On Authority and Its Relationship To Power: Barry Barnes
On Authority and Its Relationship To Power: Barry Barnes
On Authority and Its Relationship To Power: Barry Barnes
Barry Barnes
Abstract
180
On authority and its relationship to power
Power
181
Barry Barnes
Authority
182
On authority and its relationship to power
183
Barry Barnes
Maximising power
184
On authority and its relationship to power
Authorities-on
185
Barry Barnes
idiom when we use the term 'authority' for this kind of work.
Whereas one possesses the authority to do or to act, one typically
is an authority on something or somebody. One may be an
authority on the geology of the North Sea, or Hungarian folk-
songs; or on Aristotle or Thomas Aquinas.
What is implied by being an authority in this way? On a power
plus view of authority, an authority on, say, Aristotle would be
anyone generally empowered and accepted as an expositor and
interpreter of Aristotle. The authority would derive his standing
wholly and entirely from his society, which would empower him to
expound Aristotle, and treat his expositions as legitimate versions.
Any actual connection between the authority and Aristotle, or
Aristotle's texts, would be contingent, essentially accidental. A
community might have a fancy for authorities familiar with the
texts upon which they pronounced - or it might not: either way it
would appoint what 'authorities' it wished. This, of course, is
counter-intuitive. We habitually regard the connection between an
authority and that upon which he is an authority as a necessary
one. We expect an authority on Aristotle to know Aristotle, and to
expound him, so far as is possible, correctly.
This habitual way of thinking is perfectly compatible with a
power minus notion of authority. An authority on a text must
know that text, and the very fact that the text is known is
presumed to restrict discretion in expounding it. Ideally, knowledge
of the text eliminates all discretion in its exposition, so that the
authority becomes transparent to the text: the text shines through
the authority, as it were, and makes itself visible to us directly.
This, at any rate, is the theory which gives the authority its
credibility, its very standing as an authority. To the extent that it is
thought to lack discretion an authority is credited. To the extent
that it is thought to be exercising discretion an authority is
distrusted. It is no longer transparent to the text. It is no longer
Aristotle who is heard, but the personal voice of his expositor. As
discretion enters in, Aristotle becomes more and more distant, so
that at the point of full discretion there is no longer any reason to
prefer the authority to any other expositor of Aristotle. An
authority on Aristotle is the passive agent of Aristotle, rather as
the possessor of authority is the passive agent of a power. Note
that we have authorities on Aristotle in a way that we could not
contemplate having powers over Aristotle.
In discussing authorities-on, in what follows, I shall confine
myself to authorities on texts; but it is worth mentioning that the
186
On authority and its relationship to power
A central problem
Possible solutions
187
Barry Barnes
188
On authority and its relationship to power
showing how actions are successfully made out after the fact as in
accordance with rules. In both fields it is agreed that there is
nothing inherent in a verbal formulation to determine its implica-
tions or define its true significance. No particular implication can
be assigned unproblematically to a rule or instruction, by
inspection as it were, as 'the' implication of the rule; and no
particular significance can be assigned to a text as 'the' significance
of the text. Therefore, it is said, implications must be derived and
significances imputed entirely at the discretion of the agents
involved. 10
The consequences of such a position for an understanding of
power and authority are as easy to elucidate as they are hard to
accept. Having turned our assumptions about linguistic communi-
cations upside down we must expect to find our understanding of
social and cognitive authority turned upside-down too. Start by
thinking of a potential authority as an initially free agent
confronted by verbal formulations, whether to be expounded or
obeyed. Verbal formulations have neither fixed logical implications
or fixed semantic implications. Therefore, it would seem, their use
puts no restrictions upon the freedom of the agent: he retains his
complete discretion. Even though he must act [or speak] properly
and correctly, he is nonetheless free to act [or speak] as he will,
since he may make what he will of the formulations to which he
'conforms. Where the agent is expected to expound a text there will
be no 'objective' exposition available to him; he will necessarily
have to practise interpretation, exegesis, hermeneutic art. His
'exposition' will be an artful creation which, rather than finding
meaning in the text, will construct a meaning for the text. The
exposition will, to use the now all too familiar phrase, be amenable
to deconstruction. Similarly, where the agent is expected to obey
an instruction, there will be no 'objective' indication of what it is
so to obey; he will simply have to act and then make out the act as
an obedient act. His 'obedience' will be the artful creation of ex
post facto accounting, a contingent accomplishment as ethno-
methodologists are apt to say.
On this view agents retain their discretion and hence remain
powers: there can be no authorites as I have defined them. All
attempts to create and constrain authorities fail, and putative
authorities remain powers in their own right. The supposed
passive agents of a power actually remain unconstrained and
exercise discretion as they will; the supposed authorities on a text
actually expound it as they will. Here is another admirably
189
Barry Barnes
Conclusion
190
On authority and its relationship to power
191
Barry Barnes
192
On authority and its relationship to power
193
Barry Barnes
Notes
Although he does not himself accept it, Wrong (1979) rightly refers to 'the
familiar dichotomy of "naked" versus "legitimate" or "institutionalised" power,
usually called "authority", which has become such a commonplace in the
sociological literature' (pp. 39-40).
2 Matters of precise verbal definition are not of great significance in the social
sciences; an exaggerated importance is often attributed to them. Martin (1977)
is a writer who lays great emphasis on the importance of precise definition (p.
H). He goes on to criticise a whole series of definitions of 'power'. Dahrendorf
'defines out of existence non-legitimate structural or recurrent power relations'
(p. 36). Weber 'defines ... out of existence' power as a generalised means of
achieving collective goals (p. 37). 'Parsons defines out of existence the problems
which have usually preoccupied sociologists of power' (p. 3H). It rather sounds
as though verbal acts of definition can annihilate sociological phenomena and
sociological problems. But surely all they can actually do is inhibit specific ways
of using particular words, and require the use of other words instead. This, at
any rate, is why I regard problems of verbal definition, including that central to
the present paper, as small problems, and why I see only very limited
possibilities of gain from the criticism of definitions.
3 Amongst the possible exceptions here, Talcott Parsons (1967) is pre-eminent.
4 I talk of agents as the possessors of power not out of conviction, but simply as a
means of dodging for the moment some important further questions about
power. It remains to be considered whether power is better associated with
actors or with roles, and if with actors, whether collective actors may be
involved or only individual actors.
5 There is a presumption here that a routine can be treated as a stable, continuing
entity available at discretion. See also note 9.
6 Needless to say, the acquisition and loss of discretion are complex social
processes, not well thought of in atomistic terms. Loss of discretion often feeds
on itself and multiplies, as does the accumulation of discretion. The
phenomenon should perhaps be called 'the Enobarbus effect' after
Shakespeare's vivid dramatisation in Anthony and Cleopatra.
7 I do not wish to make too much of common usage or to claim that my own
favoured notions accord particularly closely with it. In common usage
'authority' is often used as a synonym for 'power', and to 'authorise' may be to
delegate discretion and hence power, as when someone is authorised to
negotiate, or to draw up and sign a treaty.
H I do not wish to imply that the best policy for a power holder is that of
maximising immediate discretion. On the contrary it will generally be wiser to
settle for less discretion and to empower agents to act on the basis of their own
194
On authority and its relationship to power
judgement. Policies designed to maximise power may be much more risky than
less ambitious ones.
9 The discussion in this paper dodges the most basic issues involved in the
problem of social order by taking the existence of routines for granted, and
speaking merely of the direction of routines. Any developed account of the
nature of power must provide a convincing account of routines and their
stability: see Barnes (1983) for an attempt to provide the beginnings of such an
account.
10 The extensive literature on rule use, following Garfinkel, and textual
deconstruction, following Derrida, is widely cited, although not all those who
have contributed to it take the view that verbal formulations can be interpreted
with complete discretion. For an alternative line of argument which arrives at
closely related conclusions, see Barnes (1982,1984).
11 The model and exemplar for this kind of approach is L. Wittgenstein (1968); see
also Bloor (1983).
12 As before (note 8), I do not wish to imply that it is natural or inevitable for
powers to seek to create passive agents; I only seek to explore the possible
consequences of attempts to do so.
References
Barnes, B. (1982), 'On the Extensions of Concepts and the Growth of Knowledge',
Sociological Review, vol. 3D,no. 1, pp. 23-44.
Barnes, B. (1983), 'Social Life as Bootstrapped Induction', Sociology, vol. 17, no.
4, pp. 524-45.
Barnes, B. (1984), 'The Conventional Component in Knowledge and Cognition', in
N. Stehr and V. Meja (eds), Society and Knowledge, Transaction Books, New
York.
Bloor, D. (1983), Wittgenstein: A Social Theory of Knowledge, Macmillan,
London. .
Martin, R. (1977), The Sociology or Power, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.
Parsons, T. (1967), Sociological Theory and Modern Society, Free Press, New
York.
Wittgenstein, L. (1968), Philosophical Investigations, Blackwell, Oxford.
Wrong, D. (1979), Power, Its Forms, Bases and Uses, Blackwell, Oxford.
195