THeories
THeories
THeories
This new interventionism, or willingness to use force in the name of humanitarian values, played a major role in
shaping international relations during the 1990s. As a result of actions such as that undertaken by NATO in response
to the Kosovo crisis, or the authorisation of
the use of force in East Timor by the Security Council, issues about the
legality and morality of humanitarian intervention again began to dominate the international legal and political
agenda. One of the most significant changes in international politics to emerge during that period
was the growth of support, within mainstream international law and
international relations circles, for the idea that force can legitimately
be used as a response to humanitarian challenges such as those facing
the people of East Timor. The justifications for these actions are illustrative of the transformation undergone by the
narratives that underpin
the discipline of international law with the ending of the Cold War.1
A new kind of international law and internationalist spirit seemed to
have been made possible in the changed conditions of a world no longer
structured around the old certainties of a struggle between communism
and capitalism.
Many
legal scholars working in the areas of human rights and international
humanitarian law were highly critical of the actions undertaken in the
Gulf. Criticisms ranged from analyses of the merely rhetorical nature of
the Security Council’s commitment to human rights, to criticism of the
effects of the bombing and sanctions on the Iraqi people, to concern
about the apparent domination of the revitalised Council by the United States.11 The response to later interventions,
however, has been more
ambivalent. There are certainly some legal commentators who have continued to express concern about the apparent
willingness of a largely
unrestrained Security Council to expand its mandate to include authorising the use of force to remedy human rights
abuses or ‘to make every
State a democratic one’.12 Many legal scholars, however, seem haunted by
the fear that opposing military intervention in Bosnia, Haiti, Kosovo or
East Timor means opposing the only realistic possibility of international
engagement to end the horrific human suffering witnessed in such conflicts. The need to halt the horrors of genocide
or to address the effects
of civil war and internal armed conflict on civilians has been accepted
as sufficient justification for intervention, even if other motives may be
involved.
Page 19
The most significant change in the human rights movement as it goes into the
twenty-first century is that it will go on the offensive. The past has been a matter
of pleading with tyrants, writing letters and sending missions to beg them not
to act cruelly. That will not be necessary if there is a possibility that they can be
deterred, by threats of humanitarian or UN intervention or with nemesis in the
form of the International Criminal Court. Human rights discourse will in the
future be less pious and less ‘politically correct’. We will call a savage a savage,
whether or not he or she is black.17
Thus Robertson has no doubt that the new right of humanitarian intervention, represented by NATO’s action in
Kosovo and the multilateral
intervention in East Timor, is to be welcomed because it allows for more
effective enforcement of human rights. The human rights movement
will no longer be reduced to humiliating acts of begging and pleading
with tyrants. Lawyers can now take a more active and forceful role in
promoting and protecting human rights globally, offering salvation to
those threatened by state-sponsored murder and genocide.
For Robertson, the test of whether such intervention is justified should
not be whether it is lawful, or authorised by the Security Council, but
rather ‘the dimension of the evil’ to be addressed by the intervention.18
The extent of this evil can partly be ascertained through global media,
where ‘television pictures of corpses in Racak, Kosovo, put such obscure Thus Robertson has no doubt that the new
right of humanitarian intervention, represented by NATO’s action in Kosovo and the multilateral
intervention in East Timor, is to be welcomed because it allows for more
effective enforcement of human rights. The human rights movement
will no longer be reduced to humiliating acts of begging and pleading
with tyrants. Lawyers can now take a more active and forceful role in
promoting and protecting human rights globally, offering salvation to
those threatened by state-sponsored murder and genocide.
For Robertson, the test of whether such intervention is justified should
not be whether it is lawful, or authorised by the Security Council, but
rather ‘the dimension of the evil’ to be addressed by the intervention.18
The extent of this evil can partly be ascertained through global media,
where ‘television pictures of corpses in Racak, Kosovo, put such obscure.
British Prime Minister Tony Blair portrayed the NATO intervention in Kosovo as a ‘just war, based not on territorial
ambitions, but on values’.26 According to Blair,
British foreign policy decisions in the post-Cold War era ‘are guided by
a . . . subtle blend of mutual self-interest and moral purpose in defending the values we cherish . . . If we can
establish and spread the values
of liberty, the rule of law, human rights and an open society, then that
is in our national interest.’27 The war in Kosovo was fought precisely to
defend such values:
This war was not fought for Albanians against Serbs. It was not fought for territory. Still less for NATO aggrandisement. It was
fought for a fundamental principle necessary for humanity’s progress: that every human being, regardless of
race, religion or birth, has the inalienable right to live free from persecution. 28
the representation
of the interventions in Bosnia and Kosovo as the actions of an international community interested in protecting
human rights and humanitarian values served to obscure the extent to which the international
community had itself contributed to the humanitarian crises that had
emerged in those places.42 While ancient hatreds and ethnic tensions
continue to be represented as the cause of the violence that erupted in
the former Yugoslavia, critics have suggested that the crisis was equally
a product of modern capitalist international relations.43 In the former
Yugoslavia as elsewhere, the project of economic restructuring and liberalisation which remains central to the new
world order contributed
to creating the conditions in which such hatreds were inflamed.44 For
these and other reasons, I had argued that the desire to use violence
and to take ‘action’ by sending armed forces to create security had to
be interrogated. As Edward Said has shown, the belief that ‘certain territories and people require and beseech
domination’ was at the heart of
making colonialism palatable.45 Given that it was so difficult for people to stand back from the culture that produced
and legitimised imperialism, it seemed necessary to be cautious about any arguments that made
the use of force appear benevolent to us today.
Proportionality
proportionality plays a
much more central part in that legal regime. For example, in the 1990--1
Persian Gulf conflict and the 1999 NATO action in Kosovo, proportionality in IHL has been relied on in many
contexts where there have been
differences as to the legality of actions of the attacking forces. 8 A further factor that contributes to the resistance to
proportionality in ius ad bellum is that its constraints are equally applicable to all parties irrespective of the legality
or perceived ‘justness’ of a party’s
resort to force. This requirement of equality of application is also a
characteristic of IHL and has been problematic in that regime over
the years. As the campaign progressed, it grew in intensity. However, it was not a campaign
against the Serbian people. It focused specifically on the forces of repression from
top to bottom to coerce a change in their behaviour or, failing that, to degrade
and ultimately destroy their means of repression. Allied planners, targeters and
pilots worked diligently to prevent injuries and loss of life among the civilian
population and to prevent collateral damage. 90
Moreover, in practice it is a more straightforward task to determine what
are the relevant rules of IHL and when they apply. The requirements
of IHL apply on the objective fact of the existence of a certain level
of armed conflict. The legality of the respective parties’ resort to force,
although it may subtly affect the implementation of IHL, is not a relevant
consideration for the regime to come into operation.
In the case of Kosovo, for example, the legitimate aim of the forceful action by NATO was to bring an end to the
human rights abuses against the Kosovars.96 Were the means employed,
however, proportionate to achieve this end? ere the means employed,
however, proportionate to achieve this end? It is debatable as to whether
a campaign of high-altitude aerial bombardment dictated by the policy
of zero casualties for the attacking force was in fact more likely to exacerbate the humanitarian problem (as indeed
appears in hindsight to be
the case) than to achieve the ends. Although it is true to say that there will be a theoretical divide
between States involved in an armed conflict in terms of their respective
legal position under the Charter ban on the use of force, its practical
impact is negligible. With some notable exceptions, States invariably
conduct themselves on the basis that, whatever the legal status of their
forceful actions, be it self-defence or what may be perceived by others as
unlawful aggression, proportionality and necessity govern their actions.
Even States that claim expansive rights to resort to force do not regard
themselves as having the right to use unlimited force.
At the end of the day it is probably as much the mere existence of
two differing rules of proportionality that operate simultaneously and
in relation to the same activity that is responsible for the marginal
attention accorded to the requirements in ius ad bellum. The dominant
position of the rule in IHL, moreover, owes much to the fact that the angible human cost of a disproportionate action
under IHL is readily
demonstrable.
o what extent, therefore, does practice in the two Persian Gulf and
the Kosovo conflicts indicate that, even if there is no negligence in the
assessment of the target or in the conduct of the attack, the likelihood
and level of civilian casualties and damage to civilian objects must still
be considered? Even if care were taken to ensure the selection of means
and methods of attack that minimised the risk to civilians and civilian
objects, were attacks avoided or cancelled if the level of civilian casualties and damage to civilian objects appeared
unacceptable? In other
words, does the practice in these conflicts confirm that proportionality
operates in this broad sense in customary law?
YES. However, what requires clarification is exactly what this State practice
indicates as to the detailed operation of the rule for both members and
non-members of the Protocol and in what respects the requirements
of the norm remain obscure. This clarification is not always readily
obtained, as although the relevance of proportionality was acknowledged in all these conflicts, there is little detailed
information as to
exactly how it was applied.