Fodor's Guide On Mental Representation
Fodor's Guide On Mental Representation
Fodor's Guide On Mental Representation
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/2254700?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Mind Association, Oxford University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to Mind
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation:
The Intelligent Auntie's Vade-Mecum
J. A. FODOR
It rained for weeks and we were all so tired of ontology, but there didn't
seem to be much else to do. Some of the children started to sulk and pull the
cat's tail. It was going to be an awful afternoon until Uncle Wilifred thought
of Mental Representations (which was a game that we hadn't played for
years) and everybody got very excited and we jumped up and down and
waved our hands and all talked at once and had a perfectly lovely romp. But
Auntie said that she couldn't stand the noise and there would be tears before
bedtime if we didn't please calm down.
Auntie rather disapproves of what is going on in the Playroom, and you
can't entirely blame her. Ten or fifteen years of philosophical discussion of
mental representation has produced a considerable appearance of disorder.
Every conceivable position seems to have been occupied, along with some
whose conceivability it is permissible to doubt. And every view that anyone
has mooted someone else has undertaken to refute. This does not strike
Auntie as constructive play. She sighs for the days when well-brought-up
philosophers of mind kept themselves occupied for hours on end analysing
their behavioural dispositions.
But the chaotic appearances are actually misleading. A rather surprising
amount of agreement has emerged, if not about who's winning, at least
about how the game has to be played. In fact, everybody involved concurs,
pretty much, on what the options are. They differ in their hunches about
which of the options it would be profitable to exercise. The resulting noise is
of these intuitions clashing. In this paper, I want to make as much of the
consensus as I can explicit; both by way of reassuring Auntie and in order to
provide new participants with a quick guide to the game: Who's where and
how did they get there? Since it's very nearly true that you can locate all the
players by their answers to quite a small number of diagnostic questions, I
shall organize the discussion along those lines. What follows is a short
projective test of the sort that self-absorbed persons use to reveal their
hitherto unrecognized proclivities. I hope for a great success in California.
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 77
First philosophical gloss: When the ordinary chap says that he's doing what
he is because he has the beliefs and desires that he does, it is reasonable to
read the 'because' as a causal 'because'-whatever, exactly, a causal
'because' may be. At a minimum, common sense seems to require belief/
desire explanations to support counterfactuals in ways that are familiar in
causal explanation at large: if, for example, it is true that Psmith did A
because he believed B and desired C, then it must be that Psmith would not
have done A if either he had not believed B or he had not desired C. (Ceteris
paribus, it goes without saying.) Common sense also probably takes it that if
Psmith did A because he believed B and desired C, then-ceteris paribus
again-believing B and desiring C is causally sufficient for doing A.
(However, common sense does get confused about this since-though
believing B and desiring C was what caused Psmith to do A-still it is
common sense that Psmith could have believed B and desired C and not
done A had he so decided. It is a question of some interest whether common
sense can have it both ways.) Anyhow, to a first approximation the common-
sense view is that there is mental causation, and that mental causes are
subsumed by counterfactual-supporting generalizations of which the
practical syllogism is perhaps the paradigm.
Closely connected is the following: Everyman's view seems to be that
propositional attitudes cause (not only behaviour but also) other proposi-
tional attitudes. Thoughts cause desires (so that thinking about visiting
Auntie makes one want to) and-perhaps a little more tendentiously-the
other way around as well (so that the wish is often father to the thought,
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
78 J. A. Fodor
Second philosophical gloss: Common sense has it that beliefs and desires are
semantically evaluable; that they have satisfaction-conditions. Roughly, the
satisfaction-condition for a belief is the state of affairs in virtue of which that
belief is true or false and the satisfaction-condition for a desire is the state of
affairs in virtue of which that desire is fulfilled or frustrated. Thus, that it
continues to rain makes true the belief that it is raining and frustrates the
desire that the rain should stop. This could stand a lot more sharpening, but
it will do for the purposes at hand.
It will have occurred to the reader that there are other ways of glossing
common-sense belief/desire psychology. And that, even if this way of
glossing it is right, common-sense belief/desire psychology may be in need
of emendation. Or cancellation. Quite so, but my purpose isn't to defend or
criticize; I just want to establish a point of reference. I propose to say that
someone is a Realist about propositional attitudes iff (a) he holds that there
are mental states whose occurrences and interactions cause behaviour and
do so, moreover, in ways that respect (at least to an approximation) the
generalizations of common-sense belief/desire psychology; and (b) he holds
that these same causally efficacious mental states are also semantically
evaluable.
So much for common-sense psychological explanation. The connection
with our topic is this: the full-blown Representational Theory of Mind
(hereinafter RTM, about which a great deal presently) purports to explain
how there could be states that have the semantical and causal properties that
propositional attitudes are commonsensically supposed to have. In effect,
RTM proposes an account of what the propositional attitudes are. So, the
further you are from Realism about propositional attitudes, the dimmer the
view of RTM that you are likely to take.
Quite a lot of the philosophical discussion that's relevant to RTM, there-
fore, concerns the status and prospects of common-sense intentional
psychology. More, perhaps, than is generally realized. For example, we'll
see presently that some of the philosophical worries about RTM derive from
scepticism about the semantical properties of mental representations.
Putnam, in particular, has been explicit in questioning whether coherent
sense could be made of such properties. (See Putnam, MH; Putnam,
CPIT.) I have my doubts about the seriousness of these worries (see
Fodor, BD); but the present point is that they are, in any event, misdirected
as arguments against RTM. If there is something wrong with meaning,
what that shows is something very radical, viz. that there is something wrong
with propositional attitudes (a moral, by the way, that Quine, Davidson, and
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 79
Stich, among others, have drawn explicitly). That, and not RTM, is surely
the ground on which this action should be fought.
If, in short, you think that common sense is just plain wrong about the
aetiology of behaviour-i.e. that there is nothing that has the causal and
semantic properties that common sense attributes to the attitudes-then the
questions that RTM purports to answer don't so much as arise for you. You
won't care much what the attitudes are if you take the view that there aren't
any. Many philosophers do take this view and are thus united in their
indifference to RTM. Among these Anti-Realists there are, however,
interesting differences in motivation and tone of voice. Here, then, are some
ways of not being a Realist about beliefs and desires.
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
8o J. A. Fodor
Second Anti-Realist option: You could take the view that belief/desire
psychology is just plain false and skip the instrumentalist trimmings. On
this way of telling the Anti-Realist story, belief/desire psychology is in
competition with alternative accounts of the aetiology of behaviour and
should be judged in the same way that the alternatives are; by its predictive
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 8I
no yes
Instrumentalist?
no yes (Dennett)
Functionalist?
we are here-*
no yes
Figure I
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
82 J. A. Fodor
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 83
I Unless you are an eliminativist behaviourist (say Watson) which puts you, for present purposes,
beyond the pale.
While we're at it: it rather messes up my nice taxonomy that there are philosophers who accept a
Functionalist view of psychological explanation, and are Realist about belief/desire psychology, but who
reject the reduction of the latter to the former. In particular, they do not accept the identification of any
of the entities that Functionalist psychologists posit with the propositional attitudes that common sense
holds dear. (A version of this view says that functional states 'realize' propositional attitudes in much the
way that the physical states are supposed to realize functional ones. See, for example Matthews, TR.)
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
84 5. A. Fodor
no yes
Instrumentalist? Functionalist?
: ~~~~~no (Searle)
no yes (Dennett)
This may strike you as a silly question. For, you may say, since propositional
attitudes are by definition relations to propositions, it follows that
propositional attitudes are by definition not monadic. A propositional
attitude is, to a first approximation, a pair of a proposition and a set of
intentional systems, viz. the set of intentional systems which bear that
attitude to that proposition.
That would seem to be reasonable enough. But the current ('Naturalistic')
consensus is that if you've gone this far you will have to go further. Some-
thing has to be said about the place of the semantic and the intentional in the
natural order; it won't do to have unexplicated 'relations to propositions' at
the foundations of the philosophy of mind.
Just why it won't do-precisely what physicalist or Naturalist scruples it
would outrage-is, to be sure, not very clear. Presumably the issue isn't
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 85
Nominalism, for why raise that issue here; if physicists have numbers to play
with, why shouldn't psychologists have propositions? And it can't be worries
about individuation since distinguishing propositions is surely no harder
than distinguishing propositional attitudes and, for better or worse, we're
committed to the latter on this side of the decision tree. A more plausible
scruple-one I am inclined to take seriously-objects to unreduced epistemic
relations like grasping propositions. One really doesn't want psychology to
presuppose any of those; first because epistemic relations are pre-eminently
what psychology is supposed to explain, and second for fear of 'ontological
danglers'. It's not that there aren't propositions, and it's not that there aren't
graspings of them; it's rather that graspings of propositions aren't plausible
candidates for ultimate stuff. If they're real, they must be really something
else.
Anyhow, one might as well sing the songs one knows. There is a reductive
story to tell about what it is for an attitude to have a proposition as its object.
So, metaphysical issues to one side, why not tell it?
The story goes as follows. Propositional attitudes are monadic, functional
states of organisms. Functional states, you will recall, are type-individuated
by reference to their (actual and potential) causal relations; you know
everything that is essential about a functional state when you know which
causal generalizations subsume it. Since, in the psychological case, the
generalizations that count for type individuation are the ones that relate
mental states to one another, a census of mental states would imply a net-
work of causal interrelations. To specify such a network would be to con-
strain the nomologically possible mental histories of an organism; the
network for a given organism would exhibit the possible patterns of causal
interaction among its mental states (insofar, at least, as such patterns of
interaction are relevant to the type individuation of the states). Of necessity,
the actual mental life of the organism would appear as a path through this
network.
Given the Functionalist assurance of individuation by causal role, we can
assume that each mental state can be identified with a node in such a net-
work: for each mental state there is a corresponding causal role and for each
causal role there is a corresponding node. (To put the same point slightly
differently, each mental state can be associated with a formula (e.g. a Ramsey
sentence; see Block, op. cit.) which uniquely determines its location in the
network by specifying its potentialities for causal interaction with each of
the other mental states.) Notice, however, that while this gives a Func-
tionalist sense to the individuation of propositional attitudes, it does not, in
and of itself, say what it is for a propositional attitude to have the proposi-
tional content that it has. The present proposal is to remedy this defect by
reducing the notion of propositional content to the notion of causal role.
So far, we have a network of mental states defined by their causal inter-
relations. But notice that there is also a network generated by the inferential
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
86 3. A. Fodor
relations that hold among propositions; and it is plausible that its inferential
relations are among the properties that each proposition has essentially.
Thus, it is presumably a non-contingent property of the proposition that
Auntie is shorter than Uncle Wilifred that it entails the proposition that
Uncle Wilifred is taller than Auntie. And it is surely a non-contingent
property of the proposition that P & Qthat it entails the proposition that P
and the proposition that Q It may also be that there are evidential relations
that are, in the relevant sense, non-contingent; for example, it may be con-
stitutive of the proposition that many of the G's are F that it is, ceteris
paribus, evidence for the proposition that all of the G's are F. If it be so, then
so be it.
The basic idea is that, given the two networks-the causal and the in-
ferential-we can establish partial isomorphisms between them. Under
such an isomorphism, the causal role of a propositional attitude mirrors the
semantic role of the proposition that is its object. So, for example, there is the
proposition that John left and Mary wept; and it is partially constitutive of
this proposition that it has the following 'semantic' relations: it entails the
proposition that John left; it entails the proposition that Mary wept; it is
entailed by the pair of propositions {John left, Mary wept}; it entails the
proposition that somebody did something; it entails the proposition that
John did something; it entails the proposition that either it's raining or John
left and Mary wept ... and so forth. Likewise there are, among the potential
episodes in an organism's mental life, states which we may wish to construe
as: (S1) having the belief that John left and Mary wept; (S2) having the belief
that John left; (S3) having the belief that Mary wept; (S4) having the belief
that somebody did something; (S5) having the belief that either it's raining
or John left and Mary wept . . . and so forth. The crucial point is that it
constrains the assignment of propositional contents to these mental states
that the latter exhibit an appropriate pattern of causal relations. In
particular, it must be true (if only under idealization) that being in S1 tends
to cause the organism to be in S2 and S ; that being in S 1 tends to cause the
organism to be in S4 that being (simultaneously) in states (S2, S3) tends-
very strongly, one supposes-to cause the organism to be in state S1, that
being in state S1 tends to cause the organism to be in state S 5 (as does being
in state S6, viz. the state of believing that it's raining). And so forth.
In short, we can make non-arbitrary assignments of propositions as the
objects of propositional attitudes because there is this isomorphism between
the network generated by the semantic relations among propositions and the
network generated by the causal relations among mental states. The assign-
ment is non-arbitrary precisely in that it is constrained to preserve the
isomorphism. And because the isomorphism is perfectly objective (which is
not, however, to say that it is perfectly unique; see below), knowing what
proposition gets assigned to a mental state-what the object of an attitude
is-is knowing something useful. For, within the limits of the operative
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 87
idealization, you can deduce the causal consequences of being in a mental state
from the semantic relations of its propositional object. To know that John
thinks that Mary wept is to know that it's highly probable that he thinks that
somebody wept. To know that Sam thinks that it is raining is to know that
it's highly probable that he thinks that either it is raining or that John left
and Mary wept. To know that Sam thinks that it's raining and that Sam
thinks that if it's raining it is well to carry an umbrella is to be far along the
way to predicting a piece of Sam's behaviour.
It may be, according to the present story, that preserving isomorphism
between the causal and the semantic networks is all that there is to the
assignment of contents to mental states; that nothing constrains the attribu-
tion of propositional objects to propositional attitudes except the require-
ment that isomorphism be preserved. But one need not hold that that is so.
On the contrary, many-perhaps most-philosophers who like the iso-
morphism story are attracted by so-called 'two-factor' theories, according to
which what determines the semantics of an attitude is not just its functional
role but also its causal connections to objects 'in the world'. (This is, notice,
still a species of Functionalism since it's still causal role alone that counts for
the type individuation of mental states; but two-factor theories acknowledge
as semantically relevant 'external' causal relations, relations between, for
example, states of the organism and distal stimuli. It is these mind-to-world
causal relations that are supposed to determine the denotational semantics
of an attitude: what it's about and what its truth-conditions are.) There are
serious issues in this area, but for our purposes-we are, after all, just sight-
seeing-we can group the two-factor theorists with the pure functional-role
semanticists.
The story I've just told you is, I think, the standard current construal of
Realism about propositional attitudes.2 I propose, therefore, to call it
'Standard Realism' ('SR' for convenience). As must be apparent, SR is a
compound of two doctrines: a claim about the 'internal' structure of atti-
tudes (viz. that they are monadic functional states) and a claim about the
source of their semantical properties (viz. that some or all of such properties
arise from isomorphisms between the causal role of mental states and the
implicational structure of propositions). Now, though they are usually held
together, it seems clear that these claims are orthogonal. One could opt for
monadic mental states without functional-role semantics; or one could opt
for functional-role semantics together with some non-monadic account of
the polyadicity of the attitudes. My own view is that SR should be rejected
wholesale: that it is wrong about both the structure and the semantics of the
attitudes. But-such is the confusion and perversity of my colleagues-this
view is widely thought to be eccentric. The standard Realistic alternative to
2 This account of the attitudes seems to be in the air these days; and, as with most doctrines that are in
the air, it's a little hard to be sure exactly who holds it. Far the most detailed version is in Loar, MM;
though I have seen variants in unpublished papers by Tyler Burge, Robert Stalnaker, and Hartry Field.
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
88 J. A. Fodor
no yes
Functionalist?
no (Searle)? yes
attitudes monadic?
we are here -*
no(=RTM) yes
FR Semantics? FR Semantics?
:no yes
no yes
(Fodor) (Harman) (Loar)
(Block) (Burge ?)
(Sellars) (Stalnaker ?)
(McGinn)
(Lycan)
Figure 3
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 89
The collection of states of mind is productive: for example, the thoughts that
one actually entertains in the course of a mental life comprise a relatively
unsystematic subset drawn from a vastly larger variety of thoughts that one
could have entertained had an occasion for them arisen. For example, it has
probably never occurred to you before that no grass grows on kangaroos.
But, once your attention is drawn to the point, it's an idea that you are quite
capable of entertaining, one which, in fact, you are probably inclined to
endorse. A theory of the attitudes ought to account for this productivity; it
ought to make clear what it is about beliefs and desires in virtue of which
they constitute open-ended families.
Notice that Naturalism precludes saying 'there are arbitrarily many
propositional attitudes because there are infinitely many propositions' and
leaving it at that. The problem about productivity is that there are
arbitrarily many propositional attitudes that one can have. Since relations
between organisms and propositions aren't to be taken as primitive, one
is going to have to say what it is about organic states like believing and
desiring that allows them to be (roughly) as differentiated as the proposi-
tions are. If, for example, you think that attitudes are mapped to pro-
positions in virtue of their causal roles (see above), then you have to say
what it is about the attitudes that accounts for the productivity of the set
of causal roles.
A natural suggestion is that the productivity of thoughts is like the pro-
ductivity of natural languages, i.e. that there are indefinitely many thoughts
to entertain for much the same reason that there are indefinitely many sen-
tences to utter. Fine, but how do natural languages manage to be produc-
tive? Here the outlines of an answer are familiar. To a first approximation,
each sentence can be identified with a certain sequence of sub-sentential
constituents. Different sentences correspond to different ways of arranging
these sub-sentential constituents; new sentences correspond to new ways
of arranging them. And the meaning of a sentence-the proposition it
expresses-is determined, in a regular way, by its constituent structure.
The constituents of sentences are, say, words and phrases. What are the
constituents of propositional attitudes? A natural answer would be: other
propositional attitudes. Since, for example, you can't believe that P and Q
without believing that P and believing that Q we could take the former state
to be a complex of which the latter are the relatively (or perhaps absolutely)
simple parts. But a moment's consideration makes it clear that this won't
work with any generality: believing that P or Q doesn't require either
believing that P or believing that Q and neither does believing that if P
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
go 5. A. Fodor
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 9I
and believing P -+ Qis causally sufficient for inferring Q, ceteris paribus. But
then: what is it about the mechanisms of thinking in virtue of which such
generalizations hold? What, in particular, could believing and inferring be,
such that thinking the premisses of a valid inference leads, so often and so
reliably, to thinking its conclusion?
It was a scandal of mid-century Anglo-American philosophy of mind that
though it worried a lot about the nature of mental states (like the attitudes) it
quite generally didn't worry much about the nature of mental processes (like
thinking). This isn't, in retrospect, very surprising given the behaviourism
that was widely prevalent. Mental processes are causal sequences of mental
states; if you're eliminativist about the attitudes you're hardly likely to be
Realist about their causal consequences. In particular, you're hardly likely
to be Realist about their causal interactions. It now seems clear enough,
however, that our theory of the structure of the attitudes must accommodate
a theory of thinking; and that it is a pre-eminent constraint on the latter
that it provide a mechanism for symmetry between the inferential roles of
thoughts and their causal roles.
This isn't, by any means, all that easy for a theory of thinking to do.
Notice, for example, that the philosophy of mind assumed in traditional
British Empiricism was Realist about the attitudes and accepted a form of
RTM. (Very roughly, the attitudes were construed as relations to mental
images, the latter being endowed with semantic properties in virtue of what
they resembled and with causal properties in virtue of their associations.
Mental states were productive because complex images can be constructed
out of simple ones.) But precisely because the mechanisms of mental causa-
tion were assumed to be associationistic (and the conditions for association
to involve pre-eminently spatio-termporal propinquity), the Empiricists had
no good way of connecting the contents of a thought with the effects of enter-
taining it. They therefore never got close to a plausible theory of thinking,
and neither did the associationistic psychology which followed in their
footsteps.
What associationism missed-to put it more exactly-was the similarity
between trains of thoughts and arguments. Here, for an example, is Sherlock
Holmes doing his thing at the end of 'The Speckled Band':
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
92 J. A. Fodor
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 93
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
94 5. A. Fodor
just are environments in which the causal role of a symbol token is made to
parallel the inferential role of the proposition that it expresses.3
I expect it's clear how this is all supposed to provide an argument for
quantifying over mental representations. Computers are a solution to the
problem of mediating between the causal properties of symbols and their
semantic properties. So if the mind is a sort of computer, we begin to see
how you can have a theory of mental processes that succeeds where associa-
tionism (to say nothing of behaviourism) abjectly failed; a theory which
explains how there could regularly be non-arbitrary content relations
among causally related thoughts.
But, patently, there are going to have to be mental representations if this
proposal is going to work. In computer design, causal role is brought into
phase with content by exploiting parallelisms between the syntax of a symbol
and its semantics. But that idea won't do the theory of mind any good unless
there are mental symbols; mental particulars possessed of semantic and
syntactic properties. There must be mental symbols because, in a nutshell,
only symbols have syntax, and our best available theory of mental processes
indeed, the only available theory of mental processes that isn't known to be
false-needs the picture of the mind as a syntax-driven machine.4
A brief addendum before we end this section: the question of the extent to
which RTM must be committed to the 'explicitness' of mental representa-
tion is one that keeps getting raised in the philosophical literature (and
elsewhere; see Dennett, CCC; Stabler, HAGR). The issue becomes clear if
we consider real computers as deployed in Artificial Intelligence research.
So, to borrow an example of Dennett's, there are chess machines which play
as though they 'believe' that it's a good idea to get one's Queen out early. But
there needn't be-in fact, there probably wouldn't be-anywhere in the
system of heuristics which constitutes the program of such a machine a
symbol that means '(try and) get your Queen out early'; rather the machine's
obedience to that rule of play is, as it were, an epiphenomenon of its follow-
ing many other rules, much more detailed, whose joint effect is that, ceteris
paribus, the Queen gets out as soon as it can. The moral is supposed to be
3 Since the methods of computational psychology tend to be those of proof theory, its limitations tend
to be those of formalization. Patently, this raises the well-known issues about completeness; less
obviously, it connects the Cognitive Science enterprise with the Positivist programme for the
formalization of inductive (and, generally, non-demonstrative) styles of argument. (On the second point,
see Glymour, AE.)
4 It is possible to combine enthusiasm for a syntactic account of mental processes with any degree of
agnosticism about the attitudes-or, for that matter, about semantic evaluability itself. To claim that the
mind is a 'syntax-driven machine' is precisely to hold that the theory of mental processes can be set out in
its entirety without reference to any of the semantic properties of mental states (see Fodor, MS), hence
without assuming that mental states have any semantic properties. Steven Stich is famous for having
espoused this option (Stich, FFPTCS). My way of laying out the field has put the big divide between
Realism about the attitudes and its denial. This seems to me justifiable, but admittedly it underestimates
the substantial affinities between Stich and the RTM crowd. Stich's account of what a good science of
behaviour would look like is far closer to RTM than it is to, for example, the eliminative materialism of
the Churchlands.
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 95
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
96 5. A. Fodor
for RTM; it's not mandatory, but you are at liberty to combine RTM with
functional-role ('FR') semantics if you choose. Thus, you could perfectly
well say: 'Believing, desiring, and so forth are relations between intentional
systems and mental representations that get tokened (in their heads, as it
might be). Tokening a mental representation has causal consequences. The
totality of such consequences implies a network of causal interrelations
among the attitudes . . .' and so on to a functional-role semantics. In any
event, it's important to see thaf RTM needs some semantic story to tell if,
as we have supposed, RTM is going to be Realist about the attitudes and the
attitudes have their propositional objects essentially.
Which semantic story to tell is, in my view, going to be the issue in mental
representation theory for the foreseeable future. The questions here are so
difficult, and the answers so contentious, that they really fall outside the
scope of this paper; I had advertised a tour of an intellectual landscape about
whose topography there exists some working consensus. Still, I want to say a
little about the semantic issues by way of closing. They are the piece of
Cognitive Science where philosophers feel most at home; and they're where
the 'philosophy of psychology' (a discipline over which Auntie is disinclined
to quantify) joins the philosophy of language (which, I notice, Auntie allows
me to spell without quotes).
There are a number of reasons for doubting that a functional-role
semantic theory of the sort that SR proposes is tenable. This fact is currently
causing something of a crisis among people who would like to be Realists
about the attitudes.
In the first place-almost, by now, too obvious to mention-functional-
role theories make it seem that empirical constraints must underdetermine
the semantics of the attitudes. What I've got in mind here isn't the collection
of worries that cluster around the 'indeterminacy of translation' thesis; if
that sort of indeterminacy is to be taken seriously at all-which I doubt-
then it is equally a problem for every Realist semantics. There are, how-
ever, certain sources of underdetermination that appear to be built into
functional-role semantics as such; considerations which suggest either that
there is no unique best mapping of the causal roles of mental states on to the
inferential network of propositions or that, even if there is, such a mapping
would nevertheless underdetermine assignments of contents to the attitudes.
I'll mention two such considerations, but no doubt there are others; things
are always worse than one supposes.
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 97
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
98 3. A. Fodor
therefore, it merely displaces the main worry from: 'What's the connection
between an attitude and its propositional object?' to 'What's the connection
between the propositional object of an attitude and whatever state of affairs
it is that makes that proposition true or false?' Or, to put much the same
point slightly differently, FR semantics has a lot to say about the mind-to-
proposition problem but nothing at all to say about the mind-to-world
problem. In effect FR semantics is content to hold that the attitudes inherit
their satisfaction-conditions from their propositional objects and that pro-
positions have their satisfaction-conditions by stipulation.
And, in the third place, to embrace FR semantics is to raise a variety of
(approximately Quinean) issues about the individuation of the attitudes;
and these, as Putnam and Stich have recently emphasized, when once con-
jured up are not easily put down. The argument goes like this: according to
FR semantic theories, each attitude has its propositional object in virtue of
its position in the causal network: 'different objects iff different loci' holds to
a first approximation. Since a propositional attitude has its propositional
object essentially, this makes an attitude's identity depend on the identity of
its causal role. The problem is, however, that we have no criteria for the
individuation of causal roles.
The usual sceptical tactic at this point is to introduce some or other form
of slippery-slope argument to show-or at least to suggest-that there
couldn't be a criterion for the individuation of causal roles that is other than
arbitrary. Stich, for example, has the case of an increasingly senile woman
who eventually is able to remember about President McKinley only that he
was assassinated. Given that she has no other beliefs about McKinley-
given, let's suppose, that the only causal consequence of her believing that
McKinley was assassinated is to prompt her to produce and assent to
occasional utterances of 'McKinley was assassinated' and immediate logical
consequences thereof-is it clear that she in fact has any beliefs about
McKinley at all? But if she doesn't have, when, precisely, did she cease to do so?
How much causal role does the belief that McKinley was assassinated have
to have to be the belief that McKinley was assassinated? And what reason is
there to suppose that this question has an answer? (See Stich, FFPTCS and
also Putnam, CPIT.) Auntie considers slippery-slope arguments to be in
dubious taste and there is much to be said for her view. Still, it looks as
though FR semantics has brought us to the edge of a morass and I, for one,
am not an enthusiast for wading in it.
Well then, to summarize: the syntactic theory of mental operations
promises a reductive account of the intelligence of thought. We can now
imagine-though, to be sure, only dimly and in a glass darkly-a psycho-
logy which exhibits quite complex cognitive processes as being constructed
from elementary manipulations of symbols. This is what RTM, together
with the computer metaphor, has brought us; and it is, in my view, no small
matter. But a theory of the intelligence of thought does not, in and of itself,
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
Fodor's Guide to Mental Representation 99
References
Barwise, SA: Barwise, J. and Perry, J., Situations and Attitudes. MIT Press (I983).
Block, WIF: Block, N., 'What is Functionalism?' in Block, N. (ed.), Readings in
Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. i. Harvard University Press (I980).
Churchland, EMPA: Churchland, P., 'Eliminative Materialism and Propositional
Attitudes', Journal of Philosophy, 78 (I98I), 2.
Cummins, NPE: Cummins, R., The Nature of Psychological Explanation. MIT
Press (I983).
Dennett, B: Dennett, D., Brainstorms. Bradford Books (1978).
Dennett, CCC: Dennett, D., 'A Cure for the Common Code?', in Brainstorms.
Bradford Books (1978).
Dennett, IS: Dennett, D., 'Intentional Systems', in Brainstorms. Bradford Books
(1978).
Dennett, TB: Dennett, D., 'True Believers: The Intentional Strategy and Why it
Works', in Scientific Explanation, Papers Based on Herbert Spencer Lectures
Given in the University of Oxford. Clarendon Press (I98I).
Dretske, KFI: Dretske, F., Knowledge and the Flow of Information. MIT Press
(I98I).
Dreyfus, WCCD: Dreyfus, H., What Computers Can't Do. Harper & Row
(I 979).
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
IOO J. A. Fodor
Field, MR: Field, H., 'Mental Representation', Erkenntnis, I3 (1978), 9-6I; also in
Block, N. (ed.), Readings in Philosophy of Psychology, Vol. 2. Harvard
University Press (i980).
Fodor, BD: Fodor, J., 'Banish DisContent'. Unpublished.
Fodor, LOT: Fodor, J., The Language of Thought. Thomas Y. Crowell Co., Inc.
(I975) and Harvard University Press, paperback (1979).
Fodor, MBP: Fodor, J., 'The Mind-Body Problem', Scientific American, 244
(I981), 515-31.
Fodor, MS: Fodor, J., 'Methodological Solipsism', The Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 3 (i98o). Reprinted in Fodor, J., Representations. Harvester (1981).
Fodor, P: Fodor, J., 'Psychosemantics, Or Where Do Truth Conditions Come
From?' Unpublished.
Fodor, PA: Fodor, J., 'Propositional Attitudes', The Monist, 6i (1978). Reprinted
in Fodor, J., Representations. Harvester (I98I).
Fodor, SSA: Fodor, J., 'Something on the State of the Art'. Unpublished.
Fodor, SWS: Fodor, J., 'Semantics, Wisconsin Style', forthcoming in Synthese.
Glymour, AE: Glymour, C., 'Android Epistemology'. Unpublished.
Haugeland, NPC: Haugeland, J., 'The Nature and Plausibility of Cognitivism',
The Behavioural and Brain Sciences, 2 (I981), 215-60.
Loar, MM: Loar, B., Mind and Meaning. Cambridge University Press (I98I).
Matthews, TR: Matthews, R., 'Troubles with Representationalism', forthcoming
in Social Research.
Putnam, CPIT: Putnam, H., 'Computational Psychology and Interpretation
Theory', in Philosophical Papers, Vol. III: Realism and Reason. Cambridge
University Press (I983).
Putnam, MH: Putnam, H., 'Meaning Holism', mimeograph, Harvard University.
Searle, MBP: Searle, J., 'Minds, Brains and Programs', The Behavioral and Brain
Sciences, 3 (I98o), 417-24.
Stabler, HAGR: Stabler, E., 'How are Grammars Represented?' The Behavioral
and Brain Sciences, 6 (I983), 391-402.
Stampe, TCTLR: Stampe, D., 'Towards a Causal Theory of Linguistic Repre-
sentation', Midwest Studies in Philosophy, II (1977), 42-63.
Stich, FFPTCS: Stich, S., From Folk Psychology to Cognitive Science. MIT Press
(I983).
Vendler, RC: Vendler, Z., Res Cogitans. Cornell University Press (1972).
This content downloaded from 201.221.122.2 on Mon, 02 Mar 2020 21:19:36 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms