Assertion of Constitutional Jus Tertii: A Substantive Approach, The
Assertion of Constitutional Jus Tertii: A Substantive Approach, The
Assertion of Constitutional Jus Tertii: A Substantive Approach, The
December 1982
Recommended Citation
Robert Allen Sedler, Assertion of Constitutional Jus Tertii: A Substantive Approach, The, 70 Calif. L. Rev. 1308 (1982).
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the California Law Review at Berkeley Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for
inclusion in California Law Review by an authorized administrator of Berkeley Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact
jcera@law.berkeley.edu.
California Law Review
VOL. 70 DECEMBER 1982 No. 6
t Professor of Law, Wayne State University. A.B. 1956, J.D. 1959, University of
Pittsburgh.
1. Sedler, Standing to Assert ConstitutionalJus Tertit in the Supreme Courl, 71 YALE L.J.
599 (1962) [hereinafter cited as Jus Tertim].
2. See generaly United States v. Raines, 362 U.S. 17, 21-23 (1960). As the Court long ago
stated: "It has been repeatedly held that one who would strike down a state statute as violative of
the federal Constitution must show that he is within the class of persons with respect to whom the
act is unconstitutional and that the alleged unconstitutional feature injures him." Heald v. Dis-
trict of Columbia, 259 U.S. 114, 123 (1922).
3. See Singleton v. Wulff, 428 U.S. 106, 114-16 (1976).
1308
1982] CONSTITUTIONAL JUS TERTII 1309
ones, led me to conclude that the Court's decisions are not consistent
with the general prohibition against the assertion of jus tertii and the
factor approach to the prohibition's exceptions that the Court purports
to accept. In fact, the Court has allowed litigants to assert third-party
rights both where the relationship between the litigant and the third
party was not a close one under the standards developed in prior cases,4
and where the third parties' assertion of their own rights in an in-
dependent action was not at all impracticable.' Given this apparent
inconsistency, I think it appropriate to consider anew the entire ques-
tion of constitutional jus tertii.
My reconsideration has led me to a very different position. I now
believe that as a general proposition, a party should be able to prevail
in constitutional litigation only if he can show some violation of his
own rights. I have also concluded that the Court has in fact acted con-
sistently with this general rule.
The first Part of this Article begins by tracing the development of
the Supreme Court's jus tertii doctrine. It then shows that the Court's
approach is analytically unsound because it considers the question of
constitutional jus tertii in terms of "standing," and that this unsound-
ness contributes to the inconsistencies in current doctrine. Part I con-
cludes that parties who are not themselves injured by a given rule or
action should not be able to challenge it by asserting third parties'
rights, and that the Court's approach has therefore been improper.
Part II of the Article argues that the results reached by the
Supreme Court in the cases in which it has viewed jus tertii in terms of
standing are consistent with my present thesis. Part II demonstrates
that in the cases in which the assertion of constitutional jus tertii was
permitted, the application of the challenged law or government action
to the party asserting jus tertii was itself unconstitutional or otherwise
invalid. Conversely, in the cases in which the assertion ofjus tertii was
not permitted, any possible violation of third party rights was irrelevant
to a determination of the constitutionality of the law as applied to the
litigant. Finally, Part III of the Article shows why it is necessary to
4. See, e.g., Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190 (1976) (vendor of beer held entitled to assert right
of male minor vendees).
5. See, e.g., Village of Belle Terre v. Boraas, 416 U.S. 1 (1974) (landlord allowed to assert
rights of tenants).
6. This reversal may in part be due to the fact that in my earlier article I did not take a
normative approach to the subject. In other words, I was not trying to develop a consistent analyt-
ical framework within which it could be determined whether the assertion of constitutional jus
tertii should be recognized. Rather, I took an "empirical" approach, analyzing the results that the
Court reached inorder to determine whether the Court recognized a legal right to assert constitu-
tional jus tertii; and if so, under what circumstances it would be permitted.
1310 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
reconcile results with doctrine and to remove the assertion of jus tertii
from constitutional litigation.
I
THE ANALYTICAL FRAMEWORK
A. The Supreme Court'sArticulatedJus Terti Doctrine
I GeneralPrincples
This Subsection defines the basic principles and distinctions un-
derlying the Supreme Court's jus tertii doctrine. The cases in which
questions of the assertion of jus tertii have arisen fall into two catego-
ries. In the first type of case, parties want to assert that a given law,
although constitutional as applied to their own conduct, would be un-
constitutional as applied to the conduct of third parties coming within
its scope. Cases in this category are facial challenges, in which parties
attack a law not because of a specific application of it to their own
conduct, but because its terms include constitutionally unreachable
conduct of third parties. An example would be a case in which the
director of a contraceptive clinic sues to invalidate a state law prohibit-
ing the use, but not the distribution, of contraceptives: the direc tor her-
self is not disadvantaged by the operation of the law, but would-be
users of her clinic are. I will hereafter refer to this kind of challenge as
a Category I case.
In the second type of case, litigants want to base claims or defenses
either wholly or partly on the ground that denial of the claim, or rejec-
tion of the defense, will violate third parties' rights. The appropriate
example here is a doctor who has been prosecuted under a state law
prohibiting the performance of abortions: the doctor will argue that
enforcement of the law against her implicates not only her rights, but
the rights of her would-be patients as well. These will be referred to as
Category II cases.
The Supreme Court has treated these two kinds of cases differ-
ently. In Category I cases, in which the litigant before the Court con-
cedes that the challenged law is constitutional as to him, the Court has
found the substance of the challenged law important, and has distin-
guished between ordinary criminal and regulatory laws and laws that
"by their terms restrict expression." 7 First amendment laws are singled
out for special treatment because a "chilling effect upon the exercise"of
First Amendment rights" may result from prosecution under an invalid
statute.' Where the challenged law by its terms restricted expression,
the Court would determine the validity of the law "on its face" regard-
less of the law's constitutionality as to the party actually before the
Court. 9
Where the challenged law did not on its face restrict expression,
the Court has decided whether a litigant could challenge its constitu-
tionality as applied to a third party by looking to severability. A sever-
able law is one that may be constitutionally applied to at least some
persons, even if it is unconstitutional as to others. If a party before the
Court could show that the challenged law was in fact nonseverable-
that is, incapable of differential application-he could include in his
challenge the contention that the law violated third parties' constitu-
tional rights.' 0 For our purposes, it is significant that in both of these
Category I situations, even if the party before the Court conceded that
the challenged law was constitutional as to him, he could prevail by
asserting third parties' constitutional rights.
In the more common Category II cases, in which a party asserts
that the rights of third parties would be violated by application of the
challenged law to him, the Court has stated that litigants generally will
not be allowed to strengthen their claims by asserting third-party rights
in addition to or in lieu of their own. In developing exceptions to that
rule, the Court has taken four factors into account: (1) the interest of
the party before the court; (2) the nature of the right asserted; (3) the
relationship between the litigant and the third party; and (4) the practi-
cability of the third party's assertion of his own rights in an independ-
ent action."I
The two most important factors were the relationship between the
litigant and the third party, and the third party's ability to bring suit to
assert his own rights.' 2 The Court purported to require a close relation-
ship, such as a professional or associational tie, between the party in
court and the third party.' 3 Furthermore, the Court claimed that it
opinion by Justice Blackmun, held that the physicians could assert their
patients' rights as well as their own.2 2
Justice Blackmun first discussed the reasons for a general prohibi-
tion against the assertion of third-party rights. He said that unneces-
sary adjudication of such rights is undesirable because (1) the third
parties might not wish to assert their rights or might be able to enjoy
them regardless of the outcome of the adjudication; and (2) the third
parties, who usually would be the best proponents of their own rights if
they did choose to assert them, would be bound by an unfavorable de-
cision under principles of stare decisis. But Justice Blackmun then de-
parted from the general rule and held that in this case, an exception to
the general rule was warranted because there was a close relationship
between the physicians and their patients, and because it would be im-
practicable for patients who needed abortions to assert their own rights.
Justice Blackmun's reiteration of the general rule prohibiting assertion
ofjus tertii in the context of a holding allowing an exception to the rule,
as well as the fact that his analysis did not command a majority of the
Court, indicated that the Court's jus tertii doctrine was in flux.
In Craigv. Boren, 23 decided six months after Singleton, the plain-
tiffs challenged an Oklahoma law that prohibited the sale of beer to
males under age 21 and females under age 18. The only plaintiff before
the Supreme Court was a bartender licensed to sell beer.2 4 The Court
saw the issue as whether "the licensed vendor of 3.2 percent beer, who
has a live controversy against enforcement of the statute, may rely
upon the equal protection objections of males 18-20 years of age to
that the district court determine the constitutionality of the restriction in the first instance. Id at
119-21. The Supreme Court subsequently held in another case that the state's refusal to provide
payment for nontherapeutic abortions was not unconstitutional. Maher v. Roe, 432 U.S. 464
(1977). See also Harris v. McRae, 448 U.S. 297 (1980).
22. Justice Stevens, concurring, took the position that because the physicians had standing to
sue and had alleged a violation of their own rights, the Court could also consider arguments
"based on the effect of the statute on the constitutional rights of their patients." 428 U.S. at 121-22
(Stevens, J., concurring in part). Four dissenters, in an opinion by Justice Powell, maintained that
the physicians should not be able to assert their patients' rights. Id. at 126-31 (Powell, J., dissent-
ing).
Justice Powell contended in dissent that in the prior cases where the assertion ofjus tertii had
been permitted, the Court had not emphasized the nature of the relationship between the litigant
and the third party, and that in any event, the challenged action in those cases directly interfered
with the relationship itself, which was not so here. Id. at 128 (Powell, J., dissenting). Justice
Blackmun insisted that the prior cases did not go off on this point. Id. at 118 n.7. Justice Powell
also contended, in sharp disagreement with Justice Blackmun, that in the prior cases a suit by the
third party was "in all practicable terms impossible." Id. at 126 (Powell, J., dissenting). Justice
Blackmun argued that the test was one of impracticability, not impossibility. Id. at 116 n.6.
23. 429 U.S. 190 (1976).
24. Originally, a male under age 21 had also been a plaintiff. By the time the case reached
the Supreme Court, he had turned 21, so the case was moot as to him. Id. at 192.
1314 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
answer all jus tertii questions. In the next Section, I will explain what I
think is the reason for the present doctrine's shortcomings.
28. See, e.g. Singleton v. Wulff, 428 U.S. 106, 112-13 (1976) (Category II); United States v.
Raines, 362 U.S. 17, 25-26 (1960) (Category I).
29. But see L. TRIBE, AMERICAN CONSTITUTIONAL LAW 102-14 (1978), relating the assertion
ofjus tertii to standing to sue.
30. Flast v. Cohen, 392 U.S. 83 (1968); Duke Power Co. v. Carolina Envtl. Study Group, 438
U.S. 59 (1978). My own view questions both the soundness of standing as a limitation on judicial
review, Sedler, Standing,Justiciability,andAll That: A BehavioralAnalysis,25 VAND. L. REv. 479,
511-12 (1972) [hereinafter cited as Standing,Justiciabilit andAll That], and the correctness of the
Supreme Court's current standing doctrine, Sedler, Standing and the Burger Court: An Analysis
andSome ProposalsforLegislativeReform, 30 RUTGERS L. Rnv. 863, 873-76 (1977) [hereinafter
cited as Standingand the Burger Court].
31. The only possible relationship between standing and jus tertii is that the Supreme Court
could allow'would-be litigants who are unable on their own to assert an interest sufficient to give
them standing, to assert the requisite interest by claiming the rights of third parties. As I later
demonstrate, however, the Supreme Court has never endorsed such a blanket proposition. See
infra note 35 and accompanying text.
32. See Schlesinger v. Reservists Comm. to Stop the War, 418 U.S. 208, 218-19 (1974);
Warth v. Seldin, 422 U.S. 490, 498-99 (1975). The test for standing to seek review of administra-
tive action is generally the same as the test for standing to sue in constitutional litigation. See
Standing, JusticiabiliyandAll That, supra note 30, at 489.
1316 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
33. The Court has held that "injury in fact" is required for standing purposes by article III's
case or controversy provision. See Schlesinger v. Reservists Comm. to Stop the War, 418 U.S.
208, 218 (1974); see also Standing and the Burger Court, supra note 30, at 874-76.
1982] CONSTITUTIONAL JUS TERTI1 1317
a party can appear in court and that of how strong his claim is once he
is there.34
This explanation shows that expressing jus tertii rules in standing
terms usually results in equating two dissimilar questions. Moreover, it
muddles attempts to separate factors relating to a would-be plaintiff's
ability to get into court from factors relating to the issues a party once
in court could raise. The result is that jus tertii has been seen as a
procedural, not a substantive, doctrine. The principle has not been that
any litigant challenging a law or government action could prevail only
by showing that its operation violated his own rights. Rather, it has
been that ordinarily litigants did not have standing to assert third-par- 35
ties' rights. Because this limitation was a prudential rule of practice
rather than a substantive limitation, exceptions could be developed
which would permit "standing to assert third-party rights" in certain
cases. This is exactly what has happened; the Supreme Court has de- 36
veloped a set of rules relating to "constitutional jus tertii standing."
Because those rules were born of confusion, they serve only to be-
get further confusion. The attempt to answer jus tertii questions by
looking to prudential procedural limitations, rather than to substantive
constraints, may explain the inconsistency between the Supreme
Court's decisions and the limiting doctrine that the Court purports to
apply. The next Section argues that the Court should discard the pro-
cedural approach and make the substantive determination that litigants
may never prevail by asserting others' rights.
34. The analytical unsoundness of approaching the assertion ofjus tertii in terms of "stand-
ing" is further demonstrated by the fact that using standing terms in the jus tertii context solves
nothing. That is, "standing" considerations would work equally toward permitting the assertion
ofjus tertii and toward denying it. On the one hand, if the gravamen of standing is to ensure that
a party always has an interest in challenging the validity of a particular law or governmental
action, arguably there will always be "standing" to assert third parties' rights because any litigant
who will prevail if the challenge is successful always has an interest in making any claims that will
help him win. By the same token, it is equally arguable that there should never be "standing" to
assert third parties' rights, because the litigant as to whom the application of the challenged law or
government action is constitutional has no interest in claiming that it is unconstitutional as ap-
plied to third parties.
This tautology surfaces in Barrows v. Jackson, 346 U.S. 249 (1953), where the Court noted
that the basis of the general rule against the assertion of jus tertii was that "a person cannot
challenge the constitutionality of a statute unless he shows that he himself is injured by its opera-
tion." Id. at 255. In the next sentence, however, the Court added that "[t]his principle has no
application in the instant case in which respondent has been sued for damages totaling $11,600,
and in which a judgment against respondent would constitute a direct, pocketbook injury to her."
Id. at 255-56. The plaintiff in Barrows was concededly injured; the Court failed to see that stand-
ing doctrine could not answer any of the jus tertii questions that followed a finding of injury in
fact.
35. Barrows v. Jackson, 346 U.S. 249, 257 (1953).
36. The Supreme Court's application of the rules in practice have caused these exceptions to
swallow up the general rule.
1320 CALIFORiVIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
ren,39 for example, should have been able to assert only the claims
stemming from the Oklahoma law's adverse impact on her right to do
business, and not any different claims that might be made by 18 to 20
year old males.
The Supreme Court has set forth the rule that a court should hear
only the claims of parties actually before it, but it has diluted the rule
with exceptions so that the exceptions overrun the rule. Thus, the
Supreme Court's present doctrine needs reformulation. The theory I
will set forth allows for constant application of the rule. It also demon-
strates how the cases in which the Supreme Court has allowed the as-
sertion ofjus tertii have actually been cases in which the litigants' own
rights were violated.
The rules the Court applies in Category I cases, as I shall explain
below, are properly focused and are consistent with my theory. The
Court's "factor doctrine," however, is the wrong approach because it
uses the wrong criteria. Claims of a close relationship between the liti-
gants and third parties, or of the impracticability of a third party's as-
sertion of his own rights, are not enough. No relationship, however
close, transfers one party's constitutional rights to another,40 and if the
law or government action can constitutionally be applied to a litigant it
should not matter that it cannot constitutionally be applied to a third
party with whom the litigant has a close relationship.
Nor should it matter that it might be "impracticable" for third par-
ties to assert their own rights in an independent action. Impracticabil-
ity does not substitute one party for another, and does not furnish a
reason why any litigant should be able to avoid the application of a law
or government action that is constitutional as to him.41
My argument, then, is that as a general proposition there is no
II
THE ASSERTION OF THIRD-PARTY RIGHTS IN RETROSPECT:
A SUBSTANTIVE HYPOTHESIS
This Part argues that in fact the assertion ofjus tertii has not been
allowed by the Supreme Court. That is, the Court has not really per-
mitted a party as to whom a challenged law is constitutional to prevail
by asserting third parties' rights. I posit, then, that the results of the
decided cases are consistent with the thesis I have stated that in consti-
tutional litigation, parties may prevail only by asserting their own
rights.43 The purpose of this Section is to show that what has appeared
as a matter of "standing to assert jus tertii" is in fact a matter of sub-
stance, and that where the Court has thought it was permitting the as-
sertion of third-party rights, the challenged law actually violated the
if they appeared in Court to assert them, the NAACP was properly allowed to assert the rights of
its members.
This circumstance, however, is rare and is different from the "impracticability of assertion"
factor that the Court has been using. In Singleton v. Wulff, 428 U.S. 106 (1976), for example, the
Court's holding did not itself allow the patients' rights to be violated. Moreover, the patients
could have brought their own suit contending that they were entitled to have the state make pay-
ment to the physicians on their behalf. The same is true of Griswold v. Connecticut, 381 U.S. 479
(1965): the persons desiring to obtain access to contraceptives could have brought suit in their
own right, using a fictitious name to maintain their privacy. Assuming that the third parties can
vindicate their own rights in an independent suit, albeit with some difficulty, there can be no
justification for permitting the litigant to prevail by asserting their rights.
. 42. In a recent article, Professor Rohr, using a "standing" analysis with respect to the asser-
tion of jus tertii, contends that "for the sake of clarity, economy, and consistency of approach,
federal courts should grant third-party standing to any litigant who appears reasonably likely to
give adequate representation to the interests of the third parties whose rights the litigant wishes to
assert." Rohr, Fightingfor the Rights of Others: The Troubled Law of Third-PartyStanding and
Mootness in the Federal Courts, 35 MIAMI L. REV. 393 (1981). The rather fundamental defect in
Professor Rohr's position is that despite his disclaimer in this regard, the assertion of jus tertii
would turn out to be an aspect of "representational standing," in which the party who is before the
court is "fighting for the rights of others." The reason that the litigant is asserting jus tertii, how-
ever, is so that he can prevail on the assailant's own claim or defense. Professor Rohr does not
fully explain what the justification is for permitting a party as to whom the application of the
challenged law or governmental action is presumably constitutional, to prevail on the ground that
such law or governmental action violates the rights of third parties.
43. See Heald v. District of Columbia, 259 U.S. 114, 123 (1922) (suggesting that general rule
is that one who challenges constitutionality of state statute must show membership in class with
respect to whom act is unconstitutional and that the statute's unconstitutional feature injures him).
1982] CONSTITUTIONAL JUS TERTII 1323
44. The term "substantive right to be free from invalid government action" refers to the
circumstance where a nonseverable federal law is "void on its face," with the result that no sub-
stantive liability can be imposed against the litigant before the Court.
45. Jus Terii,supra note 1, at 608.
1324 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
Where the law challenged by the party before the Court is severa-
ble, on the other hand, there is no issue of its constitutionality as to
third parties. Even if the law would be invalid as to others, it remains
valid as to the litigant in court. This is also consistent with my thesis.
The litigant cannot assert unconstitutionality as to third parties, not be-
cause he lacks "standing" to assert third-party rights, but because when
the statute is severable, the litigant's substantive claims can be decided
without reference to third-party issues.5 1
For example, in United States v. Raines,5 2 the Court found that
Congress intended that the challenged law,53 which prohibited "any
person" from interfering on racial grounds with another's right to vote,
should be applied to acts of governmental officials without regard to 54
whether it could constitutionally be applied to acts of private persons.
It therefore held that a government official charged with a violation of
the law could not defend on the ground that the law could not reach
private persons.
The Raines Court clearly intimated that the law's constitutionality
as to private persons was not relevant in a prosecution against state
officials. This is correct, as the official before the Court could assert no
right of his own derived from the rights of those to whom the law might
someday be unconstitutionally applied. 55
The rule regarding facial challenges in the non-expression context,
fifteenth amendment to prevent racial discrimination. Id at 217-19. The Court found that the
law was not capable of severable application. Id at 221. Because the law sought to be invoked
against the defendant was both nonseverable and unconstitutional (at least in part), there was no
valid law that could be invoked against the defendant, and his conduct could not be subject to
criminal sanction. Given the Court's holding as to the nonseverability of the law, the issue of the
constitutionality of all of the sections was necessarily relevant to the determination of whether the
law could, as a matter of federal substantive law, be invoked against the defendant. In both of
these cases, then, the assailants prevailed on the basis of their own substantive rights.
51. Thus, a party who constitutionally can be subject to the government's taxing power
would have no basis for challenging a taxing statute on the ground that it would be unconstitu-
tional as applied to others. Heald v. District of Columbia, 259 U.S. 114, 122-23 (1922). Likewise,
a defendant as to whom a severable criminal statute is not impermissibly vague would have no
basis for asserting that it would be impermissibly vague in other possible situations to which it
could be applicable. This claim is frequently made in practice and rejected on "lack of standing"
grounds. See, e.g., United States v. Alfonso, 552 F.2d 605, 615-16 (5th Cir. 1977), cert denied,434
U.S. 857 (1979); United States v. Chew, 540 F.2d 759, 761 (4th Cir. 1976), cert. denied, 429 U.S.
1043 (1977); United States v. Persky, 520 F.2d 283, 287-88 (2d Cir. 1975); Big Eagle v. Andera,
508 F.2d 1293, 1297 (8th Cir. 1975).
52. 362 U.S. 17 (1960).
53. 42 U.S.C. § 1971(c) (1976).
54. Raines, 362 U.S. at 23 n.4.
55. See the discussion in id. at 25-26. In Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190, 195 n.4 (1976), the
Court explained Raines as a case in which the interests of the assailant and the third party were
not "mutually interdependent," so that a successful prosecution against Raines "did not threaten
to impair or diminish the independent private rights of others." While this is true, it should not
have prevented Raines from challenging the law "on its face" if the law were in fact nonseverable.
1326 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
56. This rationale would not justify allowing a party to mount a facial challenge to a state
law in the non-expression situation. In the federal context, the Court must decide questions of
substantive liability as well as constitutional questions, and must determine whether there is a
valid federal law to be invoked against the litigant. In the state context, however, the only ques-
tion for the federal court is whether the state has violated the litigant's federal constitutional or
statutory rights. If the challenged state law can constitutionally be applied to the litigant, and
such application is not prohibited by federal law, the inquiry of the federal court is at an end.
Whether a state law is capable of severable application is a question of state law, and the applica-
tion of a nonseverable state law to a party whose activity the state can constitutionally reach does
not violate any federal constitutional rights of that party.
This proposition is illustrated by the case in which a nonphysician challenges a state anti-
abortion law that would be unconstitutional if applied to prohibit the performing of abortions by
physicians. If the state can constitutionally prohibit nonphysicians from performing abortions, the
conviction of a nonphysician under the statute, whether the statute is severable or not, violates no
federal constitutional rights of the defendant. For this reason, the federal court in this case cannot
properly consider the constitutionality of the state statute "on its face". The Court in effect
reached this result in Cheaney v. Indiana, 410 U.S. 991 (1973), denying cert. to 259 Ind. 138, 285
N.E.2d 265 (1972), although it couched its decision in terms of the defendant's "want of standing"
instead of in terms of the substantive constitutionality of the application of the state anti-abortion
law to this defendant. Although the Court has in the past allowed facial challenges to some state
laws in the non-expression situation, see, e.g., Berger v. New York, 388 U.S. 41 (1967); Wuchter v.
Pizzutti, 276 U.S. 13 (1928), it has more recently refused to permit such challenges, see County
Court v. Allen, 442 U.S. 140 (1979); Sibron v. New York, 392 U.S. 40 (1968); ef. H.L. v. Matheson,
450 U.S. 398 (1981) (appellant lacked standing to make facial challenge because neither she nor
any member of her class was demonstrably affected).
57. Jus Tertii, supra note 1, at 613.
19821 CONSTITUTIONAL JUS TERTII 1327
gant was an employer and could not prevail unless his own rights were violated, "the exemption
from further liability is an essential part of the scheme, so that the statute, if invalid as against the
employee, is invalid as against the employer." New York Cent. R.R. v. White, 243 U.S. 188, 197
(1917); see also Mountain Timber Co. v. Washington, 243 U.S. 219, 234 (1917).
Similarly, in Meyer v. Nebraska, 262 U.S. 390 (1923), and companion cases, in which the
Court invalidated a state law prohibiting the teaching of a foreign language to school children,
only a teacher or a school was before the Court. The Court, however, invalidated the laws on the
ground that they violated the rights of the parents and students as well as the rights of the teachers
and the schools. In fact, the Court considered these sets of rights to be inseparable and did not see
the cases as involving any attempt to assert constitutional jus tertii. It took the same approach in
Pierce v. Society of Sisters, 268 U.S. 510 (1925), in which it invalidated on due process grounds a
state law requiring parents to send their children to public schools instead of private ones. There
the plaintiffs were operators of private schools, and the Court found that the law was both an
unreasonable interference with the liberty of parents and guardians to direct the education of
children under their control, and an interference with the property interests of the schools by
preventing them from enrolling students.
In Meyer and Pierce, the violation of the rights of the students and parents was directly
relevant to the determination of the litigants' constitutional claim. If the state could not interfere
with the rights of parents and children to receive foreign language instruction or attend private
schools, there could be no justification for the interference with the liberty or property interests of
the parties who were before the Court. Ultimately, however, the litigants' claims stood or fell on
the basis of their own rights.
65. 381 U.S. 479 (1965).
66. 405 U.S. 438 (1972).
1330 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
and should-have been based on the rights of the party before the
Court, because the challenged law violated Baird's own rights.
Because the distributor Baird was not a licensed physician or phar-
macist, this case may look like a Category I facial challenge. In fact, it
was not. Baird asserted that the law was unconstitutional as to him
because it was not justifiable as a health measure, and therefore its dis-
crimination between health professionals and others was invalid. The
Court agreed, finding no valid state public health interest behind the
law and rejecting the state's severability argument that the law could at
least be constitutionally applied as to Baird, because he was not a
health professional. The majority held that the state could not legiti-
mately distinguish between health professionals and other contracep-
tive distributors. 74 This holding meant that the statute could not be
applied differently to Baird than to health professionals, and allowed
the Court to reach the question of the legitimacy of distinguishing be-
tween married and unmarried contraceptive users. The Court then de-
cided that Massachusetts had no legitimate state interest in
distinguishing between married and unmarried contraceptive users,
and invalidated the law on the assumption that Baird was asserting
unmarried persons' rights.
The case could have been decided on the basis of the distributor's
own rights. If unmarried persons have the same right of access to con-
traceptives as married persons, 75 the state, which recognized the mar-
ried patients' right of access 76 and therefore could not deny it to
unmarried persons, similarly could not interfere with the distributor's
liberty to give contraceptives to those unmarried persons.77 If the origi-
nal distinction may not be constitutionally made, any law resulting
from that distinction must be unconstitutional as well. Note that again,
the harm stemmed from the distributor-distributee relationship, and,
for the same reason that it violated the unmarried persons' rights, it
also violated Baird's rights.
The concurring Justices, White and Blackmun, agreed with the
thesis advanced here, that litigants must prevail on the basis of their
own rights, not the rights of third parties. They took the position that
the petitioner had a constitutional right to distribute contraceptives to
at least some persons. 78 The perception underlying this position must
las also filed a concurring opinion. Justices White and Blackmun concurred in the result. Chief
Justice Burger dissented.
74. 405 U.S. at 444.
75. This was the substantive holding of the majority in Eisenstadt. 405 U.S. at 453-55.
76. The state was compelled to do so under the restrictions of Griswold.
77. This is true given the finding that it could not require that all contraceptives be pre-
scribed by a physcian. 405 U.S. at 450.
78. 405 U.S. at 464.
1332 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
79. The "liberty" protected by due process has been said to include "not merely freedom
from bodily restraint but also the right of the individual to contract, to engage in any of the
common occupations of life, . . . and generally to enjoy those privileges long recognized at com-
mon law as essential to the orderly pursuit of happiness by free men." Meyer v. Nebraska, 262
U.S. 390, 399 (1923) (citations omitted). See also Allgeyer v. Louisiana, 165 U.S. 578, 589 (1897).
80. 428 U.S. 106 (1976).
81. Maher v. Roe, 432 U.S. 464, 469 (1977).
82. In Singleton, the plaintiffs probably believed that the denial of Medicaid funding for
abortions would be subject to a greater degree of scrutiny if they claimed it violated the constitu-
tional rights of the woman. While this may have been so, the denial of Medicaid funding for
abortions was nonetheless upheld in Maher and in Harris v. McRae, 448 U.S. 297 (1980).
83. 429 U.S. 190 (1976).
1982] CONSTITUTIONAL JUS TERTI1 1333
88. Shelley v. Kraemer, 334 U.S. 1 (1948). This was also the substantive holding of Barrows.
89. As noted in connection with Craig v. Boren, 429 U.S. 190, 195 (1976), the violation of the
prospective buyers' rights by the enforcement of the racially restrictive covenant against the seller
would be relevant to show a lack of justification for the interference with the seller's liberty and
property interests. But it would not be necessary for the Court to consider the violation of the
rights of the prospective buyers as such in order to hold that the awarding of damages would
violate the rights of the seller.
90. In Village of Belle Terre v. Boraas, 416 U.S. 1 (1974), a landlord and some of his former
tenants challenged the constitutionality of a village ordinance prohibiting more than two unre-
lated persons from living together. They asserted their own rights and the rights of all unrelated
persons wanting to live together on the ground that the prohibition violated the "right to privacy"
of the tenants. The Court upheld the ordinance. Because the unrelated persons did not have a
constitutional right to live together, and because the restriction on unrelated persons living to-
gether advanced what the Court found to be valid "environmental concerns," the village could
assert a legitimate interest in the ordinance, and therefore could constitutionally restrict the land-
lord's use of his property in this manner.
Belle Terre is unusual in that while the Court apparently allowed the plaintiff to assert third
parties' rights, the plaintiff's attempt to augment his claim failed because the Court then decided
that the challenged action did not violate the third parties' constitutional rights. In retrospect, the
result here can also be explained on the ground that the challenged action did not violate the
rights of the party before the Court either.
In Belle Terre, as in Craigv. Boren, the ordinance directly interfered with the property inter-
ests of the party before the Court. As a matter of due process, again, the state had to assert a
legitimate governmental interest to justify such interference. If unrelated persons did have a con-
stitutional right to live in the same dwelling, and if the state could not justify infringing that right
by asserting some legitimate governmental interest, the state by definition would have no legiti-
mate interest in interfering with the landlord's ability to rent the premises to whomever he chose.
The landlord was therefore a proper plaintiff. But because the use restriction was constitutional,
the result can be explained on the ground that the challenged ordinance did not violate the plain-
tiff landlord's due process rights.
Justice Brennan, in dissent, stated that the challenge was premised solely on the alleged in-
fringement of the tenants' constitutional rights, so that in his view, the determination of the moot-
ness question depended on whether the landlord could assert their constitutional rights. He
maintained that the assertion ofjus tertii should not be permitted, since there was no impractica-
bility of assertion of the rights by the tenants themselves, as indicated by the fact that the former
tenants had joined as plaintiffs. 416 U.S. at 10-12. The majority did not directly respond to Justice
Brennan's argument in this regard.
1982] CONSTITUTIONAL JUS TERTI1 1335
2. The Cases in Which the Assertion of Jus Tertil Was Not Permitted
This Subsection will consider the relatively few recent cases in
which the assertion ofjus tertii was not permitted. In these cases, after
refusing to allow litigants to supplement their claims by asserting third
parties' rights, the Court found that the challenged law or governmen-
tal action did not violate the litigant's constitutional rights. This result
is consistent with my hypothesis of substantive rights. In these cases,
violation of third-party rights was irrelevant to the determination of the
litigants' constitutional claims.
In Moose Lodge No. 107 v. Irvis,92 a black who had been denied
service at a private club brought suit challenging the club's policy of
refusing service to members' black guests. The Court held that he
could not also challenge the club's policy of denying membership to 93
blacks by asserting the rights of blacks wishing to become members.
This is the proper result under my thesis that the litigant's substan-
tive rights should be the only ones considered, because the court could
not have decided both questions using the same substantive criteria.
The constitutionality of the club's refusal to permit blacks to become
members was analytically dissimilar to whether its policy of refusing to
serve members' black guests was unconstitutional. Even if both the liti-
gant and the third party had equal protection claims, no relation ex-
isted between the two which involved the alleged harm. Therefore,
even if the club's membership policy did infringe black would-be mem-
bers' rights, the plaintiff, not wishing to become a member himself, suf-
fered no detriment from the policy and therefore could not challenge it.
The Court properly restricted the scope of the case to the constitution-
ality of the club's service policy, for the plaintiff's rights were infringed
by that policy alone.
91. This was the situation in Belle Terre and Singleton. The reference to the result in Single-
ton is in light of the subsequent decisions in Maher and Harris.
92. 407 U.S. 163 (1972).
93. Justice Douglas, in dissent, argued that the plaintiffshould be able to challenge the statu-
tory scheme which authorized the club to practice racial discrimination because the scheme
caused "cognizable injury" to all black residents of the state. 407 U.S. at 183-85 & n.4 (Douglas,
J., dissenting).
1336 6CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
an IRS summons, did not even have a claim that the requirements
might in some future action be declared invalid as to them. It follows
that because the banks themselves could never be subject to proceed-
ings against them or to adverse consequences as a result of the records
they were being required to keep, they had no due process claim to
challenge the requirement. The Court's holding was consistent with
my proposed rule that litigants may stand only on their own rights.
In Warth v. Se/din,9 9 plaintiffs challenged the zoning practices of
Penfield, a suburb of the City of Rochester. Some of the plaintiffs were
Rochester taxpayers, who alleged that they were injured by Penfield's
exclusionary zoning practices because those practices forced Rochester
to provide more low and moderate income housing, which in turn re-
duced the city's tax base and required its taxpayers to assume an in-
creased tax burden in order to finance essential public services.
Another plaintiff, an association whose members were Penfield resi-
dents, alleged that the exclusionary zoning practices deprived its mem-
bers of the benefits of living in a racially and ethnically integrated
community.
The Court held that these plaintiffs were attempting to assert
third-party rights, and that they could not do so. The Court said that
the Rochester taxpayers could not challenge the exclusionary zoning
practices, because they had no right to be free from the incidentally
damaging practices of neighboring towns,'0 and that there was no ba-
sis for permitting them to assert the rights of the excluded low-income
persons.' 0 ' As to the Penfield residents, the Court noted that they had
not alleged the statutory or constitutional right to live in a racially and
ethnically integrated community, 0 2 so that their contention was only
that they had been harmed "indirectly" by the exclusion of others.
Further, no protected contractual or other relationship existed between
Penfield residents and those allegedly excluded from the town, so that
no impermissible interference with such a relationship could be
shown.'0 3 The Court concluded that these plaintiffs were "attempt[ing]
to raise putative rights of third parties," and that "none of the excep-
tions that allow such claims is present here.'
Once again, the result is consistent with a rule that parties must
prevail by asserting their own rights. The litigants failed because they
could not assert sufficient rights of their own. Even if third-party righis
were affected by the Penfield scheme, the violation of such rights would
have been immaterial to a determination of plaintiffs' claims, because
the plaintiffs' claims and the third-party claims they sought to assert
had to be judged by different substantive criteria. The Rochester tax-
payers had no substantive right to be free from any adjoining munici-
pality's action that could increase their tax burden, so that the exclusion
of low-income people from Penfield, even if unconstitutional, was not
relevant to a determination of any claims of the Rochester taxpayers.
The association representing Penfield residents did not allege that it
had a statutory or constitutional right to live in a racially or ethnically
integrated community, 105 so to litigate the question of whether the
Penfield ordinance would have violated that right would have been
inappropriate.
The results of the cases in which litigants could not assert third-
party rights, then, can be explained simply by my substantive hypothe-
sis. Because the litigants' and the third parties' rights were either dis-
similar or unrelated, in none of these cases was the alleged violation of
third parties' constitutional rights relevant to the determination of the
litigants' constitutional claims. 0 6 The substantive dissimilarity or unre-
latedness of the litigants' and the third parties' claims meant that the
litigants did not suffer violations of their own constitutional rights as a
result of the challenged laws' applications, regardless of their effects on
third parties.
A summary of this lengthy Section is in order. I have argued that
in all of the cases in which litigants sought to assert third-party rights,
the results can be explained in terms of the substantive hypothesis ad-
vanced here. First, the Court's rules as to facial challenges are congru-
ent with a theory of substantive rights: a party will succeed if he can
show that he has a substantive right to be free from the application of
the law.
Second, in the cases in which litigants want to assert that third
parties will be hurt by application of the law to the party in court, the
105. The Penfield residents who were members of the plaintiff association probably could
have alleged a statutory right to interracial associations in the housing context, see Gladstone
Realtors v. Village of Bellwood, 441 U.S. 91, 95 (1979); but if they had done so, they could have
challenged the practices only on the ground that the practices constituted racial discrimination.
106. It did not seem worthwhile to test all of the older cases where jus tertii standing was
denied. A review of at least some of them, however, does support the hypothesis. For example, in
Missouri, K. & T. Ry. v. Cade, 233 U.S. 642 (1914), and in Rosenthal v. New York, 226 U.S. 260
(1912), dircussedin Jus Terti, supra note 1, at 634-35, parties subject to criminal and civil liability
respectively under state laws contended that the laws denied equal protection to potential subjects
of the laws who were not included within their coverage. But even if the laws denied equal pro-
tection (which was highly unlikely), they would not necessarily violate the constitutional rights of
the defendants. The defendants still could constitutionally be subject to liability for the harm that
they caused.
1982] CONSTITUTIONAL JUS TERTI1 1339
III
THE RECONCILIATION OF DOCTRINE AND RESULTS
107. I have not investigated the results reached by the lower federal courts in cases involving
1340 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
113. The Court had previously held that such an admission was incriminating. Blau v.
United States, 340 U.S. 159 (1950).
114. 367 U.S. at 106-10.
115. Id. at 188 (Douglas, J., dissenting). Similarly, as Justice Brennan noted, "[A] party has
been allowed to assert the constitutional rights of another person not before the Court as a named
party in a variety of situations where the effect of the challenged action on himself is derivative
from the impact on the other person." Id. at 193 (Brennan, J., dissenting in part).
116. Communist Party looks at first blush like California Bankers Ass'n v. Schultz, 416 U.S.
21(1974). How can I criticize Communist Party while I defend California Bankers? See supra
notes 94-97 and accompanying text. The answer is that the Communist Party itself was subject to
sanction for failure to register, and therefore had a right of its own to assert that it should be free
from the registration requirement. The Court recognized this right, but found that it was prema-
turely raised. In Caiffornia Bankers, by contrast, the banks were not subject to actions against
them based on the contents of the records they were required to keep. The banks therefore had no
right to claim that in the event of such actions, the requirements they challenged would work to
violate their rights. My judgments of the two cases are consistent, as they both look to the sub-
stantive rights of the paly. before the Court.
1342 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 70:1308
CONCLUSION