Analysis Ian Bent - 1
Analysis Ian Bent - 1
Analysis Ian Bent - 1
More difficult, in some ways, is to define where precisely analysis lies within the
study of music. The concerns of analysis as a whole can be said to have much in
common on the one hand with those of musical aesthetics and on the other with those
of compositional theory. The three regions of study might be thought of as
occupying positions along an axis that has at one extreme the placing of music
within philosophical schemes and at the other the giving of technical instruction
in the craft of composition. There are complicating factors, however, concerning
theory and criticism. Music theories have been developed that find their practical
expression not in composition but in analysis; from the obverse point of view one
might say that such theories derive stable concepts by abstraction from the data
that analysis provides. The relationship is thus one of mutual dependency. A
similarly mutual though less dependent relationship might be thought to exist in
principle between analysis and criticism. Many writings that are intended primarily
as criticism and lie within its traditions are recognizably analytical in their
concern with the direct description and investigation of musical detail.
Conversely, analytical writing expresses a critical position, albeit sometimes
merely by implication, but often in a sophisticated manner through the multiple
connotations of the theories it applies and the comparisons it draws. Even a
wordless analysis – which would seem the least capable of doing so – passes a value
judgment in asserting that its musical subject is worthy of study and explication.
Similarly, the analyst, like the aesthetician, is in part concerned with the nature
of the musical work: with what it is, or embodies, or signifies; with how it has
come to be; with its effects or implications; with its relevance to, or value for,
its recipients. Where they differ is in the centres of gravity of their studies:
the analyst focusses his attention on a musical structure (whether a chord, a
phrase, a work, the output of a composer or court etc.), and seeks to define its
constituent elements and explain how they operate; but the aesthetician focusses on
the nature of music per se and its place among the arts, in life and reality. That
the two supply information to each other is undoubted: the analyst provides a fund
of material which the aesthetician may adduce as evidence in forming his
conclusions, and the analyst’s definition of the specific furnishes a continual
monitoring service for the aesthetician’s definition of the general; conversely,
the aesthetician’s insights provide problems for the analyst to solve, condition
his approach and method, and ultimately furnish the means of exposing his hidden
assumptions. Their activities may overlap so that they often find themselves doing
similar things. Nonetheless, they have two essential differences, which may be
characterized in terms of the relative importance of empiricism and reflection:
analysis tends to supply evidence in answer to the empirical questions of
aesthetics, and may be content to explore the place of a musical structure within
the totality of musical structures, whereas the aesthetician’s concern is with the
place of musical structures within the system of reality. (For further discussion,
see Philosophy of music.)
Criticism is inseparable on the one hand from aesthetics and on the other from
analysis. Within criticism there has been constant debate as to the extent to which
it is a descriptive or a judicial activity. The ‘descriptive’ critic tries to do
either or both of two things: to portray in words his own inner response – to
depict his responding feelings – to a piece of music or a performance, or to think
his way into the composer’s or performer’s mind and expound the vision that he then
perceives. The ‘judicial’ critic evaluates what he experiences by certain
standards. These standards may at one extreme be dogmatic canons of beauty, of
truth or of taste – pre-set values against which everything is tested; or, at the
other extreme, values that form during the experience, governed by an underlying
belief that a composer or performer must do whatever he is attempting to do in the
clearest and most effective way. In none of the above does criticism differ
categorically from analysis: there is also a latent debate within analysis as to
whether the analyst’s function is descriptive or judicial.
A rather different relationship exists between musical analysis and music history.
To the historian, analysis may appear as a tool for historical inquiry. He uses it
to detect relationships between ‘styles’, and thus to establish chains of causality
that operate along the dimension of time and are anchored in time by verifiable
factual information. He may, for example, observe features in common between the
styles of two composers (or groups of composers) and inquire by internal analytical
methods and external factual ones whether this represents an influence of one upon
the other; or, in reverse order, seek common features of style when he knows of
factual links. Conversely, he may detect features out of common between pieces
normally associated for one reason or another, and proceed to distinguish by
comparative analysis distinct traditions or categories. Again, he may use an
analytical classification of features as a means of establishing a chronology of
events.
In turn, the analyst may view historical method as a tool for analytical inquiry.
His subject matter is rather like sections cut through history. When under analysis
they are timeless, or ‘synchronic’; they embody internal relationships that the
analyst seeks to uncover. But factual information, concerning events in time, may,
for example, determine which of several possible structures is the most likely, or
explain causally the presence of some element that is incongruous in analytical
terms. Comparative analysis of two or more separate phenomena (whether separated
chronologically, geographically, socially or intellectually) only really activates
the dimension of time – becoming ‘diachronic’ – when historical information
relating the phenomena is correlated with the analytical findings. Historical and
analytical inquiry are thus mutually dependent, with common subject matter and
complementary methods of working. (For further discussion see Historiography and
Musicology, §I and Musicology, §II, 8.)