investigates
what propositions are and what forms they may have; this part enumerates
general formal truths. The first part, which merely enumerates forms, is
the recent progress in this first part, more than anything else, that
problems possible.
of serial order, and therefore made space and time unintelligible. But
in this case it was only necessary to admit relations of two terms. The
65
judgments were true, we might suppose that a judgment consisted in
mind to the fact. From poverty in the logical inventory, this view has
the case of error. Suppose I believe that Charles I. died in his bed.
can have a relation of apprehension. Charles I. and death and his bed
are objective, but they are not, except in my thought, put together as
belief, to look for some other logical form than a two-term relation.
making the problem of error insoluble and the difference between belief
Modern logic, as I hope is now evident, has the effect of enlarging our
admissible, others, which only logic would have suggested, are added to
66
fetters, while the new logic gives it wings. It has, in my opinion,
beyond human powers. And where a solution appears possible, the new
67
LECTURE III
Philosophy may be approached by many roads, but one of the oldest and
most travelled is the road which leads through doubt as to the reality
problems.
68
questioned as to what he means by "reality," and may be asked how their
The logic of the idealist tradition has gradually grown very complex and
should not have time to reach any other aspect of our subject; we will
modern answers to them will occupy our fifth, sixth, and seventh
lectures.
probable that the immediate objects of sense depend for their existence
coloured surfaces which we see cease to exist when we shut our eyes. But
it would be a mistake to infer that they are dependent upon mind, not
real while we see them, or not the sole basis for our knowledge of the
69
external world. This line of argument will be developed in the present
lecture.
The discrepancy between the world of physics and the world of sense,
apparent than real, and it will be shown that whatever there is reason
science from the logic of the text-books and also from the logic of
idealism. Our second lecture has given a short account of modern logic
logic.
of the external world. What I have to say on this problem does not
of the directions in which evidence may be sought. But although not yet
70
completely new light on the problem, and to be indispensable, not only
certainly true. In the case of our present problem, the common knowledge
for a moment the hypothesis that the whole edifice may be built on
71
outset--that it is the duty of the philosopher to call in question the
to criticise the whole of the knowledge of daily life. The most that can
applying them with more care and with more precision. Philosophy cannot
details, not upon some external criterion which can be applied to all
the details equally. The reason for this abstention from a universal
our beliefs, and cannot be used to substitute other beliefs for them.
72
Although data can only be criticised by other data, not by an outside
does not go beyond our own personal sensible acquaintance must be for us
the most certain: the "evidence of the senses" is proverbially the least
and geography which are learnt from books, has varying degrees of
of our data; they, along with the other data, lie within the vague,
philosopher to analyse.
The first thing that appears when we begin to analyse our common
else from which it has been inferred in some sense, though not
73
necessarily in a strict logical sense, while other parts are believed on
obvious that the senses give knowledge of the latter kind: the immediate
made us aware that what is actually given in sense is much less than
most people would naturally suppose, and that much of what at first
the "real" size and shape of a visible object from its apparent size and
shape, according to its distance and our point of view. When we hear a
person speaking, our actual sensations usually miss a great deal of what
stage at a theatre than would be necessary in our own country. Thus the
outcome does not make any very great difference in our main problem.
The next step in our analysis must be the consideration of how the
74
simply what the belief asserts. Derivative beliefs in this sense
judge as to his state of mind by any logical process: the judgment grows
up, often without our being able to say what physical mark of emotion we
not the result of any logical deduction. There may or may not be a
When we reflect upon the beliefs which are logically but not
example, that tables and chairs, trees and mountains, are still there
when we turn our backs upon them. I do not wish for a moment to maintain
that this is certainly not the case, but I do maintain that the question
75
ground of obviousness. The belief that they persist is, in all men
having seen those tables and chairs, trees and mountains. As soon as the
a right to suppose that they are there still, we feel that some kind of
can be no more than a pious opinion. We do not feel this as regards the
We are thus led to a somewhat vague distinction between what we may call
"hard" data and "soft" data. This distinction is a matter of degree, and
must not be pressed; but if not taken too seriously it may help to make
the situation clear. I mean by "hard" data those which resist the
which, under the operation of this process, become to our minds more or
less doubtful. The hardest of hard data are of two sorts: the particular
facts of sense, and the general truths of logic. The more we reflect
upon these, the more we realise exactly what they are, and exactly what
verbal doubt may occur when what is nominally being doubted is not
really in our thoughts, and only words are actually present to our
76
minds. Real doubt, in these two cases, would, I think, be pathological.
At any rate, to me they seem quite certain, and I shall assume that you
our bow to the sceptical hypothesis, and, while admitting the elegant
sense or the laws of logic. The kind of respect which they deserve seems
the hard data may prove them to be at least probable. Also, if the hard
data are found to throw no light whatever upon their truth or falsehood,
the present, however, let us confine ourselves to the hard data, with a
alone.
77
Our data now are primarily the facts of sense (i.e. of our own
sense-data) and the laws of logic. But even the severest scrutiny will
sense. And facts of sense themselves must, for our present purposes, be
wholly within the specious present. And some facts of comparison, such
be included among hard data. Also we must remember that the distinction
are other minds than our own--which at our present stage must be held
doubtful--the catalogue of hard data may be different for them from what
it is for us.
Certain common beliefs are undoubtedly excluded from hard data. Such is
doubt as to whether other people have minds at all. Thus the world from
78
which our reconstruction is to begin is very fragmentary. The best we
can say for it is that it is slightly more extensive than the world at
which have obscured the meaning of the problem. The problem really is:
Can the existence of anything other than our own hard data be inferred
from the existence of those data? But before considering this problem,
surfaces which make up the visible world, are spatially external in the
It seems probable that distances, provided they are not too great, are
actually given more or less roughly in sight; but whether this is the
spatial, and is further not wholly contained within our own bodies. Thus
79
Another form in which the question is often put is: "Can we know of the
difficult one. Among many other things which we may mean by the Self,
two may be selected as specially important, namely, (1) the bare subject
which thinks and is aware of objects, (2) the whole assemblage of things
that would necessarily cease to exist if our lives came to an end. The
the data; therefore this meaning of Self may be ignored in our present
hardly know what things depend upon our lives for their existence. And
in this form, the definition of Self introduces the word "depend," which
raises the same questions as are raised by the word "independent." Let
later.
either that it is logically possible for the one to exist without the
other, or that there is no causal relation between the two such that the
one only occurs as the effect of the other. The only way, so far as I
when the other is part of the one. The existence of a book, for
pages there would be no book. Thus in this sense the question, "Can we
80
know of the existence of any reality which is independent of ourselves?"
which our Self is not part?" In this form, the question brings us back
to the problem of defining the Self; but I think, however the Self may
feelings are causally dependent upon ourselves, i.e. do not occur when
there is no Self for them to belong to. But in the case of objects of
the case, then they are causally independent of ourselves; if not, not.
Thus in this form the question reduces to the question whether we can
know that objects of sense, or any other objects not our own thoughts
and feelings, exist at times when we are not perceiving them. This form,
Our question in the above form raises two distinct problems, which it is
81
very similar objects, exist at times when we are not perceiving them?
exist either when we are perceiving the objects of sense or at any other
mental event consisting in our being aware of a sensible object, and (2)
many people at once, and is more or less permanent. What I mean is just
table, or just that particular hardness which is felt when we press it,
or just that particular sound which is heard when we rap it. Each of
argument, would only tend to show that the sensation has an outside
cause; this cause we should naturally seek in the sensible object. Thus
must have outside causes. But both the thing-in-itself of philosophy and
82
sensible object as much as of the sensation. What are the grounds for
In each case, I think, the opinion has resulted from the combination of
consciousness makes itself known in sensation, with the fact that our
sensations often change in ways which seem to depend upon us rather than
and that, if we shut our eyes, the objects we had been seeing remain as
they were though we no longer see them. But there are arguments against
we are to make any progress with the problem of the external world, we
A table viewed from one place presents a different appearance from that
sense, but this language already assumes that there is a real table of
which we see the appearances. Let us try to state what is known in terms
connected with all the appearances. What we ought to say is that, while
we have those muscular and other sensations which make us say we are
83
walking, our visual sensations change in a continuous way, so that, for
what we really know by experience, when we have freed our minds from the
But walking round the table is not the only way of altering its
visual appearance which we call that of the table. More distant objects
will also alter their appearance if (as we say) the state of the
although we can see things through it. But in this case we really see a
spotted patchwork: the dirtier specks in the glass are visible, while
the cleaner parts are invisible and allow us to see what is beyond. Thus
84
the discovery that the intervening medium affects the appearances of
Let us take the case of the blue spectacles, which is the simplest, but
may serve as a type for the others. The frame of the spectacles is of
course visible, but the blue glass, if it is clean, is not visible. The
seen through the glass. The glass itself is known by means of the sense
through it, we must know how to correlate the space of touch with the
to the statement that the blue glass, which we can touch, is between us
actually given in sense. We have fallen into the assumption that the
object of which we are conscious when we touch the blue spectacles still
them, nothing except our finger can be seen through the part touched,
than the spectacles, when seen through them, it might seem as if we must
assume that the spectacles still exist when we are not touching them;
85
and if this assumption really is necessary, our main problem is
not given in sense, though of the same kind as objects formerly given in
sense.
We may say that the object of which we become aware when we touch the
fallacious inference from the fact that they still have effects. It is
often supposed that nothing which has ceased to exist can continue to
It may be said that our hypothesis is useless in the case when the blue
glass is never touched at all. How, in that case, are we to account for
the blue appearance of objects? And more generally, what are we to make
would reveal?
86
Let us consider the more general question first. Experience has taught
tactile shape, and so on. This leads us to believe that what is seen is
But the mere fact that we are able to infer what our tactile sensations
qualities before they are felt. All that is really known is that the
We can now give a statement of the experienced facts concerning the blue
the blue spectacles, we find that whatever object is visible beyond the
empty sight-place in the same line of sight has a different colour from
87
touch-place; and as we move the tangible object in touch-space, the blue
taken as the whole of our meaning when we say that the blue spectacles
are in a certain place, though we have not touched them, and have only
we look at the moon, and find the earth's shadow biting into it, that is
to say, we see an appearance quite different from that of the usual full
was asserted must have been about sense-data; or, at any rate, if part
of what was asserted was not about sense-data, then only the other part
to law about the occurrence of sense-data, but the sense-data that occur
at one time are often causally connected with those that occur at quite
other times, and not, or at least not very closely, with those that
88
between my two sense-data; but if I look at the moon on two nights a
week apart, there is a very close causal connection between the two
which only those are actual which belong to moments when I choose to
assume that that thought, or one very like it, has been in another mind,
and has given rise to the expression which we hear. If at the same time
we see a body resembling our own, moving its lips as we move ours when
we speak, we cannot resist the belief that it is alive, and that the
feelings inside it continue when we are not looking at it. When we see
our friend drop a weight upon his toe, and hear him say--what we should
philosophy as not to be quite certain that his friend has felt the same
of this belief presently; for the moment, I only wish to point out that
it needs the same kind of justification as our belief that the moon
exists when we do not see it, and that, without it, testimony heard or
89
read is reduced to noises and shapes, and cannot be regarded as evidence
will not carry us very far towards the establishment of a whole science.
has gone. The problem is: "Can the existence of anything other than our
own hard data be inferred from these data?" It is a mistake to state the
than ourselves and our states?" or: "Can we know of the existence of
only prove that sensations are caused by sensible objects. The natural
dispelled by the fact that what common sense regards as the appearance
of one object changes with what common sense regards as changes in the
point of view and in the intervening medium, including in the latter our
own sense-organs and nerves and brain. This fact, as just stated,
bearing on our problem, we must find a way of stating it which does not
90
changes in certain sense-data are correlated with gradual changes in
certain others, or (in the case of bodily motions) with the other
sense-data themselves.
The assumption that sensible objects persist after they have ceased to
objects persist, i.e. that what happens now can only be accounted for,
Everything that one man, by his own personal experience, can verify in
the account of the world given by common sense and physics, will be
depends upon the existence of minds other than our own, and thus
and our sense-organs, causes our sensations, but is never itself given
in sensation.
91
appearances of what is supposed to be one object. It is supposed that
the table (for example) causes our sense-data of sight and touch, but
must, since these are altered by the point of view and the intervening
different from the seeing of it: the seeing of it is mental, but the
it, I think, lies in its failure to realise the radical nature of the
spectacles and the walk round the table has, I hope, made this clear.
But what remains far from clear is the nature of the reconstruction
required.
Although we cannot rest content with the above theory, in the terms in
respect, for it is in outline the theory upon which physical science and
92
The first thing to realise is that there are no such things as
are the most indubitably real objects known to us. What, then, makes us
but I wake up and find myself in England without those intervening days
visit to America. Objects of sense are called "real" when they have the
kind of connection with other objects of sense which experience has led
give rise; in themselves, they are every bit as real as the objects of
waking life. And conversely, the sensible objects of waking life must
not be expected to have any more intrinsic reality than those of dreams.
or that its various aspects can all "really" exist in the same place. If
93
something more real than objects of sense. If we see two tables, then
there are two visual tables. It is perfectly true that, at the same
moment, we may discover by touch that there is only one tactile table.
This makes us declare the two visual tables an illusion, because usually
one visual object corresponds to one tactile object. But all that we are
touch and sight is unusual. Again, when the aspect of the table changes
as we walk round it, and we are told there cannot be so many different
aspects in the same place, the answer is simple: what does the critic of
the table mean by "the same place"? The use of such a phrase presupposes
that all our difficulties have been solved; as yet, we have no right to
the same as it was. Thus the difficulty, if it exists, has at least not
Let us imagine that each mind looks out upon the world, as in Leibniz's
monadology, from a point of view peculiar to itself; and for the sake of
94
simplicity let us confine ourselves to the sense of sight, ignoring
minds which are devoid of this sense. Each mind sees at each moment an
nothing which is seen by two minds simultaneously. When we say that two
people see the same thing, we always find that, owing to difference of
worlds are perceived by them; if a third man enters and sits between
sense-organs, nerves, and brain of the newly arrived man; but we can
reasonably suppose that some aspect of the universe existed from that
point of view, though no one was perceiving it. The system consisting of
all views of the universe perceived and unperceived, I shall call the
95
"private world" is a perceived "perspective"; but there may be any
similar that they can use the same words to describe them. They say they
see the same table, because the differences between the two tables they
another. In case the similarity is very great, we say the points of view
of the two perspectives are near together in space; but this space in
which they are near together is totally different from the spaces inside
at least unperceived, and such that between any two, however similar,
there are others still more similar. In this way the space which
many objects in the one can be correlated with objects in the other,
form the system of all the objects correlated with it in all the
96
perspectives; that system may be identified with the momentary
we may ignore these at present.) All the aspects of a thing are real,
visible to more than one person, in the only sense in which it can ever
be visible, namely, in the sense that each sees one of its aspects.
It will be observed that, while each perspective contains its own space,
there is only one space in which the perspectives themselves are the
there are therefore at least as many as there are percipients, and there
may be any number of others which have a merely material existence and
are not seen by anyone. But there is only one perspective-space, whose
elements are single perspectives, each with its own private space. We
(perspectives), or, since "points of view" have not been defined, we may
spaces will each count as one point, or at any rate as one element, in
97
Suppose, for example, that we start from one which contains the
purpose we only have to move (as we say) towards the penny or away from
it. The perspectives in which the penny looks circular will be said to
that any other "thing" than our penny might have been chosen to define
experience shows that the same spatial order of perspectives would have
resulted.
perspective space) where a thing is." For this purpose, let us again
in which the penny is seen end-on and looks like a straight line of a
98
perspective space, i.e. in a certain perspective, which may be defined
as "the place (in perspective space) where the penny is." It is true
that, in order to prolong our lines until they reach this place, we
shall have to make use of other things besides the penny, because, so
far as experience goes, the penny ceases to present any appearance after
we have come so near to it that it touches the eye. But this raises no
defining the order. We can, for example, remove our penny and prolong
pennies further off in such a way that the aspects of the one are
circular where those of our original penny were circular, and the
aspects of the other are straight where those of our original penny were
straight. There will then be just one perspective in which one of the
new pennies looks circular and the other straight. This will be, by
definition, the place where the original penny was in perspective space.
The above is, of course, only a first rough sketch of the way in which
it assumes that we can remove the penny without being disturbed by any
that such niceties cannot affect the principle, and can only introduce
Having now defined the perspective which is the place where a given
99
perspectives in which a thing looks large are nearer to the thing than
We can now also explain the correlation between a private space and
certain private space, then we correlate the place where this aspect is
in the private space with the place where the thing is in perspective
space.
occupied by our private world. Thus we can now understand what is meant
understand what is meant by saying that our private world is inside our
head; for our private world is a place in perspective space, and may be
associated with every aspect of a thing: namely, the place where the
thing is, and the place which is the perspective of which the aspect in
thing, of which at most one appears in any given perspective; (2) the
the thing has the given aspect. The physicist naturally classifies
100
aspects in the first way, the psychologist in the second. The two places
and that from which, the aspect appears. The "place at which" is the
place of the thing to which the aspect belongs; the "place from which"
Let us now endeavour to state the fact that the aspect which a thing
spreading outwards from the place where the thing is, and undergoing
various changes as they get further away from this place. The laws
of the aspects that are near the thing, but require that we should also
take account of the things that are at the places from which these
which contains and places the experienced facts, including those derived
from testimony. The world we have constructed can, with a certain amount
any good reason to suppose that it is real? This brings us back to our
101
original problem, as to the grounds for believing in the existence of
truth of this belief, but we have not derived any positive grounds in
its favour. We will resume this inquiry by taking up again the question
the acquaintances of our waking hours. And yet, when we are awake, we do
not believe that the phantasm was, like the appearances of people in
imagination brings forth all that other people seem to say to us, all
that we read in books, all the daily, weekly, monthly, and quarterly
journals that distract our thoughts, all the advertisements of soap and
shown to be false, yet no one can really believe it. Is there any
102
The minds of other people are among our data, in the very wide sense in
which we used the word at first. That is to say, when we first begin to
people's bodies; and along with other such beliefs, it does not belong
The obvious argument is, of course, derived from analogy. Other people's
connected with thoughts and feelings like our own. Someone says, "Look
seen the motor-car first, in which case there are existing things of
which we are not directly conscious. But this whole scene, with our
argument from analogy more cogent when we are (as we think) awake?
the ground of its greater extent and consistency. If a man were to dream
every night about a set of people whom he never met by day, who had
103
consistent characters and grew older with the lapse of years, he might,
like the man in Calderon's play, find it difficult to decide which was
the dream-world and which was the so-called "real" world. It is only the
failure of our dreams to form a consistent whole either with each other
or with waking life that makes us condemn them. Certain uniformities are
observed in waking life, while dreams seem quite erratic. The natural
hypothesis would be that demons and the spirits of the dead visit us
this view, though it is hard to see what could be said against it. On
from a sleep which has filled all his mundane life: the whole world of
world utterly different from that of our daily cares and troubles. Who
shall condemn him? Who shall justify him? Or who shall justify the
to live?
The hypothesis that other people have minds must, I think, be allowed to
body of facts and never leads to any consequences which there is reason
104
assumed in our hypothetical construction. In actual fact, whatever we
knowledge, beyond our own private data, which we find in science and
common sense.
with objective reality has commonly been dealt with from a standpoint
which did not carry initial doubt so far as we have carried it; most
that others have minds. Their difficulties have arisen after this
object presents to two people at the same time, or to one person at two
difficulties have made people doubtful how far objective reality could
be known by sense at all, and have made them suppose that there were
account of the world given by common sense and physical science can be
place for all the data, both hard and soft. It is this hypothetical
105
is the chief outcome of our discussion. Probably the construction is
but I do not yet know to what lengths this diminution in our initial
106
LECTURE IV
science, for the most part, are willing to condemn immediate data as
gulf between the world of physics and the world of sense, and it is this
it, have not the mathematical knowledge required for spanning it. The
problem is difficult, and I do not know its solution in detail. All that
I can hope to do is to make the problem felt, and to indicate the kind
will take first the world of physics, for, though the other world is
107
given while the physical world is inferred, to us now the world of
physics is the more familiar, the world of pure sense having become
and chairs, stones, mountains, the earth and moon and sun. This
sensation, and it may be doubted whether they are there when they are
not seen or felt. This problem, which has been acute since the time of
extension, and was probably made by our savage ancestors in some very
But tables and chairs, stones and mountains, are not quite permanent
or quite rigid. Tables and chairs lose their legs, stones are split by
frost, and mountains are cleft by earthquakes and eruptions. Then there
are other things, which seem material, and yet present almost no
things--so, in a lesser degree, are ice and snow; and rivers and seas,
though fairly permanent, are not in any degree rigid. Breath, smoke,
clouds, and generally things that can be seen but not touched, were
thought to be hardly real; to this day the usual mark of a ghost is that
it can be seen but not touched. Such objects were peculiar in the fact
108
into something else. Ice and snow, when they disappear, are replaced by
hypothesis that the water was the same thing as the ice and snow, but in
a new form. Solid bodies, when they break, break into parts which are
practically the same in shape and size as they were before. A stone can
retain the character they had before the pounding. Thus the ideal of
atomism. Apart from the special form of the atomic theory which was
invented for the needs of chemistry, some kind of atomism dominated the
modifications in theory which are much slighter than the layman might
indestructible is always very small, but does not always occupy a mere
109
the motion takes place, and until lately we might have assumed one
the one all-embracing time still, I think, underlies all that physics
single time.
permanent; even the things that we think are fairly permanent, such as
mountains, only become data when we see them, and are not immediately
being given, there are several spaces for each person, according to the
110
private world, but the correlation of one private time with another is a
permanent "things," (2) the construction of a single space, and (3) the
succession.
(1) The belief in indestructible "things" very early took the form of
belief that beneath all the changes of the sensible world there must be
not existed, the same laws which are now formulated in terms of this
belief might just as well have been formulated without it. Why should we
suppose that, when ice melts, the water which replaces it is the same
111
can give laws according to which the one appearance will be succeeded by
the other, but there is no reason except prejudice for regarding both as
One task, if what has just been said is correct, which confronts us in
trying to connect the world of sense with the world of physics, is the
which fulfils roughly the same functions. The time has hardly come when
we can state precisely what this legitimate conception is, but we can
see in a general way what it must be like. For this purpose, it is only
112
at another. But what do we really know about it? We know that under
If we can state the laws according to which the colour varies, we can
certain thing will merely mean that it is one of those which, taken
than one which, like common sense and most philosophy, assumes
113
hypothetical entities whose existence there is no good reason to believe
that what is easy and natural in thought is what is most free from
illustrates.
There is, to begin with, some conflict between what common sense regards
is not very serious, and may, for our rough preliminary purpose, be
certain data from the chaos, and call them all appearances of the same
thing?
114
the Comedy of Errors illustrates, we may be led astray if we judge by
mere resemblance. This shows that something more is involved, for two
regard them as belonging to the same thing, then there was a continuous
series of intermediate states of that thing during the time when we were
the case where our attention has not been concentrated on the thing
for supposing the earlier and later appearances to belong to the same
we can, for example, pass by sensibly continuous gradations from any one
drop of the sea to any other drop. The utmost we can say is that
difference between things, though even this cannot be said in such cases
as sudden explosions.
115
This proves something, though not anything of very obvious utility to
inconsistent with the hypothesis that all changes are really continuous,
though from too great rapidity or from our lack of observation they may
condition, as appears from the instance of the drops in the sea. Thus
something more must be sought before we can give even the roughest
definition of a "thing."
case, events at the same time provided the connection is not logically
116
all belonging to a given period of time. Now physics has found it
the laws of physics, in a way in which series not belonging to one thing
appearances belong to the same thing or not, there must be only one way
physics. It would be very difficult to prove that this is the case, but
for our present purposes we may let this point pass, and assume that
those of its aspects, if any, which are not observed. Thus we may lay
down the following definition: Things are those series of aspects which
obey the laws of physics. That such series exist is an empirical fact,
(a) We have been considering, in the above account, the question of the
117
psychological. For a proposition to be verifiable, it is not enough that
at times when, in fact, they are not appearing to anyone; (γ) things
which never appear at all. All these are introduced to simplify the
statement of the causal laws, but none of them form an integral part of
answer.
perspectives, two of which never had any entity in common, but often
118
state of a thing is a whole set of aspects. An "ideal" appearance will
all its appearances are ideal. An ideal thing will be one whose states
at all times are ideal. Ideal appearances, states, and things, since
determine when they become actual. This, in fact, we have with some
this; but unless in virtue of some a priori law we cannot know it,
(2) The three main conceptions of physics are space, time, and matter.
indicated in the above discussion of "things." But space and time also
consideration of space.
People who have never read any psychology seldom realise how much mental
119
labour has gone into the construction of the one all-embracing space
into which all sensible objects are supposed to fit. Kant, who was
which is infinite is not given, while a space which can be called given
some general remarks may be made, which will suffice to show the
debate.
spaces. The space of sight is quite different from the space of touch:
later life, when we see an object within reach, we know how to touch it,
and more or less what it will feel like; if we touch an object with our
eyes shut, we know where we should have to look for it, and more or less
what it would look like. But this knowledge is derived from early
certain kinds of sight-sensations. The one space into which both kinds
besides touch and sight, there are other kinds of sensation which give
other, though less important spaces: these also have to be fitted into
120
experience makes certain is the several spaces of the several senses,
correlated by empirically discovered laws. The one space may turn out to
reality.
one has ever seen or touched a point. If there are points in a sensible
data; thus here again, we shall have, if possible, to find some logical
geometry in no way demands that we should think of them in this way. All
that is necessary for geometry is that they should have mutual relations
this is to be done, I do not yet know, but it seems fairly certain that
it can be done.
121
of all to observe that there are no infinitesimal sense-data: any
surface we can see, for example, must be of some finite extent. But what
whole. Thus one spatial object may be contained within another, and
certain class of spatial objects, namely all those (as it will turn out
in the end) which would naturally be said to contain the point. In order
Given any set of volumes or surfaces, they will not in general converge
into one point. But if they get smaller and smaller, while of any two of
the set there is always one that encloses the other, then we begin to
having a point for their limit. The hypotheses required for the relation
single spatial object always encloses itself; (3) any set of spatial
objects such that there is at least one spatial object enclosed by them
them and enclosing all objects which are enclosed by all of them; (4) to
122
will call a set of objects an "enclosure-series" if, of any two of them,
chosen member of our first series, then there are members of our first
itself also encloses an object other than itself. The "points" generated
geometry requires.
world, is rather less complicated than that of space, and we can see
for a mathematical instant, but always for some finite time, however
which are not merely and strictly instantaneous, and therefore the
123
experience, and, if legitimate, must be either inferred or constructed.
left with the alternative that they must be constructed. How is this to
be done?
they may be simultaneous, or one may be earlier and the other later.
These two are both part of the crude data; it is not the case that only
the events are given, and their time-order is added by our subjective
events. In any story of adventure you will find such passages as the
of the dauntless youth. 'At the word three I shall fire,' he said. The
words one and two had already been spoken with a cool and deliberate
distinctness. The word three was forming on his lips. At this moment a
experience that the words one and two come earlier than the flash.
instantaneous. Thus one event may begin sooner than another, and
therefore be before it, but may continue after the other has begun, and
and later, are not inconsistent with each other when we are concerned
124
with events which last for a finite time, however short; they only
and succession, are all that experience provides. Hence, unless we are
some construction which assumes nothing beyond events and their temporal
relations.
proceed? If we take any one event, we cannot assign our date exactly,
simultaneous with two events which are not simultaneous with each other.
determine whether any given event is before, at, or after this date, and
we must know that any other date is either before or after this date,
but not simultaneous with it. Suppose, now, instead of taking one event
A, we take two events A and B, and suppose A and B partly overlap, but B
ends before A ends. Then an event which is simultaneous with both A and
B must exist during the time when A and B overlap; thus we have come
125
Let C be an event which is simultaneous with both A and B, but which
with A and B and C must exist during the time when all three overlap,
and more events, a new event which is dated as simultaneous with all of
them becomes gradually more and more accurately dated. This suggests a
Let us take a group of events of which any two overlap, so that there is
some time, however short, when they all exist. If there is any other
outside the group is simultaneous with all of them, but all the events
inside the group are simultaneous with each other. Let us define this
What are the properties we expect of instants? First, they must form a
series: of any two, one must be before the other, and the other must be
not before the one; if one is before another, and the other before a
126
third, the first must be before the third. Secondly, every event must be
at the same instant, and one is before the other if there is an instant,
at which the one is, which is earlier than some instant at which the
other is. Thirdly, if we assume that there is always some change going
on somewhere during the time when any given event persists, the series
group by which the instant is constituted; and we shall say that one
instant is before another if the group which is the one instant contains
an event which is earlier than, but not simultaneous with, some event in
the group which is the other instant. When one event is earlier than,
precedes" the other. Now we know that of two events which are not
simultaneous, there must be one which wholly precedes the other, and in
that case the other cannot also wholly precede the one; we also know
that, if one event wholly precedes another, and the other wholly
precedes a third, then the first wholly precedes the third. From these
form a series.
We have next to show that every event is "at" at least one instant,
i.e. that, given any event, there is at least one class, such as we
127
used in defining instants, of which it is a member. For this purpose,
consider all the events which are simultaneous with a given event, and
do not begin later, i.e. are not wholly after anything simultaneous
with it. We will call these the "initial contemporaries" of the given
event. It will be found that this class of events is the first instant
at which the given event exists, provided every event wholly after some
contemporary of it.
Finally, the series of instants will be compact if, given any two events
of which one wholly precedes the other, there are events wholly after
the one and simultaneous with something wholly before the other. Whether
as follows:--
(b) If one event wholly precedes another, and the other wholly
128
(c) If one event wholly precedes another, it is not simultaneous
with it.
(d) Of two events which are not simultaneous, one must wholly
compact, we assume:
after the one and simultaneous with something wholly before the
other.
This assumption entails the consequence that if one event covers the
it must have at least one instant in common with the other event;
129
Camb. Phil. Soc., xvii. 5, pp. 441-449.
entities.
should be transitive, i.e. that if one event encloses another, and the
other a third, then the first encloses the third; (2) that every event
encloses itself, but if one event encloses another different event, then
the other does not enclose the one; (3) that given any set of events
such that there is at least one event enclosed by all of them, then
there is an event enclosing all that they all enclose, and itself
enclosed by all of them; (4) that there is at least one event. To ensure
any two there is one which encloses the other; this will be a "punctual
member of our first series encloses some member of our second, then
130
every member of our second series encloses some member of our first.
sound will be heard sooner by people near the source of the sound than
by people further from it, and the same applies, though in a less
and thus raises rather complicated technical problems; but from the
The above brief outline must not be regarded as more than tentative and
131
given a world with the kind of properties that psychologists find in the
the fact that its particles, points, and instants are not to be found
one whose importance and even existence has been concealed by the
obsessed by the idealistic opinion that only mind is real, and the
mathematics and modern logic, and have therefore been content to say
making any attempt to show in detail either how the intellect can
132
construct them, or what secures the practical validity which physics
recognise that they cannot achieve any solid success in such problems
meanwhile, for want of students with the necessary equipment, this vital
There are, it is true, two authors, both physicists, who have done
as one demanding study. These two authors are Poincaré and Mach,
while with Mach the sensation as a mental event is identified with its
133
objects any two of which have a relation of the sort called "symmetrical
as all having some common quality, or as all having the same relation to
some one object outside the set. This kind of case is important, and I
shall therefore try to make it clear even at the cost of some repetition
of previous definitions.
relation to another, then the other also has it to the one. Thus
this relation to another, and the other to a third, then the one has it
to the third. The symmetrical relations mentioned just now are also
"ancestor of," in fact all such relations as give rise to series. Other
134
from C. Simultaneity, again, in the case of events which last for a
the times of the two events overlap. If A ends just after B has begun,
and B ends just after C has begun, A and B will be simultaneous in this
sense, and so will B and C, but A and C may well not be simultaneous.
the same height or weight or colour. Owing to the fact that possession
hence we come to imagine that there really is a thing, other than the
relation. In all such cases, the class of terms that have the given
Since there certainly is the class, while any other common property may
135
substitute the class for the common property which would be ordinarily
assumed. This is the reason for the definitions we have adopted, and
them, but merely abstain from asserting them. But if there are not such
common properties in any given case, then our method has secured us
method we have adopted is the only one which is safe, and which avoids
136
LECTURE V
logical basis of the theory alone belongs to philosophy, and alone will
philosophy is, broadly speaking, the following: Space and time are
they are resolved into points and instants. Zeno, as we shall see,
times could not consist of a finite number of points and instants, for
137
But even when points and instants, as independent entities, are
discarded, as they were by the theory advocated in our last lecture, the
points and instants, and consider the problems in connection with this
there remains a feeling--of the kind that led Zeno to the contention
that the arrow in its flight is at rest--which suggests that points and
instants, even if they are infinitely numerous, can only give a jerky
transitions with which the senses have made us familiar. This feeling is
often a long and serious labour still required in order to feel it: it
is necessary to dwell upon it, to thrust out from the mind, one by one,
138
inadequate explanation of the continuity which we experience in the
world of sense.
In the present lecture, I shall first try to explain in outline what the
question to begin with. I do not see any reason to suppose that the
and time are actual physically existing entities, but I do see reason to
suppose that the continuity of actual space and time may be more or less
upon any properties of actual space and time. What is claimed for it is
previously very hard to analyse, are found not to present any logical
and fully adequate to the observed facts. For the present, however, it
will be well to forget space and time and the continuity of sensible
two that one comes before the other. Numbers in order of magnitude,
139
the points on a line from left to right, the moments of time from
number. It is possible to know that two classes have the same number of
terms without knowing any order in which they are to be taken. We have
wives: we can see that there must be the same number of husbands as of
certain order. A set of terms which can be arranged in one order can
always also be arranged in other orders, and a set of terms which can be
which are not continuous. Thus the essence of continuity must not be
sought in the nature of the set of terms, but in the nature of their
arrangement in a series.
called "compact" when no two terms are consecutive, but between any two
however near together, there are other fractions greater than the one
140
and smaller than the other, and therefore no two fractions are
if we choose some fraction which is very little greater than 1/2, say
51/100 we can find others, such as 101/200, which are nearer to 1/2.
Thus between any two fractions, however little they differ, there are an
have this property of compactness, though whether actual space and time
infinity, for in a compact series the number of terms between any two
given terms must be infinite. But when these difficulties have been
account, and must, in its analysis, raise just such problems as are
141
for the present, the question of its physical adequacy, let us devote
tiny speck of light moving along a scale. What do we mean by saying that
positions, the speck will not jump suddenly from the one to the other,
but will pass through an infinite number of other positions on the way.
continuity of motion by saying that the speck always passes from one
soon as we say this or imagine it, we fall into error, because there is
142
from one instant to the next, travel further than from one point to the
positions intermediate between that at the first instant and that at the
long as it moves, pass from one point at one instant to the next point
at the next instant. Thus there will be just one perfectly definite
velocity with which all motions must take place: no motion can be faster
than this, and no motion can be slower. Since this conclusion is false,
we must reject the hypothesis upon which it is based, namely that there
given distance, and then halve the half, and so on, we can continue the
process as long as we please, and the longer we continue it, the smaller
143
finite distances. If our original distance was an inch, we reach
distances is finite. "But," it may be said, "in the end the distance
distances, which must be admitted, does not imply that there are
blunder. Given any finite distance, we can find a smaller distance; this
by it.
In a continuous motion, then, we shall say that at any given instant the
occupies other positions; the interval between any two instants and
between any two positions is always finite, but the continuity of the
motion is shown in the fact that, however near together we take the two
144
positions still nearer together, which are occupied at instants that are
also still nearer together. The moving body never jumps from one
is, like Zeno's arrow;[19] but we cannot say that it is at rest at the
instant, since the instant does not last for a finite time, and there is
not a beginning and end of the instant with an interval between them.
demands, for its full comprehension, that compact series should have
thought.
now any small portion P1P2 of the path of the particle, this portion
being one which contains P. We say then that, if the motion of the
instants t1, t2, one earlier than t and one later, such that
145
particle lies between P1 and P2. And we say that this must still hold
however small we make the portion P1P2. When this is the case, we say
that the motion is continuous at the time t; and when the motion is
from P to some other point Q, our definition would fail for all
intervals P1P2 which were too small to include Q. Thus our definition
time.
P1 P P2 Q
------|----|----|----|------>
adopted other and more heroic methods of dealing with the primâ facie
Apart from definite arguments, there are certain feelings, rather than
see its motion just as we see its colour. A slow motion, like that
146
of the hour-hand of a watch, is only known in the way which mathematics
do not merely see first one position and then another--we see something
mathematical theory emphasise this fact. "Your theory," they say, "may
be very logical, and might apply admirably to some other world; but in
this actual world, actual motions are quite different from what your
theory would declare them to be, and require, therefore, some different
The objection thus raised is one which I have no wish to underrate, but
and the outlook which have led to the mathematical theory of motion. Let
this sense the hour-hand and the second-hand are equally in motion, yet
147
simultaneously in a number of places, although it must also involve our
for example, I move my hand quickly from left to right, you seem to see
the whole movement at once, in spite of the fact that you know it begins
really one indivisible whole, not the series of separate states imagined
by the mathematician.
(1) The physiological answer merely shows that, if the physical world is
thus the modest one of showing that the mathematical account is not
applies in psychology.
does not cease instantaneously with the cessation of the stimulus, but
see it for a few moments after the light-waves have ceased to strike the
148
we shall actually at one instant see the moving body throughout a finite
portion of its course, and not only at the exact spot where it is at
from this that, when we see a rapid motion, we shall not only see a
fades away into immediate memory. This state of things accounts fully
sensible at one time; and the earlier and later parts of one perceived
sensations.
This answer shows that physiology can account for our perception of
the truth of physics, and is thus only capable of showing the physical
vast theory, not yet worked out, and only capable, at present, of being
149
lectures; for the present, a mere sketch of its application to our
present problem must suffice. The world of physics, which was assumed in
physics. The question is thus forced upon us: Is the inference from
for reasons which I suggested in the third and fourth lectures; but the
showing that, although the particles, points, and instants with which
physics operates are not themselves given in experience, and are very
likely not actually existing things, yet, out of the materials provided
instants. If this can be done, then all the propositions of physics can
or at any rate more consonant with the facts than any other equally
long enough for its motion to be not wholly comprised in one sensation.
Then, in spite of the fact that we see a finite extent of the motion at
150
one instant, the extent which we see at one instant is different from
that which we see at another. Thus we are brought back, after all, to a
series of momentary views of the moving body, and this series will be
compact, like the former physical series of points. In fact, though the
apply to it verbatim.
between them. An old but conclusive reason for believing this was
another, and that other indistinguishable from a third, while yet the
first and third are quite easily distinguishable. Suppose, for example,
a person with his eyes shut is holding a weight in his hand, and someone
another small extra weight may be added, and still no change will be
perceived; but if both extra weights had been added at once, it may be
that the change would be quite easily perceptible. Or, again, take
and second, nor yet between the second and third, while yet the first
151
cannot be the same as the first, or it would be distinguishable from the
vol. i. p. 29.
152
There are a number of distinct questions which are apt to be confused
follows:--
possible?
(b) Assuming that they are possible logically, are they not
(c) Does not the assumption of points and instants make the whole
(d) Finally, assuming that all these objections have been answered,
the mathematical infinite, which will occupy our next two lectures, and
153
partly on the logical form of the answer to the Bergsonian objection
which we stated a few minutes ago. I shall say no more on this topic at
answer.
the fact that sense-data are immediately given does not mean that their
absurdum of the analytic view, that, if A and B are immediate data, and
154
A differs from B, then the fact that they differ must also be an
instance with a person, what we must mean is, becoming acquainted with
more parts of a certain whole; but the acquaintance with each part is
were perfectly acquainted with an object we should know all about it.
To know that two shades of colour are different is knowledge about them;
hence acquaintance with the two shades does not in any way necessitate
From what has just been said it follows that the nature of sense-data
cannot be validly used to prove that they are not composed of mutually
their empirical character specially necessitates the view that they are
grounds are adequate to the conclusion. They rest, at bottom, upon the
155
impossibility of explaining complexity without assuming constituents. It
is undeniable that the visual field, for example, is complex; and so far
lead us too far from our theme, and I shall therefore say no more about
it at present.
questions in turn may take two forms, namely: (α) is the hypothesis
the facts or by logic? I wish to answer, in each case, yes to the first
form of the question, and no to the second. But in any case the
i.e. it assumes that, besides the things which are in space and time,
there are also entities, called "points" and "instants," which are
156
long been regarded by mathematicians as merely a convenient fiction.
facts. But the facts are also consistent with the denial of spatial and
temporal entities over and above things with spatial and temporal
abstain from either assuming or denying points and instants. This means,
instants has the same effect as the denial of them. But in strict theory
the two are quite different, since the denial introduces an element of
the assertion. Thus, although we shall derive points and instants from
things, we shall leave the bare possibility open that they may also have
We come now to the question whether the things in space and time are to
157
into instant-particles, so that the ultimate formal constituent of the
well as the particles of physics, are not data. The same economy of
than an absolute space and time, also dictates the practical adoption of
with our actual data in having a finite extension and duration. Thus, so
(d) But we must now face the question: Is there, in actual empirical
The answer here must, I think, be in the negative. We may say that the
158
discoverable to show that objects of sense are not continuous. In what
each differs from its neighbour in a finite though very small degree.
shades in the spectrum, and so on, are all in the nature of unverifiable
known facts, and simpler technically than any other tenable hypotheses,
but not the sole hypotheses which are logically and empirically
adequate.
is defined as a group of events simultaneous with each other and not all
simultaneous with any event outside the group, then if our resulting
159
series of instants is to be compact, it must be possible, if x wholly
wholly precedes some event which wholly precedes y. Now this requires
cannot, we must do one of two things: either declare that the world of
provides the apparatus for dealing with the various hypotheses, and the
160
positive theory which is urged on the other side. The view urged
doctrine, which holds that analysis always falsifies, because the parts
any form which has a precise meaning. Often arguments are used which
that when a man becomes a father, his nature is altered by the new
with the man who was previously not a father. This may be true, but it
can never be two facts concerning the same thing. A fact concerning a
facts concerning the same thing would involve two relations of the same
Hence, if this doctrine is true, there can never be more than one fact
have realised that this is the precise statement of the view they
161
that its falsehood is evident as soon as it is stated. The discussion of
and must demand analysis. So long as our analysis has only gone as far
it must end with terms that are not changes, but are related by a
without any duration which even the most delicate instruments can
really easier than any other that the facts allow. It is a kind of
necessarily itself the statement of the crude facts, but a form in which
statements which are true of the crude facts can be made by a suitable
lecture, we have only been concerned to show that nothing in the crude
162
facts is inconsistent with the mathematical doctrine of continuity, or
mathematical motion.
163
LECTURE VI
the reality of the sensible world has been questioned, one of those
easier and more natural, from a scientific point of view, than any
other, and since Georg Cantor has shown that the supposed contradictions
fact that a continuous series must have an infinite number of terms, and
infinite from contradiction, we are at the same time showing the logical
The kind of way in which infinity has been used to discredit the world
first, the thesis states: "The world has a beginning in time, and as
164
regards space is enclosed within limits"; the antithesis states: "The
respect of both time and space." Kant professes to prove both these
the two. For our present purpose, it is the proof that the world is
finite that interests us. Kant's argument as regards space here rests
upon his argument as regards time. We need therefore only examine the
"For let us assume that the world has no beginning as regards time, so
passed by. But the infinity of a series consists just in this, that it
thing to be proved."
165
all at once by the defining property of their members, so that there is
which all Kant's philosophy was infected. In the second place, when Kant
by no means suitable for his purposes. And with this result we might, if
something like this: Starting from the present and going backwards in
they had occurred, i.e. going from the present backwards. This
series is obviously one which has no end. But the series of events up to
the present has an end, since it ends with the present. Owing to the
necessary to identify the mental series, which had no end, with the
166
physical series, which had an end but no beginning. It was this mistake,
before, the proofs of both thesis and antithesis are open to criticism,
but for the purpose of vindicating physics and the world of sense it is
enough to find a fallacy in one of the proofs. We will choose for this
thing must consist of as many parts as the thing consists of. Now space
The rest of his argument need not concern us, for the nerve of the proof
lies in the one statement: "Space does not consist of simple parts, but
holds that a space must consist of spaces rather than of simple parts.
167
Geometry regards space as made up of points, which are simple; and
the antinomy were valid, and if the antithesis could only be avoided by
reason in favour of points. Why, then, did Kant think it impossible that
the essential thing about space is spatial order, and mere points, by
themselves, will not account for spatial order. It is obvious that his
alone important, and they cannot be reduced to points. This ground for
his view depends, therefore, upon his ignorance of the logical theory of
order and his oscillations between absolute and relative space. But
there is also another ground for his opinion, which is more relevant to
ad infinitum, and at every stage of the process the parts are still
168
the process of successive division. Thus the infinite divisibility of
space gives no ground for denying that space is composed of points. Kant
does not give his grounds for this denial, and we can therefore only
conjecture what they were. But the above two grounds, which we have seen
unproved.
how it arose, and to show the irrelevance of all the solutions proposed
who study it carefully. For over two thousand years the human intellect
was baffled by the problem; its many failures and its ultimate success
The problem appears to have first arisen in some such way as the
science more arithmetical methods than those with which Euclid has made
169
apparently, that space is composed of indivisible points, while time is
not suppose that this latter belief was a conscious one, because
nevertheless operated, and very soon brought them into conflict with
phrase "finite number." The exact explanation is a matter for our next
lecture; for the present, it must suffice to say that I mean 0 and 1 and
2 and 3 and so on, for ever--in other words, any number that can be
obtained by successively adding ones. This includes all the numbers that
170
1083b, 8 sqq.
It would seem that the distinction between space and matter had not yet
"The Pythagoreans all maintained the existence of the void, and said
that it enters into the heaven itself from the boundless breath,
inasmuch as the heaven breathes in the void also; and the void
differentiates them."
Geometry from Thales to Euclid, says (p. 23): "The Pythagoreans made
parts to the how many, τ π σον, and the other to the how much, τ
πηλ κον; and they assigned to each of these parts a twofold division.
For they said that discrete quantity, or the how many, either
171
but that continued quantity, or the how much, is either stable or in
p. 48.
with empty space in between. But if so, they must have thought space
172
discovered the proposition that the sum of the squares on the sides of a
the ox was the first martyr to science. But the theorem, though it has
the sides. But Pythagoras or his early followers easily proved that the
another.[27] Thus the length of the side and the length of the diagonal
contained any exact number of times in the diagonal, and vice versa.
and n are whole numbers having no common factor. Then we must have
m2 = 2n2. Now the square of an odd number is odd, but m2, being
odd and even, which is impossible; and therefore the diagonal and the
173
Now this fact might have been assimilated by some philosophies without
essence of all things, yet no two numbers could express the ratio of the
atoms contained in it--a line two inches long would contain twice as
many atoms as a line one inch long, and so on. But if this were the
truth, then there must be a definite numerical ratio between any two
of the supreme heads of the sect; and one of their number, Hippasos of
disciples might fall into sin, and perhaps even eat beans, which
time went on, to be one of the most severe and at the same time most
174
endeavour to understand the world. It showed at once that numerical
arithmetic more advanced and more difficult than any that the ancients
effected with extraordinary skill and with great logical acumen. The
been given. With these definitions, the first and most obvious form of
the difficulty which confronted the Pythagoreans has been solved; but
We saw that, accepting the view that a length is composed of points, the
away points one by one, we should never have taken away all the points,
175
qualities. So paradoxical are these qualities that until our own day
due, not to Bolzano, but to Georg Cantor, whose work on this subject
divided into two parts, called "the way of truth" and "the way of
Parmenides tells us first about reality and then about appearance. "The
trustworthy speech and thought about the truth. Henceforward learn the
176
What has gone before has been revealed by a goddess, who tells him what
without beginning and without end; since coming into being and passing
away have been driven afar, and true belief has cast them away." The
not be out of place in Hegel:[30] "Thou canst not know what is not--that
thought and that can be." And again: "It needs must be that what can be
thought and spoken of is; for it is possible for it to be, and it is not
from this principle; for what is past can be spoken of, and therefore,
this view.
177
those of Plato, Spinoza, and Hegel--are the outcome of this fundamental
view. The contention that time is unreal and that the world of sense is
into the stream of time from an eternal world outside, than from a view
which regards time as the devouring tyrant of all that is. Both in
be mainly critical.
Jowett's translation:
"I see, Parmenides, said Socrates, that Zeno is your second self in his
writings too; he puts what you say in another way, and would fain
178
your poems, say All is one, and of this you adduce excellent proofs; and
saying the same thing in different ways, one of you affirming the one,
and the other denying the many, is a strain of art beyond the reach of
most of us.
"Yes, Socrates, said Zeno. But although you are as keen as a Spartan
hound in pursuing the track, you do not quite apprehend the true motive
intention of deceiving the world. The truth is, that these writings of
mine were meant to protect the arguments of Parmenides against those who
scoff at him and show the many ridiculous and contradictory results
which they suppose to follow from the affirmation of the one. My answer
the many if carried out appears in a still more ridiculous light than
179
Aristotle,[33] who stated them in order to refute them. Those
philosophers in the present day who have had their doctrines stated by
which have been "refuted" by every tyro from that day to this.
his opponents must deny. In order to decide whether they are valid
premisses, and to decide who was the "homo" at whom they were aimed.
Some maintain that they were aimed at the Pythagoreans,[34] while others
180
variety of interpretations, we can at least not complain of any
über Geschichte der Mathematik, 1st ed., vol. i., 1880, p. 168, who,
no doubt largely insoluble, owing to the very scanty material from which
our evidence is derived. The points which seem fairly clear are the
following: (1) That, in spite of MM. Milhaud and Paul Tannery, Zeno is
(2) that the third and fourth arguments proceed on the hypothesis of
181
indivisibles, a hypothesis which, whether adopted by the Pythagoreans or
not, was certainly much advocated, as may be seen from the treatise On
view that space and time consist of points and instants; and that as
finite number of points and instants, his arguments are not sophisms,
delusion, and spaces and times are really indivisible. The other
"If things are a many, they must be just as many as they are, and
neither more nor less. Now, if they are as many as they are, they will
182
be finite in number.
"If things are a many, they will be infinite in number; for there will
always be other things between them, and others again between these. And
pp. 364-365.
This argument attempts to prove that, if there are many things, the
hence we are to conclude that there is only one thing. But the weak
point in the argument is the phrase: "If they are just as many as they
are, they will be finite in number." This phrase is not very clear, but
suffice to prove that motion and change and plurality are impossible.
They are not, however, on any view, mere foolish quibbles: they are
years to answer, and which even now are fatal to the teachings of most
philosophers.
183
"You cannot get to the end of a race-course. You cannot traverse an
infinite number of points in a finite time. You must traverse the half
of any given distance before you traverse the whole, and the half of
that again before you can traverse it. This goes on ad infinitum, so
that there are an infinite number of points in any given space, and you
[41] Aristotle's words are: "The first is the one on the non-existence
of motion on the ground that what is moved must always attain the
middle point sooner than the end-point, on which we gave our opinion
"All space is continuous, for time and space are divided into the same
an infinite collection one by one in a finite time. For there are two
184
and we touch infinite things with infinite things, not with finite
hour, since in every space there are an infinite number of points, the
thing moved must needs touch all the points of the space: it will then
impossible."
Zeno appeals here, in the first place, to the fact that any distance,
one by one in a finite time. The words "one by one" are important. (1)
If all the points touched are concerned, then, though you pass through
them continuously, you do not touch them "one by one." That is to say,
after touching one, there is not another which you touch next: no two
points are next each other, but between any two there are always an
If, on the other hand, only the successive middle points are concerned,
obtained by always halving what remains of the course, then the points
are reached one by one, and, though they are infinite in number, they
are in fact all reached in a finite time. His argument to the contrary
may be supposed to appeal to the view that a finite time must consist of
185
dichotomy is undeniable. If, on the other hand, we suppose the argument
reached in succession, each being reached a finite time later than its
form the argument is invalid. If half the course takes half a minute,
and the next quarter takes a quarter of a minute, and so on, the whole
course will take a minute. The apparent force of the argument, on this
The second of Zeno's arguments is the one concerning Achilles and the
"Achilles will never overtake the tortoise. He must first reach the
place from which the tortoise started. By that time the tortoise will
have got some way ahead. Achilles must then make up that, and again the
186
tortoise will be ahead. He is always coming nearer, but he never makes
up to it."[44]
course by the quickest, for the pursuer must always come first to the
point from which the pursued has just departed, so that the slower
fact true; but the view that an infinite number of instants make up an
infinitely long time is not true, and therefore the conclusion that
The third argument,[45] that of the arrow, is very interesting. The text
paraphrases thus:
187
[45] Phys., vi. 9. 239B (R.P. 138).
at rest, but what is moving is always in the now, then the moving
arrow is motionless." This form of the argument brings out its force
Here, if not in the first two arguments, the view that a finite part of
the instant, for that would require that the instant should have parts.
the thousand instants, the arrow is where it is, though at the next
way the change of position has to occur between the instants, that is
to say, not at any time whatever. This is what M. Bergson calls the
meditated, the more real it becomes. The solution lies in the theory of
188
moment; but in fact there is no next position and no next moment, and
disappear.
The fourth and last of Zeno's arguments is[46] the argument of the
stadium.
A .... A ....
B .... B ....
C .... C ....
"Half the time may be equal to double the time. Let us suppose three
rows of bodies, one of which (A) is at rest while the other two (B, C)
are moving with equal velocity in opposite directions. By the time they
are all in the same part of the course, B will have passed twice as many
is twice as long as the time it takes to pass A. But the time which B
and C take to reach the position of A is the same. Therefore double the
189
argument. His translation of Aristotle's statement is as follows:
"The fourth argument is that concerning the two rows of bodies, each row
directions, the one row originally occupying the space between the goal
and the middle point of the course, and the other that between the
conclusion that half a given time is equal to double the time. The
equal time in passing with equal velocity a body that is in motion and a
instance (so runs the argument), let A A ... be the stationary bodies of
equal size, B B ... the bodies, equal in number and in size to A A ...,
the middle of the A's, and C C ... those originally occupying the other
half from the goal to the middle of the A's, equal in number, size, and
and C's pass one another, the first B reaches the last C at the same
moment at which the first C reaches the last B. Secondly, at this moment
the first C has passed all the A's, whereas the first B has passed only
half the A's and has consequently occupied only half the time occupied
by the first C, since each of the two occupies an equal time in passing
each A. Thirdly, at the same moment all the B's have passed all the C's:
for the first C and the first B will simultaneously reach the opposite
ends of the course, since (so says Zeno) the time occupied by the first
190
C in passing each of the B's is equal to that occupied by it in passing
each of the A's, because an equal time is occupied by both the first B
and the first C in passing all the A's. This is the argument: but it
B B′ B″ B B′ B″
· · · · · ·
A A′ A″ A A′ A″
· · · · · ·
C C′ C″ C C′ C″
· · · · · ·
drill-sergeants, A, A′, and A″, standing in a row, while the two files
which we consider, the three men B, B′, B″ in one row, and the three men
C, C′, C″ in the other row, are respectively opposite to A, A′, and A″.
At the very next moment, each row has moved on, and now B and C″ are
opposite A′. Thus B and C″ are opposite each other. When, then, did B
191
pass C′? It must have been somewhere between the two moments which we
supposed consecutive, and therefore the two moments cannot really have
any two given moments, and therefore that there must be an infinite
The above difficulty, that B must have passed C′ at some time between
previous instant. Any slower motion must be one which has intervals of
rest interspersed, and any faster motion must wholly omit some points.
All this is evident from the fact that we cannot have more than one
event for each instant. But now, in the case of our A's and B's and C's,
passed gives the number of instants since the beginning of the motion.
But during the motion B has passed twice as many C's, and yet cannot
have passed more than one each instant. Hence the number of instants
since the motion began is twice the number of A's passed, though we
192
previously found it was equal to this number. From this result, Zeno's
conclusion follows.
Zeno's arguments, in some form, have afforded grounds for almost all the
theories of space and time and infinity which have been constructed from
his day to our own. We have seen that all his arguments are valid (with
times consist of a finite number of points and instants, and that the
while the first and second, which were perhaps intended to refute the
escape from his paradoxes either by maintaining that, though space and
time do consist of points and instants, the number of them in any finite
followed him. Many others, like M. Bergson, have preferred to deny that
space and time consist of points and instants. Either of these solutions
will meet the difficulties in the form in which Zeno raised them. But,
infinite numbers, and series in which no two terms are consecutive, must
193
in any case be admitted. Consider, for example, all the fractions less
are others, for example, the arithmetical mean of the two. Thus no two
will be found that much of what Zeno says as regards the series of
And we cannot deny that there are fractions, so that two of the above
ways of escape are closed to us. It follows that, if we are to solve the
discover some tenable theory of infinite numbers. What, then, are the
difficulties which, until the last thirty years, led philosophers to the
The difficulties of infinity are of two kinds, of which the first may be
called sham, while the others involve, for their solution, a certain
amount of new and not altogether easy thinking. The sham difficulties
end." But in fact some infinite series have ends, some have not; while
some collections are infinite without being serial, and can therefore
instants from any earlier one to any later one (both included) is
infinite, but has two ends; the series of instants from the beginning of
time to the present moment has one end, but is infinite. Kant, in his
194
infinite than for the future to be so, on the ground that the past is
difficult to see how he can have imagined that there was any sense in
this remark; but it seems most probable that he was thinking of the
infinite as the "unended." It is odd that he did not see that the future
too has one end at the present, and is precisely on a level with the
so-called "true" infinite are curious. They see that this notion is not
the same as the mathematical infinite, but they choose to believe that
They therefore inform the mathematicians, kindly but firmly, that they
what they call the "true" infinite is a notion totally irrelevant to the
issue by even mentioning what the "true" infinite is. It is the "false"
infinite that concerns us, and we have to show that the epithet "false"
is undeserved.
195
finite numbers, and easily extended to infinite numbers under the
every number that we are accustomed to, except 0, has another number
immediately before it, from which it results by adding 1; but the first
infinite number does not have this property. The numbers before it form
no maximum, no last finite number, after which one little step would
This, we may point out, is the very principle upon which Zeno relies in
the arguments of the race-course and the Achilles. Take the race-course:
there is the moment when the runner still has half his distance to run,
then the moment when he still has a quarter, then when he still has an
this series is the moment when he reaches the goal. Thus there certainly
to show that this fact is only what might have been expected.
count the terms in an infinite collection, you will never have completed
196
seven-eighths, and so on of the course were marked, and the runner was
not allowed to pass any of the marks until the umpire said "Now," then
the goal.
its terms in review one by one. This may be seen in the case of finite
And exactly the same happens in the case of infinite collections: they
whole, and there may be new terms beyond the whole of it.
mental habits. The whole difficulty of the subject lies in the necessity
197
those who cling obstinately to the prejudices instilled by the
198
LECTURE VII
which it has given rise, are among the triumphs of scientific method in
difficult question, partly concerned with the use of words, but partly
between the two treatments being in the direction of movement and in the
when they have become fully developed, the movement is forward and
follow the inverse direction: from the complex and relatively concrete
199
Between philosophy and pure mathematics there is a certain affinity, in
the fact that both are general and a priori. Neither of them asserts
propositions which, like those of history and geography, depend upon the
actual concrete facts being just what they are. We may illustrate this
worlds, of which one only is actual. In all the many possible worlds,
philosophy and mathematics will be the same; the differences will only
which are common knowledge, seeks to purify and generalise them into the
logical analysis.
our present problem, namely, the nature of number. Both start from
200
number?" is the pre-eminent philosophic question in this subject, but it
is one which the mathematician as such need not ask, provided he knows
theorems. We, since our object is philosophical, must grapple with the
The question "What is a number?" is one which, until quite recent times,
precise answer. Philosophers were content with some vague dictum such
because some flowers are yellow. Take, for example, the number 3. A
unity"; but a collection of three things is not the number 3. The number
apart from any other defects, has failed to reach the necessary degree
201
collection of three things.
because of their very vagueness. What most men who thought about numbers
really had in mind was that numbers are the result of counting. "On
which they are reached. And infinite numbers cannot be reached at all in
this way. The mistake is of the same kind as if cows were defined as
cattle-merchants, but had never seen a cow, this might seem an admirable
would have to declare that they were not cows at all, because no
is. We count a set of objects when we let our attention pass from one to
another, until we have attended once to each, saying the names of the
numbers in order with each successive act of attention. The last number
202
named in this process is the number of the objects, and therefore
counting is a method of finding out what the number of the objects is.
But this operation is really a very complicated one, and those who
number of the objects counted unless we attach some meaning to the words
one, two, three, ... A child may learn to know these words in order, and
attaching any meaning to them. Such a child may count correctly from the
performed by a person who already has some idea what the numbers are;
and from this it follows that counting does not give the logical basis
of number.
Again, how do we know that the last number reached in the process of
counting is the number of the objects counted? This is just one of those
facts that are too familiar for their significance to be realised; but
those who wish to be logicians must acquire the habit of dwelling upon
such facts. There are two propositions involved in this fact: first,
that the number of numbers from 1 up to any given number is that given
objects, each number occurring only once, then the number of numbers
used as names is the same as the number of objects. The first of these
203
propositions is capable of an easy arithmetical proof so long as finite
numbers are concerned; but with infinite numbers, after the first, it
There are two respects in which the infinite numbers that are known
differ from finite numbers: first, infinite numbers have, while finite
properties successively.
objects, any finite number of objects can be added or taken away without
204
increasing or diminishing the number of the collection. Even an infinite
without altering the number. This may be made clearer by the help of
some examples.
in the top row has a number directly under it in the bottom row, and no
number occurs twice in either row. It follows that the number of numbers
in the two rows must be the same. But all the numbers that occur in the
bottom row also occur in the top row, and one more, namely 0; thus the
number of terms in the top row is obtained by adding one to the number
contradiction, and led to the denial that there are infinite numbers.
0, 1, 2, 3, ... n ...
1, 2, 3, 4, ... n + 1 ...
The following example is even more surprising. Write the natural numbers
the bottom row, so that under each number in the top row stands its
double in the bottom row. Then, as before, the number of numbers in the
two rows is the same, yet the second row results from taking away all
the odd numbers--an infinite collection--from the top row. This example
205
is given by Leibniz to prove that there can be no infinite numbers. He
to its double. Therefore the number of all numbers is not greater than
the number of even numbers, i.e. the whole is not greater than its
number of all finite numbers" for "the number of all numbers"; we then
obtain exactly the illustration given by our two rows, one containing
all the finite numbers, the other only the even finite numbers. It will
the whole is not greater than its part. But the word "greater" is one
it is the realisation of this fact which has made the modern theory of
infinity possible.
206
"Simp. Here already arises a Doubt which I think is not to be
resolv'd; and that is this: Since 'tis plain that one Line is given
greater than another, and since both contain infinite Points, we must
greater Line exceeds the Infinity of Points of the lesser. But now, to
conceive.
can't say that one is greater than, less than, or equal to another. For
Proof whereof I have something come into my Head, which (that I may be
"Simp. I know very well that a square Number is that which arises from
the Multiplication of any Number into itself; thus 4 and 9 are square
"Salv. Very well; And you also know, that as the Products are call'd
207
Squares, the Factors are call'd Roots: And that the other Numbers, which
proceed not from Numbers multiplied into themselves, are not Squares.
Whence taking in all Numbers, both Squares and Not Squares, if I should
say, that the Not Squares are more than the Squares, should I not be in
the right?
"Salv. If I go on with you then, and ask you, How many squar'd Numbers
there are? you may truly answer, That there are as many as are their
proper Roots, since every Square has its own Root, and every Root its
own Square, and since no Square has more than one Root, nor any Root
"Salv. But now, if I should ask how many Roots there are, you can't
deny but there are as many as there are Numbers, since there's no Number
but what's the Root to some Square. And this being granted, we may
likewise affirm, that there are as many square Numbers, as there are
Numbers; for there are as many Squares as there are Roots, and as many
Roots as Numbers. And yet in the Beginning of this, we said, there were
many more Numbers than Squares, the greater Part of Numbers being not
you'll find 10 Squares, viz. 1, 4, 9, 16, 25, 36, 49, 64, 81, 100, which
208
is the same as to say the 10th Part are Squares; in Ten thousand only
the 100th Part are Squares; in a Million only the 1000th: And yet in an
infinite Number, if we can but comprehend it, we may say the Squares are
"Salv. I see no other way, but by saying that all Numbers are
infinite; Squares are Infinite, their Roots Infinite, and that the
Number of Squares is not less than the Number of Numbers, nor this less
into English from the Italian, by Tho. Weston, late Master, and now
worthy of Galileo, but the solution suggested is not the right one. It
is actually the case that the number of square (finite) numbers is the
confine ourselves to numbers less than some given finite number, the
209
proportion of squares tends towards zero as the given finite number
increases, does not contradict the fact that the number of all finite
squares is the same as the number of all finite numbers. This is only an
same as its value when the variable actually reaches the given
point. But although the infinite numbers which Galileo discusses are
equal, Cantor has shown that what Simplicius could not conceive is true,
and that the conception of greater and less can be perfectly well
evident, from his belief that, if greater and less can be applied, a
part of an infinite collection must have fewer terms than the whole; and
and less lengths of lines, which is the problem from which the above
is not arithmetical. The number of points is the same in a long line and
in a short one, being in fact the same as the number of points in all
space. The greater and less of metrical geometry involves the new
infinity.
210
non-inductiveness. This will be best explained by defining the positive
induction."
being called Jones hereditary with respect to the relation of father and
son. If a man is called Jones, all his descendants in the direct male
line are called Jones; this follows from the fact that the property is
hereditary. Now, instead of the relation of father and son, consider the
to 101, and so on--where the "and so on" will take us, sooner or later,
to any finite number greater than 100. Thus, for example, the property
number that possesses the property, the next number must always also
possess it.
211
the finite numbers greater than a given number possessing the property,
need not belong to all the numbers less than this number. For example,
the hereditary property of being greater than 99 belongs to 100 and all
(in the direct male line) of those who have this property, but not to
all their ancestors, because we reach at last a first Jones, before whom
numbers have some property, that we have first to prove that 0 has the
the fact that such proofs are called "inductive," I shall call the
0.
Taking any one of the natural numbers, say 29, it is easy to see that it
must have all inductive properties. For since such properties belong to
such arguments we show that they belong to 29. We may define the
212
properties; they will be the same as what are called the "natural"
numbers, i.e. the ordinary finite whole numbers. To all such numbers,
additions of 1; in other words, they are all the numbers that can be
reached by counting.
But beyond all these numbers, there are the infinite numbers, and
the next are liable to fail when we come to infinite numbers. The first
to the next will ever reach from a finite number to an infinite one, and
the step-by-step method of proof fails. This is another reason for the
induction, and the strictly limited scope of this method of proof, the
supposed contradictions are seen to contradict, not logic, but only our
213
property of non-reflexiveness--may serve to illustrate the limitations
way that all numbers are increased by the addition of 1; we can only
of 1 starting from 0. The reflexive numbers, which lie beyond all those
addition of 1.
valid proof has been discovered. The infinite numbers actually known,
214
mathematical practice, if not in theory, the two properties are always
When infinite numbers are first introduced to people, they are apt to
must now turn to the logical basis of arithmetic, and consider the
definition of number was discovered about the same time by a man whose
Untersuchung über den Begriff der Zahl.[52] It is with this book that
215
consider Frege's analysis in some detail.
in the Grundgesetze der Arithmetik (vol. i., 1893; vol. ii., 1903),
from their predecessors, and points out that this must lead to a
This brings him to the question: What kind of object is it that number
can properly be ascribed to? He points out that physical things may be
count as one, not as a thousand; and one pair of boots is the same
object as two boots. It follows that physical things are not the
216
number is really something psychological and subjective, a view which
The botanist wishes to state something which is just as much a fact when
The one depends as little as the other upon our caprice. There is
therefore a certain similarity between number and colour; but this does
not consist in the fact that both are sensibly perceptible in external
things, but in the fact that both are objective" (p. 34).
spatial, the actual. The earth's axis, the centre of mass of the solar
system, are objective, but I should not call them actual, like the earth
mathematics and logic. Most philosophers have thought that the physical
and the mental between them exhausted the world of being. Some have
and therefore must be physical and empirical; others have argued that
they were obviously not physical, and therefore must be subjective and
mental. Both sides were right in what they denied, and wrong in what
they asserted; Frege has the merit of accepting both denials, and
217
The fact is, as Frege points out, that no number, not even 1, is
objects: there are in the world so and so many men. The unity which
is the unity of the general term, and it is the general term which is
the proper subject of number. And this applies equally when there is one
object or none which falls under the general term. "Satellite of the
earth" is a term only applicable to one object, namely, the moon. But
"one" is not a property of the moon itself, which may equally well be
number we have arrived so far at the result that numbers are properties
mental occurrences.
218
which are applicable to the same collection of objects, will obviously
have the same number of instances; thus the number depends upon the
class, not upon the selection of this or that general term to describe
it, provided several general terms can be found to describe the same
class. Even when the terms are enumerated, as "this and that and the
either this, or that, or the other, and only so acquires the unity which
Frege next asks the question: When do two collections have the same
illustration may help to make the method clear. I do not know how many
married men there are in England, but I do know that the number is the
same as the number of married women. The reason I know this is that the
relation of husband and wife relates one man to one woman and one woman
219
relation of father to son is called a one-many relation, because a man
can have only one father but may have many sons; conversely, the
because a man cannot have more than one wife, or a woman more than one
husband. Now, whenever there is a one-one relation between all the terms
of one collection and all the terms of another severally, as in the case
of English husbands and English wives, the number of terms in the one
collection is the same as the number in the other; but when there is not
We can now at last answer the question: What is meant by the number of
all the terms of one collection and all the terms of another severally,
we shall say that the two collections are "similar." We have just seen
that two similar collections have the same number of terms. This leads
220
applicable equally to finite and infinite numbers, and it does not
which other theories find in dealing with these two special cases.
the number 2, for instance, as the class of all couples, and the number
3 as the class of all triads. This does not seem to be what we have
In the second place, it may be admitted that the definition, like all
what we mean; but the method of such definitions would lack uniformity,
infinite numbers.
221
In the third place, the real desideratum about such a definition as that
ideas of those who have not gone through the analysis required in order
may be called numbers. So far, the simplest set known to fulfil this
with this merit, the question whether the objects to which the
classes--I mean the doctrine that there are no such objects as classes
theory which reduces numbers to classes, and of the many other theories
none of these theories are any the worse for the doctrine that classes
are fictions. What the doctrine is, and why it is not destructive, I
222
On account of certain rather complicated difficulties, culminating in
definite contradictions, I was led to the view that nothing that can be
substitute a class for the thing, you no longer have a sentence that has
fond of apples." But obviously you do not mean that there is one
individual, called "mankind," which munches apples: you mean that the
apples.
Now, if nothing that can be said significantly about a thing can be said
cannot have the same kind of reality as things have; for if they had, a
lived a Chinese philosopher named Hui Tzŭ, who maintained that "a bay
horse and a dun cow are three; because taken separately they are two,
and taken together they are one: two and one make three."[53] The author
from whom I quote says that Hui Tzŭ "was particularly fond of the
223
Greece," and this no doubt represents the judgment of common sense upon
would be irrefragable. It is only because the bay horse and the dun cow
taken together are not a new thing that we can escape the conclusion
p. 147.
When it is admitted that classes are not things, the question arises:
logic is not very numerous." Obviously this reduces itself to, "Not very
many." Then our statement is, "Not three people are interested in
224
which there is no longer any such use. The definition of such a method
that numbers are not actual entities, but that propositions in which
propositions having this form. This is in fact the case with all the
like "John" or "Jones," but are words which require a context in order
expressing them are not names, and cannot significantly be made into
their meanings, that are being discussed.[55] This fact has a very
important bearing on all logic and philosophy, since it shows how they
differ from the special sciences. But the questions raised are so large
occasion.
225
[55] In the above remarks I am making use of unpublished work by my
226
LECTURE VIII
guarantee for all the rest. These initial propositions are premisses
different from data--they are simpler, more precise, and less infected
philosophy; but the work of deducing the body of common knowledge from
But besides the logical analysis of the common knowledge which forms our
227
have arrived at its premisses, we may find that some of them seem open
to doubt, and we may find further that this doubt extends to those of
our original data which depend upon these doubtful premisses. In our
third lecture, for example, we saw that the part of physics which
depends upon testimony, and thus upon the existence of other minds than
our own, does not seem so certain as the part which depends exclusively
upon our own sense-data and the laws of logic. Similarly, it used to be
felt that the parts of geometry which depend upon the axiom of parallels
have less certainty than the parts which are independent of this
is not all equally certain, and that, when analysis into premisses has
premisses will depend upon that of the most doubtful premiss employed in
proving this consequence. Thus analysis into premisses serves not only a
philosophical analysis.
the problem of free will. For this purpose I shall inquire: I., what is
meant by a causal law; II., what is the evidence that causal laws have
held hitherto; III., what is the evidence that they will continue to
hold in the future; IV., how the causality which is used in science
228
differs from that of common sense and traditional philosophy; V., what
new light is thrown on the question of free will by our analysis of the
notion of "cause."
without having seen lightning, you infer that there nevertheless was a
"All marks in the ground shaped like a human foot are subsequent to a
human being's standing where the marks are." When we see the sun set, we
expect that it will rise again the next day. When we hear a man
(or event) from the existence of one or more others. The word "thing"
is directly verifiable, the thing inferred and the thing from which it
is inferred must both be data, though they need not both be data at the
same time. In fact, a causal law which is being used to extend our
229
knowledge of existence must be applied to what, at the moment, is not a
utility of a causal law consists. The important point, for our present
[56] Thus we are not using "thing" here in the sense of a class of
and capable of applying to many cases, the given particular from which
thunder. Thus a causal law must state that the existence of a thing of a
question.
230
It is to be observed that what is constant in a causal law is not the
object or objects given, nor yet the object inferred, both of which may
vary within wide limits, but the relation between what is given and
the discussion.
causal law, or may be only described in such general terms that many
whether the constant relation affirmed by the causal law is one which
only one term can have to the data, or one which many terms may have. If
many terms may have the relation in question, science will not be
satisfied until it has found some more stringent law, which will enable
Since all known things are in time, a causal law must take account of
thing inferred. When we hear thunder and infer that there was lightning,
the law states that the thing inferred is earlier than the thing given.
Conversely, when we see lightning and wait expectantly for the thunder,
231
the law states that the thing given is earlier than the thing inferred.
When we infer a man's thoughts from his words, the law states that the
must not be content with a vague earlier or later, but must state
how much earlier or how much later. That is to say, the time-relation
between the thing given and the thing inferred ought to be capable of
hour ago this man was alive; an hour hence he will be cold." Such a
statement involves two causal laws, one inferring from a datum something
which existed a quarter of an hour ago, the other inferring from the
Often a causal law involves not one datum, but many, which need not be
dates."
The things given will not, in practice, be things that only exist for an
instant, for such things, if there are any, can never be data. The
232
things given will each occupy some finite time. They may be not static
earlier lecture the sense in which a motion may be a datum, and need not
later than some or all of the data. It may equally well be earlier or at
the same time. The only thing essential is that the law should be such
II. I come now to our second question, namely: What is the nature of the
evidence that causal laws have held hitherto, at least in the observed
portions of the past? This question must not be confused with the
causal laws in the future and in unobserved portions of the past? For
the present, I am only asking what are the grounds which lead to a
belief in causal laws, not whether these grounds are adequate to support
received comes pain, after approaching a fire comes warmth; again, there
between certain sensations in the throat and the sound of one's own
233
after it has been experienced a certain number of times, is followed by
where one of the correlated events is found, the other will be found
Hume, who carried the discussion of cause up to this point, but did not,
case, we suppose that thunder might have been heard if we had been
embracing more circumstances, and subsuming both the successes and the
234
unless they are balloons or aeroplanes; but the principles of mechanics
supposed.
the past has proceeded according to invariable laws, what can we say as
to the nature of these laws? They will not be of the simple type which
asserts that the same cause always produces the same effect. We may take
states that the motions of planets and their satellites have at every
virtue of this law, given the state of the solar system throughout any
finite time, however short, its state at all earlier and later times is
235
determinate except in so far as other forces than gravitation or other
In the mental world, the evidence for the universality of causal laws is
less complete than in the physical world. Psychology cannot boast of any
evidence is not very greatly less than in the physical world. The crude
and approximate causal laws from which science starts are just as easy
sense, there are to begin with the correlations of sight and touch and
sensations with eyes, ears, nose, tongue, etc. Then there are such facts
as that our body moves in answer to our volitions. Exceptions exist, but
that unsupported bodies in air fall. There is, in fact, just such a
degree as will suffice to remove all doubt from the mind of a sceptical
inquirer. It should be observed that causal laws in which the given term
is mental and the inferred term physical, or vice versa, are at least
236
as easy to discover as causal laws in which both terms are mental.
not hitherto introduced the word "cause." At this stage, it will be well
to say a few words on legitimate and illegitimate uses of this word. The
and more invariable laws. We may say, "Arsenic causes death," so long as
about. But in a sufficiently advanced science, the word "cause" will not
rough and loose use of the word "cause" which may be preserved. The
turn out to be true in all but very rare and exceptional circumstances,
realised that the sequence is not necessary and may have exceptions, it
this sense, and in this sense only, that we shall intend the words when
III. We come now to our third question, namely: What reason can be given
for believing that causal laws will hold in future, or that they have
237
held in unobserved portions of the past?
What we have said so far is that there have been hitherto certain
observed causal laws, and that all the empirical evidence we possess is
compatible with the view that everything, both mental and physical, so
same or different times that, given the state of the whole universe
throughout any finite time, however short, every previous and subsequent
Have we any reason to believe this universal law? Or, to ask a more
future?
always along a certain road expects to be driven along that road again;
a dog who is always fed at a certain hour expects food at that hour and
not at any other. Such expectations, as Hume pointed out, explain only
238
afford absolutely no logical ground for beliefs as to the future, not
even for the belief that we shall continue to expect the continuation of
the last word, we have not only no reason to suppose that the sun will
fact invalid, and I do not see how such a view could be disproved. But,
admit it, we can infer that any characteristic of the whole of the
239
observed past is likely to apply to the future and to the unobserved
inference that causal laws probably hold at all times, future as well as
past; but without this principle, the observed cases of the truth of
validly inferred.
wanted for such inferences can be proved; without it, all such
inferences are invalid. This principle has not received the attention
deductive logic naturally enough ignored it, while those who emphasised
be known at all.
The view that the law of causality itself is a priori cannot, I think,
In the form which states that "every event has a cause" it looks simple;
240
necessarily be some a priori principle involved in inference from
valid; but it would appear from the above analysis that the principle in
future are valid depends wholly, if our discussion has been sound, upon
IV. I come now to the question how the conception of causal laws which
Historically, the notion of cause has been bound up with that of human
volition. The typical cause would be the fiat of a king. The cause is
prevision of the effect; hence the effect becomes the "end" at which the
that Mach and others have urged a purely "descriptive" view of physics:
physics, they say, does not aim at telling us "why" things happen, but
only "how" they happen. And if the question "why?" means anything more
241
descriptive view is indubitably in the right. But in using causal laws
memory and hope make a difference in our feelings as regards past and
future, but almost our whole vocabulary is filled with the idea of
activity, of things done now for the sake of their future effects. All
transitive verbs involve the notion of cause as activity, and would have
eliminated.
occasion, Brutus and Cæsar might engage our attention, but for the
present it is the killing that we have to study. We may say that to kill
a person is to cause his death intentionally. This means that desire for
act will cause the person's death; or more accurately, the desire and
the belief jointly cause the act. Brutus desires that Cæsar should be
242
dead, and believes that he will be dead if he is stabbed; Brutus
therefore stabs him, and the stab causes Cæsar's death, as Brutus
purpose is achieved) that B will cause C; the desire and the belief
a desire for C and a belief that B (an act) will cause C; then we have
Brutus, the desire, which comes at the beginning, is what makes the
occurred. This is true, and gives him a sense of power and freedom. It
is equally true that if the effects had not occurred, his desires would
have been different, since being what they were the effects did occur.
243
cause is an event or group of events, of some known general character,
and having a known relation to some other event, called the effect; the
relation being of such a kind that only one event, or at any rate only
one well-defined sort of event, can have the relation to a given cause.
later than the cause, but there is no kind of reason for this
that the cause can hardly stop short of the whole universe. So long as
anything is left out, something may be left out which alters the
event--we say the lightning causes the thunder, and so on. But it is
cause than unscientific common sense would suppose. But often a probable
244
philosophers advocate is an ideal, possibly true, but not known to be
times, and that when such relations fail, as they sometimes do, it is
the group. Any such constant relation between events of specified kinds
with given intervals of time between them is a "causal law." But all
causal laws are liable to exceptions, if the cause is less than the
are much more numerous) is between a bodily act and the realisation of
the purpose which led to the act. These connections are patent, whereas
causal series with desires, to suppose that all causes are analogous to
however, is not one which any serious psychologist would maintain. But
245
V. The problem of free will is so intimately bound up with the analysis
profoundly, and the fear that the will might not be free has been to
free will do not flow from this denial in any form in which there is
free will. Some of our reasons for desiring free will are profound, some
the hands of fate, so that, however much we may desire to will one
another. We do not wish to think that, however much we may desire to act
well, heredity and surroundings may force us into acting ill. We wish to
feel that, in cases of doubt, our choice is momentous and lies within
our power. Besides these desires, which are worthy of all respect, we
246
free will. We do not like to think that other people, if they knew
enough, could predict our actions, though we know that we can often
we esteem the old gentleman who is our neighbour in the country, we know
that when grouse are mentioned he will tell the story of the grouse in
enjoy it; although we once met (say) Bismarck, we are quite capable of
hearing him mentioned without relating the occasion when we met him. In
this sense, everybody thinks that he himself has free will, though he
knows that no one else has. The desire for this kind of free will seems
can be gratified with any certainty; but the other, more respectable
determinism.
as I shall try to show, are entirely distinct, and we may answer the
247
relation between an act and a certain number of earlier events, such
that, when the earlier events are given, only one act, or at most only
acts with some well-marked character, can have this relation to the
earlier events? If this is the case, then, as soon as the earlier events
relation.
mental event, embodies so much of the past that it could not possibly
different from all previous and subsequent events. If, for example, I
same cause, if repeated, will produce the same effect. But owing to
fact of repetition, and cannot produce the same effect. He infers that
every mental event is a genuine novelty, not predictable from the past,
imagine it. And on this ground he regards the freedom of the will as
unassailable.
248
Bergson's contention has undoubtedly a great deal of truth, and I have
no wish to deny its importance. But I do not think its consequences are
the act which will be performed. If he could foresee that A was going to
could not know all the infinite complexity of A's state of mind in
committing the murder, nor whether the murder was to be performed with a
that there are fine shades which cannot be foreseen. No doubt every time
the story of the grouse in the gun-room is told, there will be slight
the prediction that the story will be told. And there is nothing in
Bergson's argument to show that we can never predict what kind of act
will be performed.
Again, his statement of the law of causation is inadequate. The law does
not state merely that, if the same cause is repeated, the same
the height through which it falls and the time it takes in falling. It
is not necessary to have a body fall through the same height which has
249
possible, since it would be impossible to make the height exactly the
same on two occasions. Similarly, the attraction which the sun will
exert on the earth is not only known at distances for which it has been
always the relation of cause and effect, not the cause itself; all
kind (in the relevant respect) as earlier causes whose effects have
been observed.
is in its assumption that the cause must be one event, whereas it may
our feelings in reading the poem are most emphatically dependent upon
the past, but not upon one single event in the past. All our previous
tacitly assumes such a law. We decide at last not to read the poem
again, because we know that this time the effect would be boredom. We
may not know all the niceties and shades of the boredom we should feel,
but we know enough to guide our decision, and the prophecy of boredom is
none the less true for being more or less general. Thus the kinds of
250
impossibility of prediction in the only sense in which prediction has
directly.
the law has been verified empirically, and in other directions there is
no positive evidence against it. But science can use it where it has
The question how far human volitions are subject to causal laws is a
purely empirical one. Empirically it seems plain that the great majority
necessarily certain that all have causes. There are, however, precisely
the same kinds of reasons for regarding it as probable that they all
the state of all the matter in the world, and therefore of all the
brains and living organisms, the state of all the minds in the world
251
could be inferred, while conversely the state of all the matter in the
world could be inferred if the state of all the minds were given. It is
mind, and it is impossible to say how complete it may be. This, however,
is not the point which I wish to elicit. What I wish to urge is that,
is worth preserving in free will do not follow. The belief that they
volitions, and from the notion that causes compel their effects in
some sense analogous to that in which a human authority can compel a man
mistake. But this brings us to the second of the two questions which we
forces.
against the view that volitions have causes. This sense of freedom,
between what we please to choose and our previous history. The supposed
252
those who intend to conceive causes in a more scientific manner. If a
alien will, and acts predictable from outside causes will be subject to
that either can be inferred from the other. When the geologist infers
the past state of the earth from its present state, we should not say
that the present state compels the past state to have been what it
only sense in which effects are rendered necessary by their causes. The
is a mere confusion due to the fact that we remember past events but do
ignorance; for if that were the case, animals would be more free than
men, and savages than civilised people. Free will in any valuable sense
must be compatible with the fullest knowledge. Now, quite apart from any
embrace the future as well as the past. Our knowledge of the past is not
wholly based upon causal inferences, but is partly derived from memory.
253
way in which we see past events. They certainly will be what they will
be, and are in this sense just as determined as the past. If we saw
future events in the same immediate way in which we see past events,
what kind of free will would still be possible? Such a kind would be
most entirely universal reign of causality. And such a kind must contain
that mere ignorance can be the essential condition of any good thing.
Let us therefore imagine a set of beings who know the whole future with
absolute certainty, and let us ask ourselves whether they could have
Such beings as we are imagining would not have to wait for the event in
order to know what decision they were going to adopt on some future
occasion. They would know now what their volitions were going to be. But
would they have any reason to regret this knowledge? Surely not, unless
suppose that what is foreseen is fated, and must happen however much it
may be dreaded. But human actions are the outcome of desire, and no
volition will have to be one which does not become odious through being
foreseen. The beings we are imagining would easily come to know the
254
volitions are the outcome of desires, a prevision of volitions contrary
supposed prevision would not create the future any more than memory
creates the past. We do not think we were necessarily not free in the
past, merely because we can now remember our past volitions. Similarly,
we might be free in the future, even if we could now see what our future
demands only that our volitions shall be, as they are, the result of our
power in regard to the past. Free will, therefore, is true in the only
form which is important; and the desire for other forms is a mere effect
of insufficient analysis.
* * * * *
What has been said on philosophical method in the foregoing lectures has
through examples; but now, at the end of our course, we may collect
philosophic problems.
255
Philosophy does not become scientific by making use of other sciences,
aims at what is general, and the special sciences, however they may
theory. Philosophy is a study apart from the other sciences: its results
to the future of the universe, for example, are not the business of
to survive through years when there seems no hope of its finding any
presents itself, and by turning our attention away from the objections
the wish for comfort, we should have come to see that the opinion was
256
professional philosophers, by love of system: the one little fact which
will not come inside the philosopher's edifice has to be pushed and
tortured until it seems to consent. Yet the one little fact is more
likely to be important for the future than the system with which it is
a square and the side; this one little fact stood out, and remained a
fact even after Hippasos of Metapontion was drowned for revealing it. To
which becomes associated with it, are among the snares that the student
evidence for agreeable results, of whatever kind, has of course been the
agreeable result than to wish to arrive at a true result. But only those
257
serve any good purpose by the study of philosophy.
But even when the desire to know exists in the requisite strength, the
at command, and not to be the slave of the one which common sense has
and imagining the unfamiliar, are correlative, and form the chief part
The naïve beliefs which we find in ourselves when we first begin the
all capable of a true interpretation; but they ought all, before being
Until they have gone through this ordeal, they are mere blind habits,
may be that a majority will pass the test, we may be pretty sure that
some will not, and that a serious readjustment of our outlook ought to
258
At the same time, and as an essential aid to the direct perception of
hypotheses. This is, I think, what has most of all been lacking hitherto
the facts. Too often this state of things led to the adoption of heroic
better stocked with logical tools would have found a key to unlock the
mystery. It is in this way that the study of logic becomes the central
which bodies fall, not very interesting on their own account, but of
method whose future fruitfulness he himself divined. But his few facts
259
sufficed to destroy the whole vast system of supposed knowledge handed
system, and others another, almost all have been of opinion that a great
deal was known; but all this supposed knowledge in the traditional
systems must be swept away, and a new beginning must be made, which we
suffered from the lack of this kind of modesty. It has made the mistake
which, judged alone, might seem frivolous, for it is often only through
approached.
When our problem has been selected, and the necessary mental discipline
has been acquired, the method to be pursued is fairly uniform. The big
260
problems which provoke philosophical inquiry are found, on examination,
usually more abstract than those of which they are the components. It
will generally be found that all our initial data, all the facts that we
general and as free from complexity as possible, before the data can be
tracked further and further back, growing at each stage more abstract,
the big obvious problems. When everything has been done that can be done
carry matters further. Here only genius will avail. What is wanted, as a
possibility never conceived before, and then the direct perception that
arguments pro and con, utter bewilderment and despair. But the right
261
Of the prospect of progress in philosophy, it would be rash to speak
prodigal of promises. But to the large and still growing body of men
appeal which the older methods have wholly failed to make. Physics, with
the nature of matter, is feeling the need for that kind of novelty in
unhampered by the traditions of the past, and not misled by the literary
methods of those who copy the ancients in all except their merits.
262