Law & Corporate Finance
Law & Corporate Finance
Law & Corporate Finance
Edward Elgar
Cheltenham, UK Northampton, MA, USA
Contents
List of gures and tables
1
2
3
4
5
6
vii
1
28
70
110
152
190
223
Index
32
38
TABLES
5.1
5.2
5.3
5.4
5.5
5.6
5.7
5.8
5.9
5.10
5.11
5.12
5.13
5.14
5.15
vii
167
168
169
171
171
172
173
175
177
179
181
182
184
185
186
Justice led criminal charges against Merrill Lynch for assisting Enron in
manipulating its nancial reports. Martha Stewart was convicted for
obstruction of justice associated with her alleged insider trading. The New
York Stock Exchanges chairman and chief executive ocer, Richard
Grasso, was charged with taking excessive remuneration for his position.
Richard Scrushy, CEO of HealthSouth, has been sued for blatantly making
up the numbers in nancial reports for that company. The CEO of Rite Aid
was sentenced to eight years in jail for his part in a long-standing securities
fraud. Enron executives have pled guilty or are on trial as the book is sent
to press.
The corporate scandals of the past decade illustrate the relevance of the
law to our market economy in corporate governance. Clearly, the law is not
a panacea, for it failed to prevent the scandals. Some suggest that the law is
even counterproductive, creating more economic harm than it forestalls by,
for example, leading investors to assume that the law will protect them from
fraud, causing them to fail to be fully vigilant in making investment decisions. Of course, the frequency and severity of such dishonest corporate
behavior might have been far greater in the absence of such laws. Finding
proof of such counterfactuals (what would have happened in the absence
of the law) is impossible, but the net economic eect of corporate and securities law can be analyzed and measured to some extent.
law and of fairness itself. Louis Kaplow and Steven Shavell of Harvard Law
School have argued prominently and at length that the general welfare
and not questions of distributional fairness provide the philosophical
justication for the law.3 This is a well-ventilated philosophical debate that
is beyond the scope of our book. Instead, we simply analyze the extent to
which the law advances the general welfare of a society by facilitating
economic growth, which is surely of some value even if it is not the only
relevant value.
Some might challenge the value of national economic development,
arguing that distributional fairness (whether as corrective justice or egalitarian distribution) should trump overall societal economic wellbeing. The
two objectives are not instrinsically in conict, though. Most would prefer
a fairly distributed large economic pie to a fairly distributed small economic
pie. Others might argue that greater material wellbeing has no intrinsic
philosophical value and may not even enhance utilitarian goals such as
human happiness.4 Those who make this argument, though, are typically
those who enjoy a world of substantial material wellbeing. Those suering
the conditions of poverty seldom demean the value of greater material
wealth. Moreover, there is considerable evidence that, in general, greater
material wellbeing does have a payo in human happiness.5 In any event, it
seems clear that people generally place value on their material welfare, so
this is our primary concern when analyzing the impact of law, especially
corporate law and securities law, upon the economy.
Although economists commonly emphasize the eciency value of
private ordering in advancing societys welfare, they have increasingly
emphasized the role of the law in creating societal wealth. For example,
Douglass North helped create the New Institutional Economics and won
a Nobel Prize for his historical investigation of the importance of legal
institutions in promoting economic growth.6 He declared that the
eectiveness of enforcement of property rights and contracts is . . . the
single most crucial determinant of economic performance . . .7 This economic theory is centrally grounded in analysis of transaction costs, which
this book will discuss extensively. The availability of reasonably reliable
enforcement of appropriate legal rights, by a government with power and
economies of scale, is of considerable benet for enhancing economic
development. This economic analysis is now widely, if not universally,
accepted. The law can serve to facilitate capitalism, which in turn facilitates
economic growth.
One crucial aspect of capitalisms facilitation of economic growth is found
in the ability of individuals to invest their resources productively, proting
the individuals while simultaneously beneting others by creating employment opportunities and societal wealth. Companies need cash or other
They found that stock market liquidity and development of the banking
system were signicantly associated with contemporaneous and future
rates of economic growth, productivity growth and capital accumulation.
Other measures, such as market volatility, showed no countervailing negative eect on economic growth.
The World Bank and other organizations have also investigated the
importance of nancial markets for social welfare, using other methods. A
study examined rm-level data in 30 countries to test the number of rms
with high growth rates that could be attributed to the availability of longterm nancing. The proportion of successful companies was higher in
countries with a more liquid stock market (and better legal systems).10
Another study looked at the size of a countrys credit and equity markets
relative to its overall GDP and its allocation of capital.11 Ecient capital
allocation was signicantly correlated with more developed nancial
sectors. Countries with relatively advanced nancial systems better channeled investment to growing industries and away from declining industries.
Other research found that the government opening up nancial markets in
emerging nations was associated with signicant increases in real economic
growth.12 There is substantial empirical support for the intuitively obvious
claim that better developed nancial markets providing capital to business
are associated with greater economic growth.
While the association between a nations nancial development and its
economic growth is strong, some have questioned the direction of the
causality. They note that nancial development may just be a leading indicator of economic growth, rather than its underlying cause.13 While this is
possible, research has sought to establish directionality by considering legal
origins and other instrumental variables to demonstrate that certain legal
rules are associated with nancial development, which in turn translates
into substantial economic growth.14
The directional causality is further conrmed by historical research. The
earliest decades of the United States saw remarkable growth, both in the
general economy and in the nancial markets. The nancial development
meant that capital from Europe owed into the United States, providing
entrepreneurs and more established businesses with access to nancing.
When this history was subjected to statistical testing, the results clearly indicated that the nancial development was a contributing cause to the nations
great economic growth of the time.15 Studies of the historical evidence from
other countries further conrm the association, nding that nancial development was a causal determinant of the industrial development of the
United States, United Kingdom, Canada, Sweden and Norway.16 Other historical analyses ascribe the eighteenth-century success of Scotland and
Belgium to the remarkable eciency of their capital markets at the time. The
linkage between nancial markets and economic growth has been demonstrated theoretically and empirically. Consequently, strategies for enhancing
nancial markets have become an important part of plans to further economic growth for the benet of the society as a whole.
Much of the research in this area compares countries with dierent
nancial markets, but some research examines nancial development
within particular countries. One study found that the better a countrys
level of nancial development, the more rapid was the growth of those
industries that were typically dependent on external nancing.17 Financial
markets are linked, to some degree, with corporate governance. The quality
of corporate governance among a nations companies contributes to their
economic success. Some empirical research found that European companies with better corporate governance had better earnings-based performance ratios than did those with poorer governance.18 A study in Russia
found a strong correlation between corporate governance quality and rm
valuation.19 A broader McKinsey study found that OECD-based companies with better corporate governance had a higher valuation by 10 percent
or more.20 It is well-established that thriving nancial markets contribute
to national economic success and that quality corporate governance contributes to thriving nancial markets. The key policy question involves the
degree to which the law can facilitate quality corporate governance and
nancial markets.
Today nancial markets in the United States operate subject to extensive legal regulation and control. The connection between some measure
of legal protection and development of nancial systems is increasingly
recognized. The legal protection of property rights enables nancial development, even in the absence of external sources of nance.21 Basic legal
protection of property and contract enforcement facilitates the use of more
external nance. Laws governing corporations and securities transactions
can sometimes do likewise. These eects are a primary focus of this book.
Before analyzing the possible association of such categories of law with
nancial development and economic growth, it is important to summarize
the nature of the basic, corporate and securities laws that govern American
rms.
10
11
rules and provide essentially no law to society. If the courts are starved for
resources, they may be unable to resolve legal disputes, no matter how wellintentioned the judges are. In India, for example, the judicial system is enormously backlogged. There is a clear correlation between limits on Indias
national wealth and the time required for its judicial system to enforce a
judgment.24 One-third of the pending Indian cases began over ten years
earlier; one famous dispute among neighbors took 39 years to resolve and
outsurvived both the parties. If it is inordinately costly for a party to invoke
legal protections, their value will be correspondingly reduced. Creating a
law or even a legal system does not guarantee its eective functioning.
While numerous things may go wrong with the operation of the law, the
legal system functions well in many nations. No national system is awless
but many legal structures operate successfully, given the inherent limits of
humans and institutions. Those who enter contracts, in developed nations
at least, have a reasonable expectation that they can eectively exercise their
legal rights should the contract be breached. Numerous property, contract,
and tort cases are led and typically promptly resolved. Although most
cases are voluntarily settled and not tried, this settlement takes place in
the shadow of the law and is therefore somewhat contingent upon the
function of the legal system. In countries such as the United States, the
functioning basic law is largely taken for granted.
The existence of the basic law is generally presumed, at least in our
modern society. All nation-states have some legal adjudicatory system to
resolve disputes. A true state of anarchy is unknown in the world today.
However, the basic law is not universal in scope and should not be presumed to be a necessary situation for all human dealings. Some transactions are by nature held to be illegal (for example, extortion or dealing in
illegal substances), and the law typically refuses to govern them. The world
of these transactions is often called the underground economy, which
operates alongside but outside the reach of the law. Every nation in the
world has a substantial underground economy, though its size varies considerably among countries.25 Moreover, some actors voluntarily place their
legal transactions outside the rule of the law. Robert Ellickson has demonstrated how cattle ranchers in California have chosen to resolve various disputes, such as trespassing cattle, by private norms rather than using the
available legal system.26 Lisa Bernstein has documented how diamond merchants have opted out of the legal system for resolution of their transactional disputes.27 Even parties that use the law in transactions may not use
it completely. Many agreements provide for some private dispute resolution
mechanism, such as arbitration, rather than courts. Many contracts are
intentionally left incomplete with open-ended terms that the parties intend
to work out voluntarily. Thus, the reach of the law is not universal even in
12
contemporary America. The most signicant fact, though, may be that the
vast majority of businesses voluntarily choose to subject themselves and
their transactions to legal governance, even when they have the choice of
opting out of the legal system.
The legal system appears to oer some value for private transactions.
Basic law is generally considered to be empowering in its recognition of
property rights and its enforcement of contracts, and such law is typically
embraced by even conservative economists. The fundamental law of torts
is generally restrictive in nature, but this nature is limited, to at least some
degree, by the parties ability to contract around the law of torts. This
ability to opt out of various tort law provisions is not universal and is the
source of some economic controversy regarding the tort/contract boundary. While there is an ongoing debate over the intrinsic eciency of
common law rules, the basic law, at least the common law heritage, is generally considered to be, on balance, ecient and empowering.
Corporate Law
Corporate law presents a somewhat more complex case. The basic law of
corporations is generally applauded by even conservative economists as
essentially empowering.28 The establishment of limited liability entities
such as corporations enables individuals to invest their resources productively, while simultaneously limiting the magnitude of the economic risk
faced by those individuals. A corporate investor places his or her invested
funds at risk but is generally free from liability with respect to his or her
other resources. The issuance of corporate shares also facilitates the free
and ecient transferability of ownership interests. This structure oers a
considerable benet, both to the individual and to society as a whole.
Corporate law is primarily created by states, not the federal government. It
is legislative in origin but provides a considerable judicial role, especially
when, as in Delaware (which is far and away the most important jurisdiction), it is largely implemented by the courts of equity rather than those of
law. However, some aspects of corporate law receive criticism as unduly
restrictive, and some economists have argued that companies be given
greater ability to choose among corporations laws or to contract around
their terms.
Corporate law is sometimes conceived as contractarian in nature, as a
deal between the individual and the government. There is no natural right
to the limited liability protections oered by corporate law. From a fairness
perspective, the law may be presented as the governments bestowal of the
benet of limited liability in exchange for an agreement to abide by certain
rules of corporate governance, laid down in the details of the corporate
13
code. The contractarian justication cannot truly explain the law of limited
liability, however. Some limited liability entities, such as limited partnerships, are governed by a law that is much less restrictive than the law of corporations. More centrally, the authorization of limited liability entities is
justied by the benets they provide society, not the private benets to
investors. Limited liability encourages investment, which encourages the
development of new production, with new employment opportunities and
overall economic growth to the benet of society. Consequently, corporate
laws requirements should be determined by their eect on the overall societal welfare not as some sort of payback in exchange for liability protection. Corporate law, thus, should stand or fall on its benets to society.
The essence of corporate law is the limited liability it provides and the
rules for corporate governance that it establishes. To obtain the benets of
limited liability for investors, corporations must abide by the rules of corporate governance law. Entities choose to incorporate within a particular
state and thereby become subject to that jurisdictions distinct corporation
law. In the United States, virtually all companies incorporate either in
Delaware or in their own home state. The incorporation process requires
the development of articles of incorporation (sometimes called the corporate charter or certicate), which is publicly available and becomes something like the constitution that governs the corporation. The law places
some requirements on the contents of these articles but allows considerable
discretion.
The key aspect of corporate law is the allocation of power in the
company among the shareholders, the board of directors, and corporate
ocers. Basic authority rests with the owner/shareholders, who can elect or
remove directors and make certain very fundamental decisions for the
company. The directors supervise the corporations business, though, and
shareholders are not authorized to tinker with the day-to-day managerial
decisions (except indirectly through changes on the board). The directors
hire the ocers who generally manage the company on a day-to-day basis.
Much of corporate law is directed at the potential agency problems that
arise between the shareholders who own the corporation and the directors
and ocers who manage it. The directors and ocers are the agents of the
shareholders and should operate it in their principals best interest. Like all
individuals, though, directors and ocers have their own self-interests that
they may advance at the expense of the shareholders interests. Corporate
law aims to restrain the self-interested actions of directors and ocers
through the imposition of certain duciary duties that are owed to shareholders. Unconstrained, directors and ocers might act selshly or foolishly. The duty of loyalty is to ensure that ocers do not enrich themselves
at the expense of shareholders, by self-dealing or usurping the business
14
15
for more private ordering in this context. Corporate law, like partnership
law, provides a basic set of default rules that can be substantially altered by
the owners so long as third parties are not prejudiced. Partnership law provides somewhat more scope for entities to opt out of the legal rules, though.
For corporations, many of the default rules are also binding rules.
For example, in Delaware, individual directors may be exculpated from
personal liability for breach of the duty of care, though not for breach of
the duty of loyalty. Corporations also may buy insurance to protect their
directors and ocers from the risk of great personal liability. Companies
may issue preferred shares, which are largely ruled by their certicate of
designations, even when its terms conict with some aspects of the general
corporate law. Thus, corporate law, while it contains multiple restrictive
components, allows considerable space for private ordering of investment
contracts.
Securities Law
Securities law is even more controversial from the perspective of economists. Much of securities law, and certainly its more controversial elements,
is fundamentally restrictive. Securities law, for example, often prohibits corporate ocers from proting from their positions by trading in securities
based on their nonpublic information about their companies, a practice
known as insider trading, and securities law also creates liability for material misrepresentations of fact made by companies and their ocers and
directors. The restrictive provision of securities law relating to fraud claims
has been considered excessive by some and their potency was reduced by
legislative action in the 1990s, under the Private Securities Litigation
Reform Act of 1995 (PSLRA) and the subsequent Securities Litigation
Uniform Standards Act of 1998 (SLUSA). Perhaps ironically, these were
federal level legislative actions directed in part at judicial interpretations
regarded as excessively restrictive. The fundamental disclosure, fraud prevention and governance requirements of securities remained intact following PSLRA and SLUSA, however, notwithstanding signicant academic
and political criticism.
US federal securities law developed during the Great Depression, following the stock market crash of 1929, as is described further in Chapter 4
(though various state regulations of securities preceded this federal legislation). The initial major federal law in the area was the Securities Act of
1933. This law basically governs the initial issuance of securities, rather
than transactions in already-issued shares. To issue such shares, a company
must either le an extensive registration statement with the SEC and transmit to potential investors a prospectus, or must nd an exemption in the
16
statute. The 1933 Act and SEC rules promulgated pursuant to it have
detailed and extensive disclosure requirements, including provision of
audited nancial statements. The Securities Act also created a system of liability when the registration statement and prospectus contain materially
false information. Like most other federal securities laws, the 1933 Acts
provisions are enforced both by the government and by private parties. The
SEC can bring civil proceedings to punish violations. The Department of
Justice can le criminal charges against intentional violators. And often
investors who have suered economic injury as a consequence of violations
of the Act may bring civil damage actions against various wrongdoers.
Securities law was soon expanded with the passage of the Securities
Exchange Act of 1934, which created the Securities Exchange Commission.
While the Securities Act focused on the initial sale of securities to the
public, the Exchange Act focused on the secondary securities markets.
Realizing that companies sell new securities only infrequently and therefore
would seldom be required to le 1933 Act registration statements, Congress
provided that major public corporations would have to le periodic reports
to keep investors updated as to their nancial status. As those requirements
have evolved, they now require public companies to le annual, quarterly,
and periodic statements with the SEC as well as to transmit annual reports
to shareholders. Again, the 1934 Act and attendant SEC rules contain comprehensive and detailed disclosure requirements. One of the major controversies of securities law, and one that we shall address in this book, is
whether the disclosure requirements of the 1933 Securities Act and the
1934 Exchange Act are necessary. Many argue that issuers and investors
would voluntarily bargain to an optimal level of disclosure in the absence
of these disclosure requirements. Another relevant question is whether the
rules require too much disclosure and disclosure of the right kind.
The 1934 Exchange Act does much more than require periodic reporting
by public companies. It contains a broad antifraud provision, section 10(b),
now supplemented by SEC Rule 10b-5, that punishes false statements and
misleading omissions made in those periodic reports and in other communications by issuers, their ocers and directors, and other buyers and sellers
of securities. As with the 1933 Act, violations of section 10(b)/Rule 10b-5
can be punished by SEC administrative and civil actions, by criminal
charges brought by the SEC and by investors civil damage actions, often
brought as class actions. These lawsuits are quite controversial. Many
believe that they represent a terrible abuse of the legal process and prot
primarily plaintis attorneys at a tremendous cost to public companies
and their ocers, directors, auditors, attorneys and investment bankers
who are often defendants in such lawsuits. As noted earlier, the PSLRA of
1995 and SLUSA of 1998 were passed to make it harder for plainti
17
investors to win such suits and for plaintis attorneys to prot from bringing them. The controversial nature of the suits is highlighted by the fact that
some observers have concluded that the PSLRA and SLUSA sent a
message to ocers, directors, auditors, and others that they did not need to
take securities fraud liability seriously and indirectly created the atmosphere of abuse that spawned the Enron debacle and related scandals. Such
suits may be considered either a destructive abuse of the law or a necessary
supplement to enforcement by an often undermanned SEC.
The Exchange Act also registers and regulates stock brokers and dealers.
It regulates stock exchanges and authorizes self-regulation of securities
professionals by organizations such as the New York Stock Exchange
(NYSE) and the National Association of Securities Dealers (NASD). The
Exchange Act also includes provisions that aect corporate governance by
creating disclosure requirements for proxy solicitations when shareholders
are asked to vote for directors at annual meetings and for extraordinary
corporate transactions such as mergers at special meetings. False statements made in proxy solicitations, whether by incumbent directors, insurgent shareholders, or others, can be punished under section 10(b), if
intentional, and under section 14(a) even if only negligently made.
The Exchange Act was amended by the Williams Act in 1968 to regulate
tender oers, in which a corporate acquirer makes a public oer to all corporate shareholders of a target company to buy their shares, usually in
order to take control of the company. An unregulated tender oer provides
opportunities for abuse, including coercion by the oering party, manipulation and self-dealing by management of the target company, and undue
secrecy and fraud by all parties involved. As in so many other areas, federal
regulation of tender oers requires full disclosure of relevant information,
punishes fraud, and adds various substantive and procedural provisions
designed to rationalize the process and give target shareholders an opportunity to digest the disclosed information.
The insider trading provisions of the Exchange Act are particular controversial. Corporate directors, ocers and other insiders will be privy to
some nonpublic information about the company that could signicantly
aect the value of its stock. This information might involve imminent
events such as a lucrative merger oer, positive or negative government
action, or a major technological breakthrough that will likely result in a
valuable patent being granted. Buying or selling shares on this inside information can enable the insider to reap large gains after the information
becomes public and the market price reacts to disclosure of the information. In most cases, this practice was not illegal under the basic law or corporate law but under the Exchange Act, such trading by insiders on
nonpublic information is usually unlawful.
18
19
OVERLAP
The Sarbanes-Oxley Acts incursions into the realm of corporate governance demonstrate that the basic law, corporate law, and securities law
overlap and intersect, as is most clearly illustrated by the law of fraud. The
basic law has long recognized fraud claims which have the following basic
elements: (1) a false statement of fact (or sometimes an omission); (2) made
with knowledge of its falsity, or scienter; (3) reasonable reliance on the false
statement by the plainti; and (4) consequent damages. This law is general
and applies in numerous contexts, including corporate investments. Many
common law fraud cases are brought in the United States and many
succeed, but proof of scienter may be quite dicult, and proof of reasonable reliance may also prove troublesome. In some contexts, false factual
statements may be actionable with a lower standard, such as negligent misrepresentation, but these contexts are limited ones.
Corporate law generally does not have a distinct law of fraud, but its law
of duciary duties overlaps the law of fraud. Fraudulent behavior directed
toward a companys shareholders will typically violate the duciary duties
of loyalty, due care or disclosure. Fiduciary law has various advantages
over the law of fraud for the prospective plainti. It has a much relaxed
standard for scienter, extends to actions that are not misrepresentations
and therefore require no reliance, and in some circumstances even shifts the
burden of proof to the defendant to justify his or her actions. Corporate
duciary law also allows large groups of shareholder plaintis to join
together in a single lawsuit, which provides eciency benets and may
strengthen the chance of success. This law does have one major procedural
obstacle, however. In general, these breaches harm the corporation and, in
general, shareholders can recover only derivatively for the reduced value of
20
the corporation. Unless the board is clearly biased or displayed no reasonable business judgment, such a derivative action requires that the potential
plainti shareholder rst make a demand on the board, which may choose
not to pursue even a legitimate legal claim, as not being in the corporations
best interests. Fiduciary law is also limited to the existing shareholders of a
company (and not necessarily all of them), so a number of injured parties
may be unable to sue. A purchaser of stock generally has no corporate law
remedy for fraud that occurred prior to the purchase.
Securities law has its own laws of fraud, the elements of which, as noted
above, roughly trace those of the common law. The key fraud provision is
found in section 10(b) of the Exchange Act, and it adds some additional
requirements to the common law elements of fraud, such as the necessity
that the fraudulent statement be made in the context of the purchase or sale
of securities (such that those who fail to buy or sell due to fraud cannot
sue). Section 10(b) also adds a more rigorous requirement that the false
statement be material. The law of securities fraud has relaxed other
common law elements, though. Under the traditional common law, a
plainti must have seen or heard the statement and directly relied on it.
Under contemporary securities law, a plainti can sue for fraud without
having read or directly relied on the statement, because the fraud presumably was read and relied on by others and incorporated in the market price
of the stock under the ecient market theory. This presumption of reliance
enables vast numbers of investors who have never relied upon, read, nor
even seen corporate misstatements to proceed via a class action which may
produce extremely large total damages. Such class actions are less available
under the common law because of the individualized reliance requirement.
With the reliance presumptions of securities law, the common questions of
falsity and scienter predominate, so the class action device may be available.
Securities law also functionally strengthens the law of fraud because the
securities laws have such extensive disclosure requirements. The many disclosures create more opportunities to sue for false statements or for omissions, when the disclosures contained only half truths. Securities law also
provides potential liability for fraud through market manipulation that
may not directly involve a misrepresentation of fact. The Securities Act of
1933 also contains some provisions that are relevant to securities fraud,
which have much more relaxed standards of proof but are also much more
limited in their scope.
The common law, corporate law and securities law of fraud thus overlap
in part but have distinguishing attributes as well. These alternative paths
generally strengthen legal protections, because a plainti may avail himself
or herself of whatever legal regime oers the best chance of success and
may usually sue on any or all theories simultaneously. The various
21
OUTLINE OF CHAPTERS
The second chapter of this book examines the economics of these legal
rules from a classical economic perspective. The economic justication for
legal institutions revolves around transaction costs. In the absence of the
22
23
suggests that individuals will make the choice (such as the investment) that
oers the most lucrative benets, after calculating probable risks, prospects,
and associated costs of action. The rational choice paradigm is convenient
for modeling and surely contains some element of truth. People generally
prefer more money to less, all other things being equal, and will make the
choice that provides more money. However, the rational choice model may
fail to account for human frailties. Investors are not calculating robots and
they may be inuenced by various irrational factors in their choice. A
mountain of experimental psychological research has identied some of
these irrational factors, which may produce a systematic distortion of
random decisionmaking, not just random mistakes.
Our knowledge of these psychological inuences on human decisionmaking can help inform our choice of ecient legal and nancial systems.
To the extent that people have systematic psychological biases or use potentially unreliable psychological shortcuts called heuristics, the law can help
oset these features and nudge markets toward more ecient, fair outcomes. In the absence of any such eect, market participants will enter into
unwise, inecient transactions that benet neither themselves nor society
more broadly. While all humans, including government regulators and
judges, are subject to these cognitive limitations, it may be possible to
design structures that minimize their eects, and the corporate and securities laws can represent just such structures.
The fourth chapter of the book examines in more detail the history of
legal regulation of the rm in the United States. The basic legal system of
property, contract, and tort predates the American Revolution, as the
United States employed the traditional practices and precedents of
English common law, and these laws provided some governance for business of the era, including the development of duciary law. State corporate law traces its origins to the earliest days of our nation, and much of
the early law restricted the activities that corporations could undertake.
Delaware passed an empowering corporate law in 1899 that allowed
companies much greater freedom in designing their certicates and
provoked a wave of reincorporation in that state. Since that time,
Delaware has sought a balance of empowering and restrictive rules and
maintained its status as the preeminent state of major incorporations in
the United States.
The story of the development of federal securities law forms a central
part of the history in this chapter. For most of American history, the nation
had successful markets in corporate securities without any governing
federal securities law. The Securities Act and Exchange Act were promulgated in the 1930s, to respond to particular patterns of behavior that
were considered abusive. The requirements of securities law have developed
24
considerably since that time, though, under the implementing actions of the
SEC and the development of the law in court decisions. Two constant
themes of federal securities regulation have been that fraud is bad and that
greater disclosure is good. A focus of this book will be upon whether those
two guidelines have produced good or ill for Americas nancial markets
and economic wellbeing. The recognition of a private right of action over
and above government enforcement, enabling investors to bring their own
suits, considerably enhanced the impact of securities law, though these
private actions have been quite controversial and allegedly contrary to the
welfare of securities markets.
The fth chapter of the book embarks on an empirical study of the
eect of the law on nancial markets and economic wellbeing. This association has now been the subject of various economic cross-country
studies, using many dierent dependent and independent variables, which
has generally shown a positive eect for the legal system and particular
legal rules. While these studies make a persuasive case for the value of the
law, they have been conducted by economists and have not successfully
captured legal variables. In many cases, they have used overly simplistic
binary variables for the law, or have ignored legal procedure for legal substance, or vice versa.
We do not replicate this considerable and impressive past research but
seek to build upon it. Our empirical analysis uses some of the same variables as in prior studies but adds variables to better capture the substantive
and procedural features of national legal systems. The chapter seeks to integrate the ndings of the prior research by incorporating its various independent variables (the dierent measures of legal governance of the rm)
and dependent variables (the dierent measures of nancial and broader
economic outcomes). The chapter demonstrates how various legal requirements, including some of the restrictive requirements, have a positive
impact on various measures of economic wellbeing.
The sixth chapter of the book turns to contemporary academic and
political controversies regarding the proper legal regulation of rms. In the
wake of the nancial scandals discussed above, the public has often
demanded greater legal regulation of companies, as reected in legislation
such as the Sarbanes-Oxley Act. By contrast, a number of conservative academics have made more rigorous economic arguments for the value of less
regulation of corporations and securities markets, in the interest of enhancing nancial markets. We analyze these recommendations, based on the
theory and empirical ndings of the prior chapters.
Most of the proposals involve greater market choice for companies or
investors, based on the presumption that restrictive statutory requirements
limit valuable exchanges. These proposals include:
25
NOTES
1.
2.
26
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
18.
19.
20.
21.
22.
23.
24.
25.
26.
27.
28.
27
29
is a form of transaction cost, though, which adds to the cost of the bargain
and will be discussed below in greater detail. Absent blind trust, a party
must undertake the costs of investigating the trustworthiness of a potential
partner. Market transaction costs include costs of information, bargaining/negotiation over transactions, contracting (formal or informal), monitoring and enforcement of agreements, and search and information costs.1
The virtue of legal regulation comes largely from a reduction in these costs.
30
31
32
Figure 2.1
Honesty
Opportunism
Invest
2,2
2,4
Dont
Invest
0,0
0,0
inuence either decision. In this gure, the rst number represents the gain
or loss for the investor, the second gure the gain or loss for the other party.
In this simplied model, the investor has no opportunity to cheat and the
estimated payos are articially set (though the exact numbers do not
dictate the results, so long as the relative relationship is not altered).
If there is no contract, neither party sustains any economic eect, hence
the result of 0,0. If the contract is performed successfully, each gains from
the exchange in the amount 2,2. If the investor invests and the other party
is opportunistic, the investor is a net loser of its investment (2), while the
opportunistic party is a big gainer (4). The best strategy for the noninvestor party, in this single play scenario, is to be opportunistic. Of course,
the investor realizes that the preferred strategy for the other party is to be
opportunistic, which causes a loss to the investor, so the investor, in anticipation of this opportunism, has a dominant strategy of not investing in
the rst place. Of course, people do sometimes invest even in the absence of
any legal protection and others are honest, by nature, even though opportunism might oer them greater returns. However, if honesty is not
rewarded by an economic system, opportunism will be more common and
investment will be risky and less frequent. Consequently, the greatest societal loss from uncontrolled or undeterred opportunism is not in the costs
of the opportunism itself, the greatest loss lies in the transactions that do
not occur, because of fear of rational opportunism that prevents the risk of
transactions.
The possible escape from this Prisoners Dilemma involves the prospect
of repeated interactions. In the above gure, the opportunistic party gets a
one-shot gain of 4 but presumably no future investments from the investor,
as he will be shunned as an untrustworthy business partner. An honest
party, by contrast, may gain a series of repeated investments, yielding
benets of the gains from trade (2) times the frequency of these repeated
investments, which might seem to be a more lucrative strategy than that of
one-shot opportunism. Consequently, the investor would see that the better
33
strategy for the other party was honesty, to induce a string of repeated
investments, and would therefore risk the investment.
The eect of repeated transactions does not truly cure the Prisoners
Dilemma, however. At a formal level, economists have demonstrated that
the repeat transactions theory depends on innite repetition of these transactions. Otherwise, cooperation will unravel from the end.13 There would
always be an incentive for opportunism in the nal transaction, which
would deter investment in the nal transaction, which would in turn create
the incentive for opportunism in the penultimate transaction, which would
in turn deter investment in that transaction, and so on back to the original
transaction. Thus, rational game theory calls the reliance on repeat transactions into question.
There are other problems with the repeated transaction solution as well.
The rst problem is the articial presumption that the opportunistic party
cannot engage in repeated transactions with even higher payos. Even if the
opportunist is shunned by the rst investor, he or she may nd other
suckers. In a very small community, one or two instances of gross opportunism might prevent a party from doing any future business. However, in a
larger, more anonymous, community, the individual might succeed in a
series of multiple lucrative opportunistic transactions, reaping the benet of
4, every time the honest party would reap a benet of only 2. For example,
consider the serial con-men who have ourished over time, selling everything from snake oil to shares in uranium mines and other penny stocks.
Nobel Laureate George Akerlof analyzed this point in his famous
article, The Market for Lemons.14 He shows how in purely private ordering
bad products, such as used cars, can drive out good products, in cases where
sellers have more information on product quality than do buyers. Likewise
dishonest dealings tend to drive honest dealings out of the market.15 The
consequences of this phenomenon are not limited to the dishonest dealings
themselves. In a dishonest market, there will be far fewer transactions and
those that occur will be at a higher cost.
Inevitable detection problems also undermine the repeated transactions
answer to the Prisoners Dilemma. Opportunism need not be gross and
immediately obvious. A party might engage in more subtle opportunism
that took some time to discover, which would enable the party to reap the
benets of a good reputation and consequent repeat transactions and also
some benets of opportunism. A manager might cook the books and
make it appear as if he was honest, when he was not. Even with honest
accounting, if a corporation suers adverse results, it may be unclear for
some time whether they were simply the consequence of random chance or
opportunism and whether the results are likely to continue in the future. In
addition, an opportunistic party might succeed in maintaining anonymity,
34
behind a corporate shell or other entity, so that investors are unaware that
they may be dealing with a party who has a track record of dishonest,
opportunistic behavior. The parties who are best able and most likely to
engage in opportunism may be precisely the same ones who are best able and
most likely to cover up this behavior, in order to continue proting from it.
These detection problems are greater than they might rst appear. The
above discussion has presumed that the existence of opportunism was clear,
and parties only had to take the time to discover which parties had behaved
opportunistically. In practice, though, the opportunistic party can try to
cover its tracks, and it may even try to shift the blame to the other party,
claiming that the innocent party was truly the opportunistic one. If the
party succeeds, it will accrue the benets of both opportunism and reputational benets. The claims of a lawsuit are commonly met with counterclaims alleging that the plainti was the party who truly breached the
contract. A key benet of an eective legal system is the sorting out of the
claims and the identication of the true opportunistic party. In this manner,
the legal system does not replace but can signicantly enhance the
eectiveness of reputational sanctions. Without such a system, parties
would have to bear the considerable expense of conducting their own
private mini-trials to identify untrustworthy parties before the fact. This
investigation itself would seem to evidence suspicion and mistrust, before
the relationship even began.
The claim that the law undermines or crowds out trust is nave about the
inherent goodness of human nature and relies on largely undemonstrated
assumptions. The discussion of the nature of business trust is also too simplistic, as if the issue were only trust or not trust. In real business relationships, the more relevant question is To what degree should I trust?
Entities may make sensitive proprietary information available to others,
evidencing trust, while simultaneously retaining various protections for
their rights, evidencing some measure of distrust. Business research indicates that typical relationships contain a blend of trust and distrust.16 The
law enables parties to trust, without trusting absolutely and retaining some
protection against opportunism. In addition, businesses have various
potential partners and must decide not just to trust but also whom to trust,
among the alternatives. The law can facilitate both these decisions involving how much to trust and whom to trust.
Without the law, investors have to rely upon their own private investigation of investment quality and negotiate protection for their future interest. Investment contracts are particularly ill-suited to such eorts. It is more
dicult for investors to inspect a business than a physical good. The costs
of the investigation may be considerable and the eciency of securities
markets may depend on the ability of investors to be passive. Investors
35
benet from diversifying their portfolios but with added transaction costs
for each additional potential investment, such diversication can become
quite expensive. To the extent that the law can reduce the need for such
investigation or facilitate inexpensive investigation, it can enhance capital
markets.
The development of capitalist economies in post-communist states oers
a valuable test case for the role of law in market transactions. Research in
the relatively new economies of Eastern Europe has demonstrated that law
and trust are complementary rather than antagonistic. The researchers surveyed the eect of the law and legal institutions on the success of commercial transactions and considered the eect of relational contracting and
various legal measures.17 For commercial transactions, it found that the
variables capturing the possibilities for forming long-term relationships do
not appear to be as important as the law-related variables.18 A separate
study of Eastern Europe found that eective courts perceptibly increased
the level of trust in business transactions.19 Reliance on reputation and
repeat transactions apparently does not promote business trust as well as
does legal protection.
Despite the inherent limitations of exclusively private ordering, the
nature of the repeat play scenario of the Prisoners Dilemma, where parties
can benet from establishing a reputation for honesty, undoubtedly can
have some positive economic eect, especially in relatively small communities. It is distinctly possible that in small societies, where individuals know
one another well, legal restrictions simply add unnecessary xed costs to
the trusting equation. Drafting detailed contracts and complying with legal
rules and enforcing litigation certainly have their costs. In small, relatively
homogenous societies these costs may be unnecessary because private dealings can provide sucient incentive for honest business behavior.
Even some larger societies may rely on relationship-based systems. The
East Asian countries that had such economic success in the late twentieth
century relied heavily on relationship investing. These nations were not
pure cases of relational trust, because they had powerful governments that
directed the relational business. Nevertheless, they relied on interlocking
relational investments among business partners rather than more anonymous stock markets.20 Even in these nations, relational governance can
only go so far and as economies grow, relational governance can become
much more costly than rule-based governance.21 As economies grow, relational systems are also more vulnerable to crises. Because they are much less
transparent, serious problems in the relationship remain secret until they
have reached enormous proportions. Consequently, investors may not be
able to observe the change in the relation until the advent of a crisis, and
then panic erupts, as in fact occurred in the East Asian economies.22
36
37
38
Figure 2.2
Honesty
Opportunism
Invest
2,2
1,1
Dont
Invest
0,0
0,0
cell would be 0,0, as there would be no litigation costs but the rescission
would restore the parties to the dont invest scenario.
This gure illustrates the value of the law for encouraging transactions.
Now the dominant strategy for both parties is investment and honest performance of the contract. Both are better o than they would be with any
other combination of opportunism or failure to invest. Of course, the cells
of this gure assume that the law works perfectly. If this were so, one would
never actually see opportunism, which is an inevitably inferior strategy. It
is obvious that fraudulent opportunistic behavior continues to exist in our
world, even in the presence of legal constraints. The law does not work perfectly and parties may believe that they can get away with some forms of
opportunism. Some undoubtedly do, but the existence of legal enforcement
and liability awards must materially increase the risk of opportunistic
behavior and thereby shift the cost-benet calculus in the direction of
Figure 2.2.
The critics of the law could counter that the above economic model
ignores aective trust and basic human trustworthiness. In consequence,
the model overstates the need for external law and ignores the risk that the
law could crowd out extralegal trust among parties. Some defenders of
economic models, like Oliver Williamson, essentially claim that there is no
such thing as aective trust and might therefore sco at this answer. Neither
approach eectively captures reality. While Williamsons theory, that all
decisionmaking is cognitive and rational, might have validity, it does not
capture the reality of trust. Individuals often choose to trust others without
making a conscious cognitive assessment, based on some shorthand heuristic of trustworthiness (for example, he is a family member) that may or may
not have cognitive validity. This is what passes for aective trust, but such
aective trust may be easily exaggerated. There are untrustworthy people
throughout the world and the person who easily gives up aective trust is
sure to suer from dealings with the untrustworthy. Such an event might be
expected to lower the level of aective trust that person gives in the future.
39
40
41
against that of Chung Hu, a Houston stockbroker who warned his clients
to get out of Enron stock and was red by UBS Paine Webber for upsetting the Enron executives.31 The shortcomings of reliance on intermediaries
is expanded in Chapters 3 and 4. It does not appear as if brokerage intermediaries oer a reliable solution to managerial opportunism.
The problems with these entities is not conned to the recent market
bubble. Informational intermediaries have had a very mixed historical track
record in providing private monitoring. Consider the credit-rating agencies,
such as Standard & Poors. Unfortunately, as Frank Partnoy has pointed
out, those agencies performed abysmally in the 1990s.32 He noted that
[t]he last ones to react, in every case, were the credit-rating agencies, which
downgraded companies only after all the bad news was in, frequently just
days before a bankruptcy ling.33 Jonathan Macey suggests that creditrating agencies are essentially captured by the rms they rate because
their ratings can have such a signicant negative impact upon the rated
companies that the agencies are extremely reluctant to downgrade credit
ratings thus detonating a corporate nuclear bomb.34
Accounting rms represent a particularly crucial informational intermediary in the modern economy through corporate auditing. It might seem as
if these rms could serve as valuable and reliable intermediaries. Companies
hire auditors in order to demonstrate to investors that their books are accurate and hence have an incentive to hire auditors with a reputation for
scrupulous accuracy. Accounting rms consequently would have an incentive to maintain that reputation through honest auditing, even without any
government regulation. The case is not so clear, though, once one considers
counteracting incentives for opportunism. An auditing rm may have other,
more lucrative sources of revenue, such as consulting, and may nd it
protable to compromise accurate auditing in order to maintain that
revenue stream.35 Even if the rm as a whole had an incentive to maintain
an impeccable reputation, individual partners in the rm may have an incentive to cheat, to preserve their client base and compensation from the rm.36
Accounting rms may be able to get away with opportunism and still retain
reputational benets, due to detection problems. The Generally Accepted
Accounting Principles are rife with room for auditing judgment calls. The
actual quality of an audit can be very dicult to ascertain.37 Thus, an
auditor can mask opportunism as a debatable discretionary judgment. Even
if the auditors themselves were scrupulously honest, rms have some opportunity to mislead their auditors. They exert substantial control over the
information provided to auditors and even the most determined auditor
usually cannot detect a well-organized fraudulent scheme. Even when auditors do detect the scheme, the client management often escapes serious reputational damage by blaming the wrongdoing on rogue employees.
42
43
for such time-consuming development of reputation comes high entry barriers, whether for the transacting rms themselves or the private monitoring intermediaries. As a consequence, such markets will tend to be highly
concentrated or even monopolistic. As a result, use of private systems will
have to pay the higher costs of monopoly rents, which may include some
opportunistic behavior on the part of the monopolist. The high sunk costs
of reputational systems have still another serious economic shortcoming in
adapting to change. If a new technology of a given technical superiority
becomes available, a relation-based system will be slower to adopt it than a
rule-based system, because the incumbents sunk stake in the prior technology provides less gain from switching to the newer technology, and barriers to entry prevent new competitors from arising and using the new
technology.39
Legal systems have some of the same sunk costs as private monitoring
and enforcement systems. These costs are only justied if they are not
unduly great and if the legal systems are suciently eective in practice. It
takes some time for legal systems to establish their societal utility. Once they
do so, they can produce the benets oered by the law but legal systems also
may be resistant to change and use of new technology. However, the government as monopolist monitoring intermediary has advantages over
private monopolist intermediaries, at least when the government is a democratic one. A private monopolist has concern only for the welfare of itself
(or its owners) and not the general societal welfare. A government, by contrast, has some concern for the overall societal welfare. Government ocials
will have some incentive to take some monopoly rents from this process, say
in the form of nicer oce furnishings. Democratic governance limits the
amount of this action, though. A casual glance demonstrates that oce
appointments of the managers of private industry, not to mention their
salaries, considerably exceed those of most high level government ocers.
The government may also oer eciency benets from economies of scale
beyond those of even large private monopolies. The government, of course,
is susceptible to private rent-seeking, as would be a private intermediary
institution, but transparent democratic governance limits this eect.40
Government enforcement through general revenues also oers other
benets to economic development. Private institutions cannot minimize
transaction costs as readily as can the government.41 Although reliance on
a private monopolist intermediary has lower transaction costs than a
system where each party must independently investigate all its partners,
those parties will still be required to pay the signicant costs of private
intermediary enforcement. This system might seem more ecient than that
of a government, because it internalizes the transaction costs among the
parties to the deal. However, economic development and successful capital
44
markets have enormous societal benets in the form of positive externalities. The entire society benets from economic growth, over and above the
prots gleaned by the parties. Consequently, to align social welfare with
private welfare, it is appropriate that some of the costs of transactions, such
as government enforcement, be spread throughout the society.
When ex ante intermediation protection against opportunism fails, a post
facto remedy is valuable, both for particular victims and for future deterrence. Purely private post facto enforcement has problems that go beyond
private monitoring through intermediaries. Private parties in the United
States commonly take disputes out of the court system, to arbitration, for
resolution. They do so with the knowledge that such arbitration awards will
generally be enforced much as would a courts decree. Without the government enforcement that comes with law, some private enforcement mechanism for private dispute resolution would be necessary. Such private
enforcement mechanisms exist today, for contracts outside the law or where
the law is ineective.
Throughout history, organized crime has performed functions such as
contract enforcement when the law is absent or ineective. Indeed, the
Maa itself may have arisen because the collapse of feudalism left Sicily
without any state authority to enforce deals.42 Where legal enforcement is
weak, organized crime has often lled the gap.43 The breakdown of government enforcement in Russia and Eastern Europe led to use of organized
crime to enforce contracts. In Latin America, shortcomings in the judicial
system have led to the use of justicieros to enforce private justice. In Japan,
the yakuza mobsters are used to enforce contracts and extract payments for
torts, when weaknesses in the legal system render it inadequate. Private
reliance on organized crime for enforcement would seem clearly inferior to
that of government, if only because government has a greater interest in
overall public welfare, while the interests of organized crime are merely
private.
Under some circumstances, private relational governance may be superior to legal rule-based governance. In small, simple economies, the costs
of creating and enforcing legal rules may exceed their benets. Once
economies grow larger and more complex, however, this is no longer the
case. In the United States of the nineteenth century, there was a steady evolution from informal to formal legal governance of business contracts and
rms. Between 1840 and 1920, the relational trust-based governance was
slowly supplanted by institutional trust based on law, as the economy grew
and the relational governance became inecient.44 The East Asian
economies of the latter part of the twentieth century underwent a similar
evolution.45 Developed economies are clearly past the tipping point, where
legal regulation adds eciency. With the increased globalization of the
45
46
47
48
Limited liability reduces the magnitude of investor risk, but investors may
still suer great losses from corporate opportunism, as in the case of Enron.
A legal rule can enhance eciency by reducing the need for investors
to engage in costly and continuous monitoring of their managerial agents
actions.
There are valid arguments about the costs associated with compulsory
corporate rules. Rule enforcement inevitably has its costs. Dierent entities
have dierences in their basic businesses and in the identities of their
owners and managers and therefore may have dierent optimal governance
arrangements. Forcing certain commonalities upon these entities means
foregoing optimality, in at least some circumstances. But this added cost of
uniform legal rules only exists if one presumes that the owners and managers of these entities would nd and adopt the optimal governance rules,
in the absence of the law, a presumption that is not self-evident in light of
the agency problems of the rm. Merely identifying the rules could involve
considerable transaction cost that is avoided by the legal structure. The economic value of compulsory corporate rules will depend on the extent of the
agency problems in a purely private ordering, transaction costs, and on the
quality of the rules themselves, not some a priori abstract analysis of a perfectly functioning world without any agency and transaction cost problems.
The development of corporate law has reected recognition of this
tradeo between the risks of opportunism and the costs of legal intervention into corporate decisionmaking. The widely adopted business judgment rule gives great deference to the decisions of corporate ocers and
directors. It dictates that courts will not intervene in corporate decisionmaking when a plainti alleges a breach of the agents duty of care, unless
the breach appears especially egregious. This rule recognizes the costs of
legal second-guessing, balanced against the risk of agent misbehavior. The
true dangers of opportunism lie not in breaching the duty of care, however.
The duty of loyalty is the duciary duty at issue in the typical case of
opportunism, with agents proting at the expense of their principals. If the
entire board has a conict of interest, or is dominated by an individual with
a conict of interest, the court will give much stricter scrutiny to the corporate decision. The law thus strikes a balance between the value of controlling opportunism and the costs of excessive oversight. Of course, the
optimality of this balance is debatable and some have suggested that corporate law fails because it is too deferential to free management choice.55
The private voluntary choice of rms to adopt the corporate form provides something of a natural experiment that demonstrates the eciency of
the balance struck by corporate law. The law oers limited liability options
for investors, other than the corporation. Limited partnerships and limited
liability companies (LLCs) both provide such limited liability. These
49
alternative forms have their own state enabling laws that are typically less
restrictive than is corporate law. Consequently, they oer greater opportunity for arranging governance contractually, rather than by law. If such
private contractual governance were more ecient, one might expect
investors to ood to these alternative limited liability entities. And while
LLCs and other such entities have become increasingly popular for small
business organizations, corporations retain their preeminent role among
large business enterprises.56
Another criticism of restrictive corporate laws lies in claims of
ineciency arising from the laws ineectiveness. Easterbrook and Fischel
argue that the general availability of private contractual ordering means
that managerial opportunism is like a balloon that, when constricted in one
place, merely expands in another. They thus suggest that if corporate law
should forbid managers to divert corporate opportunities to themselves,
they might respond by drawing higher salaries or working less hard to open
up new business opportunities.57 At some level, this claim surely has truth.
The law does not extinguish the incentives for opportunism, and corporate
ocers certainly have been known to take excessive salaries. However, the
claim falls far short of invalidating restrictive corporate law, for two
reasons. First, the two forms of opportunism are not exclusive, that is, a
manager might both usurp corporate opportunities and take a higher
salary, absent the legal restrictions. The law might therefore reduce opportunism to some degree by eliminating one channel. Second, dierent forms
of opportunism present very dierent monitoring problems and associated
transaction costs for shareholders. The ocers cash salary is transparent
and easy to monitor, whereas the ocers usurpation of corporate opportunities is more dicult for shareholders to observe and hence a more
appropriate subject for legal deterrence. The corporate law sensibly restricts
the latter opportunism more than the former, because salaries are relatively
more amenable to control through private ordering. Prevailing standards
of corporate law do not fully displace private ordering; Delaware law is
empowering in many cases and, when restrictive, can operate to help overcome market ineciencies in controlling managerial opportunism.
Corporate law can also play an important clarifying function for business relationships, as in the case of contract formalization. An agent automatically assumes some duciary responsibility to the principal, but the
precise nature of the relationship may be obscure, absent the dened standards of corporate law. A duciary has some duty to disclose facts to shareholders but the reach of the duty may be uncertain. A duciary has a duty
of loyalty, but whether that duty is breached at the margin may be uncertain. Even in an atmosphere of trust, a misunderstanding about the scope
of these duties could prevent ecient investment decisions and interfere
50
with the relationship between investors and managers. The law can facilitate this relationship by clarifying expectations.
Corporate law is not absolutely necessary for legal governance of the
principal/agent relationship, as parties may contract the specic details of
the relationship. This individual contracting, though, adds to transaction
costs, as the parties hammer out the details of their relationship. The
parties must decide the terms they desire and the extent to which they can
compromise, which involves investigation into the need for particular protections and the appropriate language for those protections. Corporate law
can reduce these transaction costs with established uniform rules. Default
rules still permit the parties some choice to modify the legal standard,
though mandatory rules cannot be evaded through contract. Perhaps a
greater benet of the corporate law is not the particular choice of language
governing the relationship but the clarication of what that language
means. Words are not determinate and parties can agree on words without
agreeing on their meaning, and certainly without appreciating what a
future court might deem to be the words meaning.
The words of corporate law are not intrinsically clearer than those contained in a contract, and the potential scope of a general duciary duty
is quite vague. However, the identical statutory language governs many
transactions, so the meaning of these particular words becomes better
understood over time. While not every provision of corporate law has been
well-ventilated in court, the more signicant provisions such as duciary
duties have been extensively litigated over decades, and their dimensions are
now relatively well understood. This understanding provides the parties
with understanding and certainty that would not be available under contract language that may never have been interpreted in court. Easterbrook
and Fischel recognize some value to corporate law providing a set of terms
o-the-rack so that participants in corporate ventures can save the cost of
contracting.58 While there are many private services that provide such
o-the-rack contract terms, they cannot supply the interpretation of
those terms, as can government courts. When o-the-rack terms are
mandatory, they can oer still greater advantages in this regard, because
investors need not beware opportunistic modication of those terms by
self-interested managers.
A remarkable practice is the fact that public corporations very rarely use
the legally allowed freedom to draft certicates that are dierent from the
default terms provided by state law.59 This is a private ordering deference
to state choice, which seems unusual. The fact represents a market check
indicating that either the state will adopt better corporate procedures than
will the corporation itself (perhaps due to agency problems) or that the
network eects of belonging to a uniform corporate law system exceed
51
52
53
54
55
a seller or purchaser may sue under section 10(b), and a party that fails to
buy or sell securities has no possible claim. In other circumstances, such as
reliance, the federal securities fraud action is less restrictive of plaintis. By
adapting fraud to the circumstances of broadly traded publicly-held securities, in tandem with a mandatory disclosure regime and SEC enforcement, securities fraud laws can be much more eective than common law
fraud liability. By reducing informational asymmetries and providing protection for potential investors, such securities laws might reduce the cost of
capital to rms.
One key advantage of the securities fraud cause of action is its incorporation of some of the principles of nancial ecient market theories. At
common law, investors had to prove reasonable reliance on the fraudulent
misrepresentation, which meant that they must have read or heard its contents. This reading or hearing is exactly the sort of transaction cost to be
avoided by ecient markets. For every single investor in the market to read
every single prospectus and quarterly report of every candidate for investment would require very substantial costs. The theory of ecient markets
suggests that market prices reect this information, thanks to sophisticated
large institutional investors and intermediaries, even when most investors
are unfamiliar with the information. Hence, under the federal securities law,
a party may sue for fraud based on his or her reliance, not on the exact misrepresentation, but on the ecient markets use of that information.
The relaxed reliance requirement has another very great benet for
federal securities law, enabling more class action fraud litigation. There are
considerable transaction costs involved in enforcing rights through litigation, for plaintis as well as defendants. While many lament the overlegalization of our society, research in areas such as malpractice shows that the
vast majority of deserving plaintis do not even sue to recover what they
deserve. The costs of litigating can be especially great for fraud claims,
because plaintis need not only demonstrate that a defendant made a
material factual misrepresentation, they must also demonstrate that the
defendant knew of the falsity at the time (scienter or at least recklessness).
If each individual shareholder had to sue independently to recover his or her
damages, most fraud cases would not be brought, because the costs and risk
of litigation would exceed the recovery, even when fraud occurred. This
would mean less deterrence of fraud, which in turn means that investors face
more risk and are less likely to place their funds into securities with such
risk. The class action procedure, by cumulating the claims of all defrauded
shareholders, enables greater and more ecient enforcement. The securities
laws relaxed reliance requirement is crucial to enabling class actions.
Another incidental economic benet of section 10(b) is the nationalization of securities fraud law. Every state has some cause of action for fraud,
56
and their requirements are roughly similar, but each states law has its
nuances. Securities are traded in a national market and corporate representations are spread nationally. In the context of fraud, each alleged misrepresentation would have to be evaluated separately, perhaps under the
law of each of the 50 states. Some of the state laws could even conict,
where one state might require disclosure of certain information, while
another might prohibit its disclosure as unreliable. Being subject to all these
state rules is highly inecient for companies and adds transaction costs
associated with compliance. The nationalization of fraud rules for a
national market adds consistency and eciency to the law.
One further key economic benet from securities laws is the creation of
a uniform mandatory disclosure and enforcement system for investors.
While the free market celebrates diversity and choice, there are circumstances when coordination on a uniform mandated system has great
benets. Consider driving behavior. Highways are much more ecient (and
safer) because the United States has a law dictating driving on the right.
A free market system, in which drivers individually negotiated side of
road during each of their highway encounters would be far less ecient
than the uniform government rule. Indeed, the government rule would
probably be net benecial even if it picked the wrong side of the road for
ecient driving, simply by creating predictable uniformity in driving. Some
obvious examples of this principle in economic relationships include the
use of a common currency and standardized weights and measures.
Economically, the relevant issue involves what are sometimes called
network eects. Network eects describe the eciency benets associated
with everyone using the same system. The benets arising from common
use of the same system are sometimes called network externalities. When
all participants in a market conform to the same system, transaction costs
can be lessened. For this reason, product and service standardization is
used to reduce uncertainties, and eciency may call for the stipulation of a
minimum acceptable standard, leaving it to the market to exceed those
standards where ecient.66 The value of this coordination network externality can be seen in the development of private institutions, such as the
New York Stock Exchange, to create common rules for securities transactions. Signicantly, the NYSE, a private institutional intermediary, has
many mandatory rules for its members, although most of these rules have
been required or at least strongly encouraged by the SEC. This provides
some market test for the virtue of mandatory rules.
Michael Klausner has argued that corporate law can be justied in part
by network externalities.67 He observes that the traditional contractarian
paradigm of parties selecting the best rules for their transaction loses the
external benets of consistent contract terms and interpretation. He
57
stresses the benet of not only the common language of the law and contracts, but also that of judicial rulings that interpret and clarify that language. Klausner is generally skeptical of mandatory legal rules, as opposed
to default rules, in corporate law, though he recognizes that they may sometimes be preferable.68 His analysis of mandatory rules, though, is focused
on the identication of the best rule and not on transaction costs. Allowing
any deviation from the legal rules adds transaction costs for investors, if
only those costs associated with identifying the existence and meaning of
such a deviation. Rao thus notes that [m]arginal additions to standardization usually lead to decreasing utilities or returns, suggesting the existence of an optimal level of standardization, conducive enough to lead to
the formation of expectations.69
The same network externalities that support a common corporate law
apply to securities law. Corporate law provides a coordination benet that
protects investors against post-purchase opportunism, through reliable
legal rules. Securities law provides the same benet, primarily for those who
have not yet invested and need protection against fraudulent inducement of
their investment. Federal securities law gives assurances that investors will
have certain disclosures, that certain key information will not be omitted
from those disclosures, and that they will have legally enforceable rights
against parties who make materially misleading disclosures. Private networks can provide some of these benets but are not an adequate replacement for government. Because of the widespread positive external benets
of the coordinated system, no private network can fully capture the utility
it creates, which means that private networks will underinvest in creation of
these benets.70 Free-rider prospects for those outside the network compound this problem, as do the problems of intermediary opportunism and
market power discussed above. Experience in Russia demonstrates that
private intermediaries cannot eectively capture the coordination benets
provided by the law.71
Network eects have at times been lamented for their perpetuation of
ineciency. It is true that the eciencies of existing networks mean that a
less ecient incumbent technology might prevail in the market over a more
ecient new technology, because the less ecient incumbent had established network eects that deterred switching to the newer and better technology. In the free market, this need not be a serious problem, if the better
technology is signicantly better, those benets will outweigh the costs of
transitioning to it. There is ample historical evidence demonstrating that
network members will transition to form a new network around a demonstrably better product.72
It might seem like governmentally-imposed networks pose a greater risk
of this type of ineciency than do private networks, because the law may
58
59
internal questions of corporate governance and the rights of current shareholders. The best price rules of the Williams Act governing tender oers
prevent acquirers from favoring corporate insiders at the expense of other
existing minority shareholders. Similarly, the Sarbanes-Oxley legislation of
2002 involves matters of internal corporate governance in addition to regulation of transactions with prospective purchasers. These rules would be
evaluated according to and justied by the analysis of agency problems discussed above in the context of state corporations laws, though the network
eects analysis in this section is also relevant to their value. For example,
an investor benets from the ability to rely on a uniform set of mandatory
restrictive legal proxy disclosure rules, rather than having to rely on continuously investigating and monitoring his or her contractual rights to
information disclosure.
60
York Stock Exchange issues, but found a dramatic eect for issues not
traded on the NYSE which were often overpriced prior to the Securities
Acts eect.77 Moreover, the dispersion of returns and associated risk was
lower after the Securities Act for all groups of shares studied, included
those traded on the NYSE. The results indicated that the information
eects of securities regulation should be reected in the risk borne by
investors, and not the average risk-adjusted returns.78
The mandatory disclosure rules also have seen some historical study.
George Benston studied the reaction of the market to the passage of the
1934 Exchange Act, by testing the subsequent results of rms which had
previously made required disclosures of sales against those which had
not.79 He found no material eect from the legislation. The study has seen
signicant criticism,80 though, and its implications are uncertain.81 Even
Benstons results indicated that the 1934 Act improved pricing accuracy in
the market. Several studies found that the mandatory disclosure provisions
of the 1933 and 1934 Acts reduced underwriter costs and that the disclosure programs increased investor condence and led directly to a large
increase in investor participation in the stock markets.82 A more recent
study, however, found that the laws passage did not markedly increase
public disclosures.83 We will examine this historical evidence further in
Chapter 4. Any such historical analysis is somewhat constrained by limits
on available data, but the record can provide some information.
These studies from the era surrounding the adoption of the securities
laws may be expected to underestimate the value of those laws in todays
world. As noted above, a new law takes some time to establish its market
credibility and yield its positive eects. Moreover, the SEC and its rules
were still relatively embryonic at the time period studied in this research
(prior to 1953 or even earlier). Thus, a lack of eect immediately after
passage of the laws does not mean much about the current operation of
those laws. It seems reasonable to expect that the Commissions rules and
enforcement activities have improved over time, as its sta has gained more
expertise and experience with implementing the laws. Any positive benets
of securities law would also grow as private parties became more familiar
with the regime and associated network eects aliated with the law. The
true benets from the law increase as it establishes its reliability and credibility and compliance becomes routinized and therefore cheaper. In the
process, heuristics of trust develop that increase market eciency.
The historical empirical measurements of securities law may inevitably
underestimate its benets, because they test only the federal securities laws.
Before the nation had a federalized Securities Act or Securities Exchange
Act, the states had written their own securities legislation, called blue sky
laws. These state laws had some signicant limitations, which provoked the
61
demand for uniform federal legislation. However, the state laws surely
oered some portion of the potential economic benets from securities
laws, so that studies of the federal laws would only capture a portion of the
benet from such laws, rather than representing a comprehensive measure.
Some international research also sheds light on the economic virtue of
securities laws. Corporate takeovers can help promote the ecient allocation of capital, by displacing ineective management. Acquirers typically
pay a material premium over the market price of a stock, which is undervalued. The presence of such acquisitions evidences some shortcomings in
internal corporate governance, suggesting that public shareholders are
either unaware of managerial shortcomings or unable to do anything about
them in corporate elections. The ability of outside acquirers to take over a
company, through devices such as tender oers, can thus enhance eciency
beyond that achievable by existing shareholders.84 Incidentally, the threat
of a takeover may also inuence managers to perform better and save their
jobs. The overall eectiveness of acquisitions in promoting this eciency,
though, depends on a variety of factors, including transaction costs, agency
costs, information problems, etc. Not all takeovers are ecientthe
acquirers managerial decision is also inuenced by agency opportunism
risk, but the presence of acquisitions can help discipline the market and
enhance eciency.
One test for the economic value of corporate and securities law is to
observe its eect on the market for corporate control through acquisitions.
A study at the European Corporate Governance Institute found that the
volume of merger and acquisition activity from 1999 to 2002 was much
greater in countries that had stronger shareholder protection and higher
accounting standards.85 In addition, hostile takeovers are more frequent in
countries with greatest investor protection, the premium paid to shareholders is greater in these countries, and cross-border mergers are more
likely if the target company is governed by stronger investment protection
laws. While these investor protections themselves add costs to acquisition
activity (such as mandatory disclosure requirements and restrictions on
how the takeover is structured), they apparently oer much greater countervailing economic benet and consequently enhance the market for corporate control.
Evidence for the economic benets of the securities law can also be seen
from a natural experiment involving foreign issuers of securities. Foreign
companies cross-list their securities, in the form of certain categories
of American Depository Receipts (ADRs), on US markets, thereby subjecting themselves to some of the restrictions of this countrys securities
laws. Doing so has the economic benet of providing more direct access
to US capital, but given the globalization of nancial capital markets,
62
cross-listing is not vital to accessing US capital. Some countries, to encourage cross-listing on their markets, have advertised corporate-friendly legal
rules, though the United States has maintained its strict securities law
requirements. These stricter rules may well have enhanced cross-listing in
the United States, implicitly demonstrating the economic advantages of its
securities regulation.
John Coee and others have suggested that such cross-listing in the
United States is a form of bonding by foreign companies, in which they
accept the relatively rigorous requirements of US securities law in order to
demonstrate the quality of their company and credibility of their disclosures.86 Cross-listing may take dierent forms but typically requires foreign
rms to materially increase their disclosures. US securities laws can lend
credibility to the cross-listing companies that enhances their investment
appeal. Companies from countries with lesser legal requirements may
reduce the agency risk costs of investment by binding themselves to tighter
standards.87 The existence of cross-listing provides another natural experiment regarding the value of US legal governance of corporate securities.
The phenomenon of cross-listing has been extensively investigated by
nancial economists. Much of the research shows a distinct benet to
cross-listing. An investigation of hundreds of cross-listings found that the
process signicantly reduced a companys cost of capital, and that the
benet was greater as the increased government regulation from crosslisting was greater (that is, as the home governance was weaker and when
the cross-listing was with an American exchange that exercised greater
supervisory power).88 A study of Canadian rms found that cross-listed
rms traded at a higher price than did their purely domestic counterparts.89
Other studies have shown that cross-listings increase rms market values.90
The benet is greatest for minority shareholders, as might be expected,
because of their vulnerability to opportunism.91 More specic accounting
research demonstrates that the value from the US securities laws comes
from the disclosure requirements, which enable more accurate projections
of the companys prospects.92
Some additional research has found that rms from weak investor protection nations were less likely to cross-list in the United States, but that
companies from those nations who did cross-list issued more equity.93
While this result has been used to question the bonding hypothesis, it is consistent with the possibility that agency problems prevent even ecient
bonding through cross-listing. The cross-listing test thus has some theoretical imperfections, because the individuals who choose to cross-list, a
companys ocers, are the very individuals whose opportunism is regulated
by US securities laws. Hence, the rms that might most benet from
bonding may be the least likely to undertake the process. Perhaps for this
63
64
65
but possibly substantial amount. The true cost of the corporate and securities laws for NYSE-listed companies is something below US$12.2 billion.
To put this in context, the total market value of NYSE-listed companies
at the time was nearly US$10 trillion, according to the Exchanges factbook. The total costs of going public for these companies are thus less than
0.00012 of the companies market capitalization. Hence, only a miniscule
marginal benet from the law of 0.00012 would be required to economically justify their costs. Given the context of equity markets, the absolute
cost of going public is plainly quite small, and the potential net benet of
corporate and securities law is easily seen. The cost of the laws could be
justied by any market benet, even a proportionally tiny one. If the laws
work in the manner hypothesized above, they should pay for themselves
many times over.
CONCLUSION
Much conventional economic analysis of law rejects mandatory rules,
because they limit private choice. This analysis can approach the
Panglossian, claiming that a laissez faire result is the best possible result
and not to be questioned, simply because it is the product of a free market.
While there is obvious truth in recognizing the value of private choice, such
choice does not necessarily yield perfect results, and a government regulatory system can still oer additional economic benets even when it
restricts some aspects of that private choice. Government action can
enhance trust, can reduce transaction costs, and can contribute to valuable
network externalities that promote the development of nancial markets.
There is a strong theoretical case that legal rules, including restrictive
rules, contribute to economic eciency and developed capital markets.
While some economists argue that our rules are too restrictive and interfere
with the development of free markets, their case is an abstract one that does
not seem consistent with the experiential evidence. To the contrary, the best
case against our laws may be that they are insucient and permit too much
opportunism to continue unchecked. Certainly the corporate scandals of
recent years do not imply that our legal requirements are unduly rigorous.
This is an imperfect human world, though, and no procedure, legal or
private, will succeed in exterminating objectionable behavior. Decisions are
made on the margin, and legal rules, both empowering and restrictive, can
facilitate markets and economic development at this level, notwithstanding
their imperfections.
The economic case for basic, corporate, and securities laws laid out in
this chapter is theoretical and does not reach the level of proof. Given the
66
very small costs of the laws, it seems a plausible case, but it is not yet proved.
If the assumptions about trust and relative transaction costs and the costs
of government intervention that underlie this chapter were modied, one
could reach dierent conclusions about the economic value of these laws,
as many have. The issue of the relative accuracy of the various assumptions
and the economic eect of the law is ultimately a consequentialist one,
which requires real world empirical testing of the eect, of which this
chapter includes only little. The empirical research cited in this chapter supports the role of the laws we discuss. Additional empirical support for this
chapter is found in the history that will be supplied in Chapter 4 and the
quantitative studies addressed in Chapter 5. At present, we maintain only
that there is a valid economic theoretical reason to believe that the laws we
examine do indeed enhance eciency and economic development. The
critics economic case, which itself is almost entirely theoretical, is not a
sucient or compelling answer to the claim that the laws have value.
Before turning to our own empirical investigation of the theories,
however, we consider the behavioral analysis of economic decisionmaking.
While classical economic analysis has considerable validity, it rests upon
certain rational choice assumptions about individual decisionmaking that
are not entirely accurate. Considerable psychological research demonstrates that the assumptions of self-interested rational choice economic
analysis do not inevitably govern human actions. These ndings have implications for the choice between relational private and rule-based legal governance. The behavioral analysis builds upon and complements the
classical economic analysis of this chapter to set forth the theoretical basis
for the benets of law, including the mandatory restraining legal rules of
corporate and securities law.
NOTES
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
67
Lisa Bernstein, Opting Out of the Legal System: Extralegal Contractual Relations in the
Diamond Industry, 21 J. LEGAL STUD. 1 (1992).
Matt Ridley, THE ORIGINS OF VIRTUE 202 (1996).
See Gillian K. Hadeld, Contract Law is Not Enough: The Many Legal Institutions that
Support Contractual Commitments, at 6, forthcoming in HANDBOOK OF NEW
INSTITUTIONAL ECONOMICS (Claude Menard & Mary Shirley eds. 2004).
Avinash K. Dixit, LAWLESSNESS AND ECONOMICS 16 (2004).
George A. Akerlof, The Market for Lemons: Quality Uncertainty and the Market
Mechanism, 84 Q.J. ECON. 488 (1970).
Id. at 495.
Roy J. Lewicki, et al., Trust and Distrust: New Relationships and Realities, 23 ACAD.
MANAGEMENT REV. 438 (1998).
Kathryn Hendley, Peter Murrell, & Randi Ryterman, Law Works in Russia: The Role of
Law in Interenterprise Transactions, in ASSESSING THE VALUE OF LAW IN TRANSITION ECONOMIES (Peter Murrell ed. 2001).
Id. at 85.
John McMillan & Christopher Woodru, Courts and Relational Contracts, 18 J. L.
ECON. & ORG. 221 (2002).
See John Shuhe Li, Relation-Based versus Rule-Based Governance: An Explanation of the
East Asian Miracle and Asian Crisis, 11 REV. INTL ECON. 651 (2003).
Id. at 660.
Id. at 661.
Avinash K. Dixit, LAWLESSNESS AND ECONOMICS 12 (2004).
P. Milgrom & J. Roberts, Economic Theories of the Firm: Past, Present, and Future, 11
CAN. J. ECON. 444, 449 (1988).
John P. Powelson, THE MORAL ECONOMY 111 (1998).
Sitkin & Roth, supra note 5, at 371.
Putnam, supra note 2, at 35063.
Alfred Chandler, SCALE AND SCOPE: THE DYNAMICS OF INDUSTRIAL CAPITALISM 28687 (1990).
Frank H. Easter brook & Daniel R. Fischel, THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF
CORPORATE LAW 13031(1991).
Roger Lowenstein, ORIGINS OF THE CRASH 153 (2004).
Id. at 190.
See Frank Partnoy, INECTIOUS GREED (2003).
Id. at 352.
Jonathan R. Macey, A Pox on Both Your Houses: Enron, Sarbanes-Oxley and the Debate
Concerning the Relative Ecacy of Mandatory Versus Enabling Rules, 81 WASH. U. L.
Q. 329, 342 (2003).
See Arthur A. Schulte, Jr., Compatibility of Management Consulting and Auditing, 40
ACCT. REV. 587 (1965).
See Robert A. Prentice, The Case of the Irrational Auditor: A Behavioral Insight into
Securities Fraud Litigation, 95 N.W. U. L. REV. 133, 194 (2000).
See Stanley Bairman, Discussion of Auditing: Incentives and Truthful Reporting, 17 J.
ACCT. RES. 25 (1979).
Of Scolds and Conicts, WALL ST. J., June 22, 2004, at A18.
Dixit, supra note 13, at 8485.
Donald Wittman, THE MYTH OF DEMOCRATIC FAILURE: WHY POLITICAL
INSTITUTIONS ARE EFFICIENT (1995).
Rao, supra note 1, at 92.
Oriana Bandiera, Land Reform, the Market for Protection and the Origins of the Sicilian
Maa: Theory and Evidence, 19 J. LAW ECON. & ORG. 218 (2003).
See Frank B. Cross, Law and Economic Growth, 80 TEX.L.REV. 175152 (2002).
See L.J. Zucker, The Production of Trust: Institutional Sources of Economic Structure, 8
RESEARCH IN ORG. BEHAVIOR 55 (1986).
See Shuhe Li:, supra note 20.
68
46.
47.
48.
49.
50.
51.
52.
53.
54.
55.
56.
57.
58.
59.
60.
61.
62.
63.
64.
65.
66.
67.
68.
69.
70.
71.
72.
73.
74.
75.
76.
77.
78.
79.
80.
81.
82.
69
See Paul G. Mahoney & Jianping Mei, Mandatory vs. Contractual Disclosure in
Securities Markets: Evidence from the 1930s, University of Virginia Law School John M.
Olin Program in Law and Economics Working Paper #25 (2006).
Easterbrook & Fischel, supra note 29, at 17172.
Stefano Rossi & Paolo Volpin, Cross-Country Determinants of Mergers and Acquisitions,
ECGI Finance Working Paper No. 25/2003 (September 2003).
See John C. Coee, Racing Towards the Top? The Impact of Cross-Listings and Stock
Market Competition on International Corporate Governance, 102 COLUM. L. REV.
(2002).
See R.M. Stulz, Globalization of Equity Markets and the Cost of Capital, J. APPLIED
CORPORATE FIN. 8 (1999).
See Luzi Hail & Christian Leuz, Cost of Capital and Cash Flow Eects of U.S. CrossListings, ECGI Finance Working Paper (May 2004).
See Michael R. King & Dan Segal, Corporate Governance, International Cross Listing
and Home Bias, CAN. INVESTMENT REV. 8 (Winter 2003).
See Craig G. Doidge, Andrew Karolyi & Rene M. Stulz, Why are Foreign Firms Listed
in the U.S. Worth More?, 71 J. FIN. ECON. 205 (2004).
See Craig G. Doidge, U.S. Cross-Listings and the Private Benets of Control: Evidence
from Dual-Class Firms, 72 J. FIN. ECON 519 (2004).
Mark Lang, Karl Lins & Darius Miller, ADRs, Analysts, and Accuracy: Does Cross
Listing in the United States Improve a Firms Information Environment and Increase
Market Value, 41 J. ACC. RSCH. 317 (2003).
W.A. Reese & M. Weisbach, Protection of Minority Shareholder Interests, Cross-Listings
in the United States, and Subsequent Equity Oerings, 66 J. FIN ECON. 65 (2003).
Christine Botosan, Disclosure Level and the Cost of Equity Capital, 72 THE
ACCOUNTING REV. 323 (1997).
See Katarina Pistor, Law as a Determinant for Equity Market Development: The
Experience of Transition Economies in ASSESSING THE VALUE OF LAW IN TRANSITION ECONOMIES, supra note 17, at 267.
Id. at 278.
Thomas E. Hartman, Foley & Lardner LLP, The Cost of Being Public in the Era of
Sarbanes-Oxley (presented at the 2004 meeting of the National Directors Institute).
Id. at 14.
71
72
73
notion that people prefer cognitive consistency and when they have made
a decision their minds will tend to suppress information inconsistent with
the decision they have made. Thus, an auditor who has publicly taken the
position that her clients nancial statements are accurate or an attorney
who has publicly stated that his client is innocent will have great diculty
objectively processing new information that is inconsistent with those positions. This concept reinforces belief persistence, the tendency of people to
hold to beliefs long after the basis for those beliefs has been thoroughly
discredited.
Emotions
Emotions can and do aect peoples reasoning. Even if a person had access
to full information, sometimes emotions such as anger or sadness prevent
or severely impede rational thought. The connection between emotions and
reasoning is complex, and it is well known that damage to key emotional
centers of the brain can make it dicult for people to make good decisions
or, indeed, to make decisions at all.7 One emotion that people do not enjoy
is regret; therefore, they will take extensive steps to avoid feeling regret, a
phenomenon termed regret aversion. Because humans tend to regret
adverse consequences that stem from their actions more than adverse consequences stemming from their inaction (the omission bias), anticipated
regret aversion can channel human decisionmaking in important ways.
Regret aversion suggests that, absent any legal protection, many individuals will choose not to invest in the market for fear of suering great losses,
even if the risk of such losses is small. Relatedly, people possess an innate
sense of fairness and will act in a way that damages their own self-interest
in order to punish others whom the decisionmaker believes have acted
unfairly. While emotions are not necessarily irrational, they are generally
ignored by traditional economic analysis.
Undue Optimism and Overcondence
It seems to be evolutionarily adaptive to be unduly optimistic, to believe
that the bad things that occur in life will mostly happen to other people and
not to us. There is some evidence that only the chronically depressed are
well-calibrated in this regard. Newlyweds optimistically believe that there
is a zero chance that they will get divorced, though 4050 percent of marriages end in divorce. People also tend to think that they are more moral,
more competent, better drivers, smarter investors,8 and otherwise generally
superior to their fellows. Because of undue optimism and overcondence,
people can make decisions that are ill-considered and occasionally unduly
74
risky. Undue optimism might, for example, cause a party to be blindly trusting of another even when such trust was unwarranted.
Illusion of Control
Related to undue optimism and overcondence is the illusion of control,
the irrational belief people often hold that they can inuence things that
are truly out of their control. Because of this illusion, people tend to roll a
pair of dice hard when they want a high number and softly when they want
a low number, and they value more highly a lottery ticket that they chose
from a bin as compared to a similar lottery ticket in that same bin that
someone else chose for them.
Availability Heuristic
Because of the availability heuristic, people often think that events that
seldom occur actually happen more frequently simply because they have
been in the news recently or are otherwise particularly available to recall.
Because murders make the headlines and strokes usually do not, people
tend to think that more people die of murder than strokes when the actually ration is 11 to 1 in the other direction. This heuristic, like many others,
will cause individuals to miscalculate the ecient transaction costs necessary for a particular decision.
Representativeness Heuristic
Because of the representativeness heuristic, decisionmakers tend to judge
probabilities by outing numerous rules of statistics and focusing instead
upon the degree of similarity that an item seems to bear to a category or
parent population. For example, in deciding whether a person is an accountant or a professional basketball player, people will tend to focus on how
much the person ts the stereotype of the two professions (tall? mildmannered?), ignoring the fact that there are many times more professional
accountants than professional basketball players. The fact that the representativeness heuristic tends to cause people to ignore base rates creates
many errors in statistical reasoning.
False Consensus Eect
People are often surprised that others do not share their views on issues
ranging from capital punishment to the designated hitter. They expect
others to share their viewsif they believe ABC Co. is a good investment,
75
they act as though others will believe that also.9 They expect others to share
their qualities: honest people expect other people to be honest; crooks have
much lower expectations for their fellow man. Because of the false consensus eect, honest people are often insuciently wary. A related phenomenon is the personal positivity biaswhich is what causes people to think
that although most politicians are crooks, their Senator is honest and
although many stockbrokers are untrustworthy, the one they have chosen
is a prince among men.
Insensitivity to the Source of Information
People have diculty not taking into account information that they are
exposed to, even if they are given evidence that the source of the information is biased or perhaps of dubious reliability. People adjust their perception of the information in light of the problems with the source, but
typically do not do so suciently. For example, from May 2000 to February
2001, the NASDAQ stock index fell by more than one-third, yet Wall Street
stock analysts sell recommendations held steady at 0 percent.10 This was a
clear signal to the market that many analysts were more concerned with
opportunistic behavior, protecting the interests of the investment bankers
in their rms, than they were with producing accurate reports. Nonetheless,
the market did not adequately adjust for the unreliability of the stock analysts.11 The SEC decried earnings management, yet issuers continued to
practice it and generally fooled even professional investors.12 This explains
how even unreliable intermediaries may thrive, failing to correct for opportunistic behavior.
The Conformity Bias
People tend to look to others for cues as to how to act. When more forks
than they are used to seeing are arranged around their plate at a fancy
dinner, they tend to look to others to see which one to pick up rst. In business as well, decisionmakers will be heavily inuenced by the decisions and
actions of those around them. Solomon Asch proved that subjects will
often say that one line that is obviously shorter than another is indeed
longer if several confederates of the experimenter have said that it is longer.
In cooperation games, people tend to cooperate if they think that is what
other participants will do; they tend not to cooperate if competition seems
to be the expected conduct. People are so inuenced by the actions and
views of others that in some contexts groupthink occurs, where group
loyalty in a homogeneous group and pressures to conform in a homogeneous group lead to a deterioration of mental eciency, reality testing,
76
77
Loss Aversion
A major implication of framing is that peoples decisions can be greatly
impacted by whether a problem is presented in a gain frame or a loss
frame. The reason is that people suer from the impact of losses about
twice as intensely as they enjoy gains. They will often, therefore, make seemingly irrational decisions in an eort to avoid sustaining losses. As with
regret aversion, this heuristic will cause individuals to underinvest in
markets, harming the economy, as the relative risk of loss grows.
Endowment Eect
Loss aversion is exacerbated by the endowment eect. Although a pen
would appear to be a pen and a candy bar a candy bar, hundreds of studies
show that if the pen or candy bar are ours, if we consider them part of our
endowment, we will often demand many times as much money to part with
them as we would have paid to acquire them in the rst place. Because
people do not feel that they were endowed with money they do not have on
account, hidden taxes ourish in our economy. Consistent with this
research, mutual funds continuously charge customers with hidden fees.
Investors avoid high front-end load fees that are quite visible, but tend to
ignore seemingly smaller ongoing operating expenses and other fees that
are hidden by the volatility of equity returns.16
Prospect Theory
Loss aversion, the endowment eect, reference dependent utility (the fact
that we are often more concerned with our position relative to other reference pointssuch as the status quo or the wealth of our neighborsthan
with our absolute position), and framing are four pieces that help make up
prospect theory, Kahneman and Tverskys proposed improvement upon
rational man economics subjective utility theory. Although not perfectly
satisfying, prospect theory suggests, in part, that the notion of utility
should be replaced with value, which is dened in terms of gains and
losses from a reference point with the value function being greater for gains
than for losses. Preferences will depend on whether a problem is presented
in a loss frame or a gain frame.17
Mental Accounting
Although to homo economicus, a dollar is a dollar, homo sapiens often treats
dollars dierently by placing them in separate mental accounts. Thus, for
78
example, people may be willing to spend money won in a rae in a frivolous way when they would not willingly spend money from their regular
paycheck in that way. Stocks may be treated dierently as well. One study
found that when employees options in pension funds are limited to stocks
and bonds of other companies, they average investing 51 percent of their
money in the stock funds and 49 percent in the bond funds. If a third choice
is added in the form of their own companys stock, they tend to invest 42
percent in their companys stock, and then 29 percent in the other stock
funds and 29 percent in the other bond funds. They account dierently for
their own companys shares, leading to a much dierent balance between
stocks and bonds.18 As noted above, a feature such as this will cause the
misallocation of the ecient optimization of transaction costs.
Status Quo Bias
All things being equal, people prefer the status quo, the familiar. They tend
to stick with the old favorite, even if they might choose an alternative were
they choosing for the rst time. Related to this is the habit heuristic. As a
handy mental shortcut, many people choose to drive a certain route to work
or to order a certain dish at a restaurant because they always do it and
need not expend mental energy reweighing the advantages and disadvantages of alternate choices.
Sunk Cost Eects
Assume that a couple has purchased tickets to a play whose traveling cast
is visiting their city from New York. On the day of the performance they
both feel sick and are told by reliable sources that the show really stinks. If
they had been given the tickets, the couple might well choose to stay home.
But if they paid for the tickets, they will hesitate to waste their money and
so they are much more likely to go to the play and suer loss of time that
will compound their loss of money. Rational people would not do this,
economists counsel, but most real people honor sunk costs.19 Indeed, once
costs are sunk, individuals and groups often decide to pour more and
more resources into a deteriorating situation in an irrational escalation of
commitment.
Time Delay Traps
When an action has short-term and long-term consequences, people tend
to underappreciate the impact of the latter. They tend to value immediate
over delayed gratication and often have great diculty making rational
79
80
81
82
fact that institutional investors were as prone to the hysteria of the dot.com
bubble as lay investors was not surprising to behavioralists. A wide array of
studies have indicated that experts with sophistication and experience,
including physicians, statisticians, judges, auditors, engineers, securities
analysts, nancial analysts, institutional investors, and others are often
nearly as subject to (and, occasionally, more subject to) the problems
caused by heuristic-driven and biased thinking as are lay people.37 In the
words of Hersh Shefrin, Wall Street strategists are prone to committing a
variety of behavioral errors and biases: gamblers fallacy, overcondence,
and anchoring.38
Research has found that investing professionals are boundedly rational;
operating under conditions that have both nancial and ego consequences
and where information acquisition costs are virtually zero, even professional security analysts deciding on which securities to select do not acquire
most (or even much) of the information available.39 Even institutional
investors tend to base their investing decisions on hunches, emotions, and
intuitions.40 Professional investors, like others, are subject to the availability heuristic, meaning in part that they are more likely to buy the stocks of
companies that are easy to recall, perhaps because they have been mentioned in the newspaper recently.41 Professional investors are also subject
to the representativeness heuristic, meaning that they are more likely to
judge some probabilities based not on statistical likelihood but upon the
similarity that an item seems to bear to a category or parent population.
This heuristic is part of the reason that professional investors irrationally
believe in the proverbial hot hand, the erroneous notion that a money
manager or security analyst who has been on a roll will stay on a roll.42 It
appears that investing professionals tend to ignore low probability events.43
This above discussion is far from exhaustive but should suce to illustrate that institutional and other sophisticated investors behavior does not
overcome the eects of psychological heuristics. If people are not models
of rationality and even institutional and other sophisticated investors can
make systematic misjudgments that prevent the nancial markets from
being as ecient as economic theory presumes, there is room for law and
regulation to play a role in improving market eciency.
83
humans act as they do. As already noted, the most frequent and signicant
misassumption of economic analysis is that human beings are optimally
rational maximizers of their expected utilities. Behavioral decision theory,
which starts from more realistic assumptions as to why people act as they
do, can help explain the role of law in advancing the eciency of markets.
Consider contract law. An overarching premise of economic analysis of
contracts, including those used to embody rights in corporate structures
and purchases and sales of securities, is found in an aspect of the Coase
Theorem which provides that the initial assignment of legal rights does not
determine which use will ultimately prevail because the parties will bargain
to the most ecient state of aairs.44 In other words, if left to their own
devices and without transaction costs, free of government interference, promoters of and investors in enterprises will negotiate to the most ecient
possible contract.
However, research from behavioral psychology indicates that the initial
assignment of legal rights matters signicantly in contractual bargaining.
Evidence indicates that people are both loss averse and impacted by the
endowment eect. Together, these concepts indicate that the initial distribution of rights will greatly impact negotiation between two parties.45 For
example, if a statute provides that employees will presumptively have
certain types of benets unless they agree to forfeit them, they are much
more likely to be accorded those benets by an employer than if the statute
provides that employees presumptively will not have those benets unless
they bargain with the employer to achieve them.46 Therefore, it is likely that
under a corporate code that assumes shareholders will not have inspection
rights or voting rights unless they take measures to have the Articles of
Incorporation amended, then they are much less likely to have such rights
than if the corporate code assumes that such rights exist. Economists recognize that transactions costs mean that the simple Coase Theorem cannot
describe reality but behavioral psychologists go further and recognize that
even in the absence of material transaction costs, such a renegotiation is not
likely to occur.
Besides loss aversion and the endowment eect, the related concept of
the status quo bias plays a role here. Ceteris paribus, people prefer the status
quo.47 Part of the reason is regret aversionthat they are more likely to
regret bad consequences that stem from their actions than from their inactions. By sticking with the status quo they reduce the risk of feeling regret
in the future.48 Thus, when New Jersey reduced the price of automobile
insurance along with coverage but gave insureds the option to opt into a
more expensive policy with broader rights and Pennsylvania did the
oppositeenacted an expanded-rights presumption that gave insureds the
option to opt into a cheaper regime with fewer rights to sue, in each state
84
most insureds chose what they perceived to be the status quo. A large
majority of New Jersey residents chose cheaper insurance and less coverage while a large majority of Pennsylvanians chose more expensive insurance and more coverage.49 As Korobkin has demonstrated experimentally,
parties tend to treat form contracts as the status quo and to accept them
with little question or negotiation.50 Consumers may well accept a warranty disclaimer or arbitration clause that is part of a form contract
because it seems to be the status quo, where they would object loudly to the
suggestion that such a provision be penciled into a form contract that did
not contain them.51
Some argue that although the status quo bias might explain why Coasian
bargaining does not occur in real life when economists theorize that it
should, it does not explain why abusive terms persist. The notion is that
competition should force merchants to place pro-consumer provisions in
their contracts. Unfortunately, the reverse is often true. Because consumers
and investors tend not to pay attention to nonprice terms and often believe
that unfair collateral terms such as waivers of rights or arbitration provisions will never apply to them (because of the tendency people have to be
unduly optimistic and to ignore low probability events), competition actually forces merchants to include such terms so they will not miss out on the
prots their competitors are achieving by scalping customers. The simple
fact is that contract renegotiation is quite rare, indicating that contracting
parties do not, when faced with a contract that is not optimal, reopen bargaining to work toward a better solution, indicates that the Coase theorem
is unduly optimistic. If parties cannot be counted to bargain to the most
ecient result, then there may well be a role for law and regulation.
As indicated in the previous chapter, trust is an important part of a business environment, and law can foster trust. People do not wish to do business in a crooked marketplace. This is true in part because of rational fears
of being exploited by dishonest companies and individuals. In addition, it
is true because people inherently value fairness. Humans are guided by an
innate sense of fairness that drives their actions, attitudes and behaviors.52
Although it is not always rational for people to act fairly toward others in
a one-shot ultimatum game context, they often do. They do because fairness matters, as research in behavioral decision theory indicates. In the
experimental ultimatum game, A may be given US$100 with the power to
oer any division between himself and B. But if B rejects the division,
neither party receives anything. Rationally, economists say, A should oer
US$1 to B and propose to keep US$99 for himself. B should accept this
because US$1 is better than nothing. However, typically oerors propose
much fairer divisions of the US$100 (often 50/50) and oerees who are
oered a very small share often reject it. They would rather receive nothing
85
86
87
88
Put all these factors together and it is not terribly surprising that auditors act recklessly from time to time. As Professor Loewenstein has noted,
if one wanted to create a business setting that would virtually guarantee
unethical behavior, it would be dicult to improve on the existing case of
independent auditing.63 It is Pollyanna-ish to believe that the reputational
constraint is sucient in light of these behavioral tendencies.
89
90
unlikely to detect if he is being lied to, and to be overcondent in his conclusion that the promoter has been truthful. Once he has decided to trust
the promoter, he is unlikely to discount suciently representations made if
any evidence appears as to the untrustworthiness of the CEO. Cognitive
dissonance and belief persistence will impede his processing of information
that undermines his initial conclusion that the promoter is honest and that
the company is a promising one. Overcondence and undue optimism will
bolster this conclusion. All these factors put together paint a picture of a
vulnerable investor whose fate is uncomfortably in the hands of another. A
legal regime that imposes duties of loyalty upon the CEO and other managers and punishes violations provides protection for the investor that
would otherwise be lacking. In so doing, it encourages investment.
Professors Blair and Stout have pointed out that just as shareholders
cannot be omnipresent to monitor the stewardship of their investment,
neither can the law be everywhere (nor can it be perfectly enforced).66
Therefore, trust remains an important factor in the corporate governance
calculation. As those commentators note, however, trust derives largely
from social norms. The law dramatically impacts those norms. Professors
Donaldson and Dunfee point out that [o]utside sources may inuence the
development of norms. Law, particularly when it is perceived as legitimate
by members of a community, may have a major impact on what is considered to be correct behavior.67 Thus, when the Civil Rights Act of 1964 outlawed racial discrimination, peoples views of the acceptability of such
discrimination was signicantly altered. Because of the conformity bias,
what is considered correct behavior exerts a major inuence upon how
people act.
For present purposes, corporate law establishes that managers and directors are to act in the best interests not of themselves, but of shareholders.
In so doing, the law not only gives them external incentives in the form of
liability rules to act in this way, it also changes their internal preferences by
helping to establish trustworthy actions as the societal norm. Thousands of
cooperation games administered by psychologists over the years establish
that people are more willing to cooperate (irrationally, according to economic incentives) if they are instructed to do so, and/or if they believe that
others will cooperate (the conformity bias). The law instructs managers to
act in a duciary capacity and thereby increases the odds that they will do
so. This message is repeatedly sent to managers by judges who often
describe the managers duciary duty in the strongest terms. The law also
helps to establish the social norm, reinforcing the likelihood that managers
will choose to act as duciaries.
While contractarians argue that the duciary duty is just another in the
nexus of contracts that comprise corporate law, Blair and Stout argue
91
92
93
94
US$700 million even though the president of its futures division stated on
tape that a doofus ipping a . . . coin every day would have had more
success than the adviser (who lost US$556 million while trading).82
Among the reasons for the inadequacy of the reputational constraint for
remedying the misalignment of interest between broker and customer is
that even when brokers pursue their own interests at their clients expense,
their reputations may not suer much or at all. During the bubble of the
1990s, the stock market rose so dramatically that it was dicult for even
dishonest and incompetent brokers to lose money for their clients. Because
people make decisions in relation to a reference point,83 investors tend to
be much more upset if they lose money in an absolute sense than if they are
simply not making as much money as other investors.
Additionally, because of cognitive dissonance and other factors,
investors often will remember having made more money than they truly
did. Studies show that investors frequently remember that their mutual
fund performed better than it really did. Even if they do notice that their
broker has done a poor job, regret theory predicts that they will often not
complain. If they did, it would highlight in their own mind the mistake they
made in hiring this broker and they would suer regret that they would just
as soon avoid. Even if investors do notice the poor decisions made by their
brokers and do complain, the ability of any rm to trade on its reputation
depends on appearance rather than fact. By shunting claims to arbitration
and settling cases without admitting or denying wrongdoing, rms are able
to minimize the publicity for many of their brokers wrongs. Due to the
availability heuristic, investors bombarded with advertisements about the
reliability of a brokerage rm are likely to believe them despite the occasional public report of a problem, especially because most other rms that
a customer might choose to do business with may have recently been
involved in scandals as well.
A nal point is that most stockbrokers leave the industry within three
years of starting. How can they be concerned with their long-term reputational capital? Even if they plan on staying around, [r]eputational sanctions also have limited eect on especially venal parties.84 The bottom line
is that empirical evidence indicates that the reputational constraint aects
brokers, but weakly.85 Legal regulation is needed as an important supplement. Similar analyses could be done regarding investment advisers, stock
analysts, stock exchanges, and other professional securities actors.
Corporate Disclosure
Mandatory disclosure is aif not thedening characteristic of US
securities regulation.86 The primary justication for mandatory disclosure
95
96
pattern this years audit plan after last years audit plan,91 which can give
dishonest clients a road map for cloaking their fraud.
Finally, Professor Bainbridge observes that social norms aect decisionmakers.92 If the norm among companies is not to disclose, is it not more
dicult for full disclosure to evolve? Bainbridge suggests that legal reform
probably could not precede cultural change in most societies, especially
since managers of companies have substantial political inuence. This is a
fair point but in other nations legal change may well happen as it does in
the United Statesan episode of major corruption or a traumatic break in
the markets can create the conditions needed for political change. That is
how the 1933 and 1934 Acts and Sarbanes-Oxley Act were passed. We have
seen how a change in the law can indeed alter norms, as in passage of the
Civil Rights Acts. Indeed, full disclosure was not the norm in America
before the 1933 and 1934 securities laws were passed, but quickly became
the norm thereafter. Before 1933, prospectuses in America were little more
than notices. Afterwards, issuers soon embraced the full disclosure norm,
although perhaps not enthusiastically. The law created a requirement that
was followed under the pain of liability, and gave rise to a norm, such that
even domestic issuers in exempt oerings and foreign issuers operating
under their own exemptions often provide prospectus-like disclosure today.
They do so not because the law requires it, but because it has become the
expectation, what investors are used to seeing. By setting the standard for
registered domestic public oerings, Congress actually raised the disclosure
bar in many other settings.
Bainbridge suggests that because the legal requirement of full disclosure
has become the norm in America there is no longer justication for mandatory disclosure in the United States. It is in fact likely that if mandatory disclosure were repealed, social norms, the status quo bias, and other factors
would ensure that voluntary disclosure would remain substantial. But, in
the absence of the reinforcement of legal requirements, it would likely
decay over time although it is unlikely that it would ever sink to pre-1933
levels. And obviously the rst to start disclosing less would be the companies that have bad news. Investors would realize this, of course, but typically would not discount for it suciently. If the law has successfully
created a valuable norm, that is not much of an argument for abolishing
the law, at least given its relatively low cost.
For all the reasons just explored, it is dicult for corporate managers to
choose to fully disclose in the absence of legal requirements. It is true that
even if the law does not require disclosure, managers might choose to do it
voluntarily if sucient pressure were exerted by investors. However, behavioral analysis not only indicates why issuers will not voluntarily disclose
information at an optimal level, it also explains why investors will not
97
98
The next chapter will indicate that history contradicts the assumptions
of purely private ordering. But consider a contemporary scenario in which
a promoter of ABC Co. makes glowing oral representations to an investor
about ABC. Those oral representations convince the investor that he
should buy the stock. The promoter then produces a form contract. One
thing that is extremely unlikely to happen at this point is for the investor to
refuse to buy the stock unless the promoter provides just the level of
antifraud protection that the investor desires. The investor might desire a
negligence or recklessness standard of liability. The promoter might prefer
that he be liable only if he acted with scienter. The promoter might wish to
require that all claims be arbitrated, while the investor might wish to have
the right to go before a jury.
Despite the parties dierent desires, the most likely thing that will
happen is not a haggling over these terms. Instead, it is mostly likely that
the investor will sign the contract, even if it contains a provision stating that
ABC Company and its agents make no representations other than those
contained in writing in this document and the investor acknowledges that
he is relying on no other statements and that this document represents the
entire agreement between the parties.
Because Congress understood human nature and the fact that any conman who could induce an investor to put money into a bogus deal also had
a good chance to convince the investor to waive any antifraud rights he
enjoyed, it placed in both the 1933 Securities Act and the 1934 Securities
Exchange Act provisions that sought to prevent investors from waiving
rights accorded them by the Acts. Most courts have refused to enforce such
waivers as inconsistent with the antiwaiver provisions of the 1933 and 1934
Acts, but a substantial number of courts have enforced them, functionally
allowing investors to waive any substantive protection from securities fraud.
But why would seemingly rational investors blithely sign away their
rights? Why do they so often elect to sign contracts that give them no protection from fraud? Why are they unlikely to bargain for just the right
level of antifraud protection? The short answer is: For the same reasons
that product consumers bought products such as automobiles under contracts that contained virtually no warranties and no signicant protection
from defective products before courts and legislatures devised modern
product liability law. The longer answer requires a little more behavioral
analysis.94 Contemplate these behavioral considerations, among many
others that could be discussed:
99
and they should not bother to read them. Usually they are dealing with
a sellers agent who does not have the authority to bargain over their
terms anyway. As Judge Posner has noted, the information costs of
reading a form contract typically make it not worth the time to do so.95
Overcondence, undue optimism, and illusion of control: People tend
to believe that they are better than they really are at judging character, that the bad things like being victimized by fraudsters that
happen to other people will not happen to them and that they can
control situations that are not truly controllable, such as by selecting
the seller of the securities they buy. For these reasons, as Ribstein has
noted, [i]nvestors, like others, may be overly optimistic in the sense
of discounting risks, including the risk of fraud.96 These factors
often cause investors to sign contracts that irrationally waive protection from fraud because they believe that they will not be victims of
fraud. Studies show that when asked about the contracts that they
have signed people believe that they are more favorable to them than
they actually are.
Probabilities and future events: As noted earlier, most people are not
particularly good at calculating probabilities, often substituting ruleof-thumb heuristics for more rigorous statistical analysis. They tend
especially to ignore low probability risks, such as the chance that the
seller of their securities is ripping them o, even when large amounts
of money are at stake. Just like product purchasers, investors in securities seldom consider that they might have to bring a lawsuit later on
to vindicate their rights.
False consensus eect and personal positivity bias: As noted earlier,
both false consensus eect, which causes honest people to believe
that others are honest as well, and the personal positivity bias, which
causes people to generally view others favorably, work together to
lead people to be insuciently wary of fraud. Because these tendencies are reinforced by the concept of cognitive dissonance, once
investors decide that they wish to do business with a particular promoter or stockbroker, they will have great diculty properly processing information that begins to indicate that that promoter or
stockbroker is a crook.
Inability to detect deception: Peoples belief that they can detect when
they are being lied to, coupled with their typical utter inability to do
so, often causes them to be insuciently cautious regarding fraud. In
business, lies are particularly hard to detect because people regard
lies as part of playing a complex game.97 If people just know
that they are not being lied to, they will be unduly willing to sign a
contract waiving protection from fraud.
100
For all these reasons and others, it is easy to see why investors did not
before securities regulation existed and likely would not today adequately
bargain for antifraud protection. For reasons noted immediately above,
people are not facile at telling when they are being lied to and not adept
at accurately adjusting their conclusions when they learn that the source
of information upon which they are relying is not trustworthy. Therefore,
their adjustment in price will typically be insucient to account for the
risk of fraud they face. There are no formulas that can be applied or computer programs that can be run to accurately adjust the price of the securities to compensate for the risk of fraud. How does one eciently
discount the dierence between a recklessness standard and a negligence
standard, between an arbitration clause and the right to a jury trial?
Professor Sale has pointed out that the markets did not accurately
discount for the possibility of gatekeeper failure in the 1990s,100
and Professor Choi admits that unsophisticated investors would probably not be able to value dierent protective devices that issuers might
adopt.101
Eective antifraud provisions are therefore necessary and ecient
private ordering cannot restrain fraud. Because of behavioral tendencies,
people do not always rationally play the game as described above in Figure
2.1. Many invest notwithstanding the risk of fraud, and some of them suer
101
the consequences of fraud. For others who are more cautious, behavioral
concerns such as regret theory and loss aversion mean that no investment
will take place, as in Figure 2.1. The more fraud that transpires at the
expense of the risk-taking population simply highlights to the cautious the
dangers of placing their savings in equity securities.
102
Political concerns can minimize the eectiveness of securities regulation. There is substantial evidence that the SEC was not active enough in
the 1990s. Because of political pressure, it was underfunded, understaed,
and under the gun in many situations when it tried to improve corporate
performance. As an example, in 2000, the SEC compromised in a battle
with the Big Five auditing rms and allowed them to continue providing
consulting services to audit clients. Just about the only concession the
SEC extracted from the politically-charged battle was a requirement that
the clients disclose in their proxy statements all the fees that they paid to
their auditors. The amounts disclosed showed shocking levels of consulting fees and clearly should have drawn into question the independence of
these auditors. But, of course, the discussion earlier in the chapter
explained that when investors learn of the questionable nature of a source
of information, they tend not to accurately discount the information
itself. In light of what happened with Enron, WorldCom, Global
Crossing, and all the others, it appears that the eventual ban on most
consulting services enacted in the Sarbanes-Oxley Act should have been
instituted earlier.
The SEC has the benet of a decisional process that eectively gathers
information from all points of view. The Commission also has signicant
formal and informal avenues of communication with the securities industry, ensuring that it has the input and often the support of market professionals it seeks to regulate. The Commissions sta generally keeps in close
contact with those it regulates via informal meetings with securities professionals.
When new rules are considered, the SEC has a decisionmaking process
that insures substantial infusion of the views of all parties. Unlike an individual decisionmaker prone to the conrmation bias, seeking out only
information that supports preexisting views, the Commission publishes
proposed rules, has a lengthy comment period, examines and responds to
the comments. If a controversial rule is proposed, literally thousands of
comments may be lodged by advocates and opponents, investors and securities professionals, academics of all viewpoints, and many others. The
process often results in the Commission substantially adjusting, amending,
or even scrapping its original proposals. The fact that the Commission itself
must contain members from both major political parties also helps to foster
the give and take that improves the decisionmaking process.
Additionally, the SEC uses two simple decisional heuristics that have
served it well over the years: (1) disclosure is good; and (2) fraud is bad.
These are the very heuristics that help combat the shortcomings of purely
private ordering. Although it is certainly true that too much disclosure can
be inecient and that too many resources could be invested in trying to
103
CONCLUSION
In our imperfect world behavioral decision theory makes it clear that
investors do not typically demand full disclosure or protect themselves adequately from fraud, even within the constraints of limited information and
transaction costs. And corporate ocers and directors sometimes fail to
fully disclose, breach their duciary duties, and even commit securities
fraud. Sometimes these actions serve their own rational interests; other
times they are simply manifestations of poor intertemporal decisionmaking or bounded will power.
In a world populated by imperfect decisionmakers, law can advance fairness goals and market eciency. For example, corporate law encourages the
trust that is so critical to investment by helping establish the social norms
that signal proper conduct for managers. Legislation changes what people
believe about approval patterns in their society and because people value
approval (the conformity bias), their new beliefs lead to dierent behaviors.103 When Congress twice in the 1980s passed legislation to punish
insider trading, peoples views of the acceptability of that practice changed.
When the SEC bans misleading and manipulative conduct, nancial
morality evolves.104 These unfair and inecient acts become less acceptable
and people become less likely to engage in them for both legal and moral
reasons. In Professor Welles words, [b]y prohibiting fraud and mandating
disclosure, the securities laws protect investors and promote honesty, trust,
and ethical behavior in commercial transactions. The securities laws set
standards that serve to socialize, to educate and to direct individuals toward
more morally appropriate forms of behavior.105 It is widely acknowledged
that when Congress legislated against securities fraud by passing the 1933
and 1934 Securities Acts, the level of such fraud was reduced.106
No mechanism of social control is perfect and there will be times, as
during the dot.com bubble, when substantial numbers of actors will forget
the rules. It will seem that earnings management is at least kind of ok
because so many competitors are doing it. Bullying auditors into accepting
aggressive accounting measures wont seem so bad, because others actions
are sending the cues that this is acceptable. Round-tripping by telecom
companies and manipulating deregulated markets by energy traders will
temporarily become accepted within the industry. Then it takes action,
such as passage of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act, to remind economic actors
what the social and legal norms truly are.107
104
NOTES
1. Conlisk notes: There is a mountain of experiments in which people: display intransitivity; misunderstand statistical independence; mistake random data for patterned
data and vice versa; fail to appreciate law of large number eects; fail to recognize statistical dominance; make errors in updating probabilities on the basis of new information; understate the signicance of given sample sizes; fail to understand
covariation for even the simplest 22 contingency tables; make false inferences about
causality; ignore relevant information; use irrelevant information (as in sunk cost fallacies); exaggerate the importance of vivid over pallid evidence; exaggerate the importance of fallible predictors; exaggerate the ex ante probability of a random event
which has already occurred; display overcondence in judgment relative to evidence;
exaggerate conrming over disconrming evidence relative to initial beliefs; give
answers that are highly sensitive to logically irrelevant changes in questions; do redundant and ambiguous tests to conrm an hypothesis at the expense of decisive tests to
disconrm; make frequent errors in deductive reasoning tasks such as syllogisms;
place higher value on an opportunity if an experimenter rigs it to be the status quo
opportunity; fail to discount the future consistently; fail to adjust repeated choices to
accommodate intertemporal connections; and more. John Conlisk, Why Bounded
Rationality?, 34 J. ECON. LIT. 669, 670 (1996). See also Larry T. Garvin, Adequate
Assurance of Performance: Of Risk, Duress, and Cognition, 69 U. COLO. L. REV. 71,
145 (1998) (Cognitive psychology and experimental economics have found a smorgasbord of cognitive errors, which collectively falsify most of the axioms of rational
choice theory.).
2. See BOUNDED RATIONALITY: THE ADAPTIVE TOOLBOX (Gerd Gigerenzer &
Reinhard Selten eds. 1999).
3. See THE ECONOMICS OF IRRATIONAL BEHAVIOR (Francesco Parisi & Vernon
Smith eds. forthcoming).
4. Herbert A. Simon, ADMINISTRATIVE BEHAVIOR xxiv (2d ed. 1957).
5. Max H. Bazerman, JUDGMENT IN MANAGERIAL DECISION MAKING 3941
(3d ed. 1994).
6. Leon Festinger, A THEORY OF COGNITIVE DISSONANCE (1957).
7. See Antonio R. Damasio, DESCARTES ERROR (1994).
8. See Werner F.M. De Bondt, A Portrait of the Individual Investor, 42 EUR. ECON. REV.
831 (1998).
9. Robert J. Shiller, IRRATIONAL EXUBERANCE 143 (2000).
10. Barbara Moses, Research Analysts Under Fire, ALI-ABA Broker Dealer Regulation
Course study (January 1011, 2002).
11. See Roni Michaely & Kent L. Womack, Conict of Interest and the Credibility of
Underwriter Analyst Recommendations, 12 REV. FIN. STUD. 653 (1999).
12. See Andrei Shleifer, INEFFICIENT MARKETS: AN INTRODUCTION TO
BEHAVIORAL FINANCE 187 (2000).
13. Irving L. Janis, GROUPTHINK: PSYCHOLOGICAL STUDIES OF POLICY DECISIONS AND FIASCOES 9 (2d ed. 1982).
14. See Max Sutherland, ADVERTISING AND THE MIND OF THE CONSUMER 21
(1993).
15. Showing Fidelity, FINANCIAL TIMES, June 9, 2004, at 14.
16. See Brad M. Barger, et al., OUT OF SIGHT, OUT OF MIND: THE EFFECTS OF
EXPENSES ON MUTUAL FUND FLOWS 1 (December 2003), available at
http://ssrn.com/abstract496315.
17. Daniel Kahneman & Amos Tversky, Prospect Theory: An Analysis of Decision Under
Uncertainty, 47 ECONOMETRICA 263 (1979).
18. See Richard H. Thaler, Mental Accounting Matters, in ADVANCES IN BEHAVIORAL
ECONOMICS 75, 99 (Colin F. Camerer, George Loewenstein & Matthew Rabin eds.
2004).
105
19. Hal R. Arkes & Catherine Blumer, The Psychology of Sunk Cost, 35 ORGANIZATIONAL BEHAV. & HUM. DECISION PROCESSES 124 (1985).
20. TIME AND DECISION: ECONOMIC AND PSYCHOLOGICAL PERSPECTIVES
ON INTERTEMPORAL CHOICE (George Loewenstein, Daniel Read & Roy F.
Baumeister eds. 2003).
21. Reinier H. Kraakman, Corporate Liability Strategies and the Costs of Legal Controls, 93
YALE L. J. 857, 888 (1984).
22. See Robert A. Prentice, Chicago Man, K-T Man, and the Future of Behavioral Law and
Economics, 56 VAND. L. REV. 1663, 16961702 (2003).
23. See Gary W. Emery, CORPORATE FINANCE: PRINCIPLES AND PRACTICE
600603 (1998).
24. Michael C. Jensen, Some Anomalous Evidence Regarding Market Eciency, 6 J. FIN.
ECON. 95 (1978).
25. See Richard H. Thaler, THE WINNERS CURSE (1992); QUASI-RATIONAL
ECONOMICS (1991); ADVANCES IN BEHAVIORAL FINANCE (R. Thaler ed.
1993).
26. See ADVANCES IN BEHAVIORAL ECONOMICS (Colin F. Camerer, George
Loewenstein, & Matthew Rabin eds. 2004).
27. Stephen C. Choi & A.C. Pritchard, Behavioral Economics and the SEC, 56 STAN. L.
REV. 1, 5 (2003).
28. Sholom Benartzi & Richard H. Thaler, Myopic Loss Aversion and the Equity Premium
Puzzle, 110 Q. J. ECON. 73 (1995).
29. Terrance Odean, Do Investors Trade Too Much?, 89 AM. ECON. REV. 1279 (1999).
30. See Richard Deaves, et al., AN EXPERIMENTAL TEST OF THE IMPACT OF
OVERCONFIDENCE AND GENDER ON TRADING ACTIVITY 21 (2003), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract497284.
31. Terrance Odean, Are Investors Reluctant to Realize Their Losses?, 53 J. FIN. 1775 (1998).
32. Dale Grin & Amos Tversky, The Weighing of Evidence and the Determination of
Condence, 24 COG. PSYCHOL. 411 (1992).
33. Nick Barberis, Andrei Shleifer & Robert Vishny, A Model of Investor Sentiment, 49 J.
FIN. ECON. 307 (1998).
34. Larry E. Ribstein, Market vs. Regulatory Responses to Corporate Fraud: A Critique of
the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002, 28 IOWA J. CORP. L. 1, 2223 (2002).
35. Lynn A. Stout, The Unimportance of Being Ecient: An Economic Analysis of Stock
Market Pricing and Securities Regulation, 87 MICH. L. REV. 613, 647 (1988).
36. See Riva D. Atlas, Even the Smart Money Can Slip Up, N.Y. TIMES, December 30, 2001,
sec. 3, at 1.
37. See Robert A. Prentice, Chicago Man, K-T Man, and the Future of Behavioral Law and
Economics, 56 VANDERBILT LAW REVIEW 1663, 172829 (2004).
38. Hersh Shefrin, BEYOND GREED AND FEAR: UNDERSTANDING BEHAVIORAL FINANCE AND THE PSYCHOLOGY OF INVESTING 58 (2000).
39. Jacob Jacoby, Is It Rational to Assume Consumer Rationality? Some Consumer
Psychological Perspectives on Rational Choice Theory 23, N.Y. Univ. Ctr. for Law &
Bus., Working Paper #CLB-00009, 2000.
40. Robert J. Shiller, IRRATIONAL EXUBERANCE 379400 (2000).
41. Robert J. Shiller, Bubbles, Human Judgment, And Expert Opinion 23, 11 Cowles Found.,
Discussion Paper No. 1303 (May 2001).
42. Werner de Bondt, EARNINGS FORECASTS AND SHARE PRICE REVERSALS
(1992).
43. Henry Hu, Misunderstood Derivatives: The Causes of Informational Failure and the
Promise of Regulatory Incrementalism, 102 YALE L. J. 1457, 1489 (1993).
44. Ronald Coase, The Problem of Social Cost, 3 J. L. & ECON. 1 (1960).
45. Cass R. Sunstein, Looking Forward: Behavioral Analysis of Law, 64 U. CHI. L. REV.
1175, 1179 (1997) (The [Coase] theory is wrong because the allocation of the legal entitlement may well matter, in the sense that those who are initially allocated an entitlement
are likely to value it more than those without the legal entitlement.).
106
46. See Cass R. Sunstein, Switching the Default Rule, 77 N.Y.U. L. REV. 106, 112 (2002)
(making this point).
47. Most people have a strong preference for the status quo. See e.g., Colin Camerer,
Prospect Theory in the Wild, in CHOICES, VALUES, AND FRAMES 295 (Daniel
Kahneman & Amos Tversky eds. 2000) (nding that motorists choices of insurance coverage were signicantly aected by default legislative rules); Raymond S. Hartman, et al.,
Consumer Rationality and the Status Quo, 106 Q. J. ECON. 141, 160 (1991) (nding that
electricity consumers given a choice between higher rates with higher reliability service
and lower rates with lower reliability tended to choose whichever choice was presented
as representing the status quo); William F. Samuelson & Richard Zeckhauser, Status
Quo Bias in Decision Making, 1 J. RISK & UNCERTAINTY 7, 2633 (1988) (nding
that people tend to select whichever investment alternative or health plan is presented as
the status quo); Maurice Schweitzer, Disentangling Status Quo and Omission Eects: An
Experimental Analysis, 58 ORG. BEHAV. & HUM. DECISION PROCESSES 457,
47273 (1994) (reporting experiments nding that people prefer both the status quo and
inaction and that these preferences can be additive).
48. Robert A. Prentice & Jonathan J. Koehler, A Normality Bias in Legal Decision Making,
88 CORNELL L. REV. 583 (2003); John S. Hammond, Ralph L. Keeney, & Howard
Raia, The Hidden Traps in Decision Making, HARVARD BUSINESS REVIEW 47
(SeptemberOctober 1998).
49. See David Cohen & Jack L. Knetsch, Judicial Choice and Disparities Between Measures
of Economic Values, 30 OSGOODE HALL L.J. 737 (1992).
50. See Russell Korobkin, The Status Quo Bias and Contract Default Rules, 83 CORNELL
L. REV. 608 (1998).
51. See G. Richard Shell, Fair Play, Consent and Securities Arbitration: A Comment on
Speidel, 62 BROOK. L. REV. 1365, 136769 (1996).
52. Francesco Parisi & Vernon Smith, THE LAW AND ECONOMICS OF IRRATIONAL
BEHAVIOR: AN INTRODUCTION 5 (2004), available at http://ssrn.com/
abstract537784.
53. See Ernst Fehr & Simon Gachter, Fairness and Retaliation: The Economics of
Reciprocity, J. ECON. PERSP. 159 Summer 2000.
54. E. Allan Farnsworth, CONTRACTS 2, 1314 (1982).
55. Id. at 326.
56. Id. at 232.
57. See Evelin Sullivan, THE CONCISE BOOK OF LYING 206 (2001).
58. DiLeo v. Ernst & Young, 901 F.2d 624 (7th Cir. 1990).
59. Patricia M. Dechow, et al., Causes and Consequences of Earnings Manipulation: An
Analysis of Firms Subject to Enforcement Actions by the SEC, 13 CONTEMP. ACCT.
RES. 1, 31 (1996).
60. Tom Lauricella, For Staid Mutual-Fund Industry, Growing Probe Signals Shake-Up,
WALL ST. J., October 20, 2003, at A1 (quoting Levitt).
61. See Tom Lauricella & Deborah Solomon, Scrutiny of Mutual Funds Grows as SEC
Probes Deals With Brokers, WALL ST. J., October 23, 2003, at A1 (quoting Bogle).
62. All examples in the following laundry list are explicated in detail and documented fully
in Robert A. Prentice, The Case of the Irrational Auditor: A Behavioral Insight into
Securities Fraud Litigation, 95 NW. U. L. REV. 133 (2000).
63. George Loewenstein, Behavioral Decision Theory and Business Ethics: Skewed TradeOs Between Self and Others, in CODES OF CONDUCT: BEHAVIORAL
RESEARCH INTO BUSINESS ETHICS 214, 226 (David M. Missick & Ann E.
Tenbrunsel eds. 1996).
64. George M. Cohen, When Law and Economics Met Professional Responsibility, 67
FORDHAM L. REV. 273, 288 (1998).
65. William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner, THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF TORT
LAW 28081 (1987). Some game theorists have posited that it is, in many factual scenarios, rational for buyers to decide not to read seller-provided form contracts. See e.g., Avery
Katz, The Strategic Structure of Oer and Acceptance: Game Theory and the Law of
66.
67.
68.
69.
70.
71.
72.
73.
74.
75.
76.
77.
78.
79.
80.
81.
82.
83.
84.
107
Contract Formation, 89 MICH. L. REV. 215, 28293 (1990) (noting the fact that the
decision to spend resources becoming informed must precede the information that reveals
whether it is worth doing so, and that the drafters of form contracts have the incentive to
take advantage of this . . . [And] it is just this fact that makes reading irrational.).
Margaret M. Blair & Lynn A. Stout, Trust, Trustworthiness, and the Behavioral
Foundations of Corporate Law, 149 U. PA. L. REV. 1735 (2001).
See Thomas Donaldson & Thomas W. Dunfee, TIES THAT BIND: A SOCIAL CONTRACTS APPROACH TO BUSINESS ETHICS 9596 (1999): Outside sources may
inuence the development of norms. Law, particularly when it is perceived as legitimate
by members of a community, may have a major impact on what is considered to be
correct behavior. Thus, the U.S. Corporate Sentencing Guidelines may be expected to
inuence perceptions of appropriate structures and policies for assigning managerial
responsibility pertaining to corporate social responsibility. Conventional wisdom holds
that U.S. law has inuenced changes in ethical norms pertaining to racial or genderbased discrimination and also as to the legitimacy of insider trading. See also Mark
Kelman, Consumption Theory, Production Theory, and Ideology in the Coase Theorem, 52
S. CAL. L. REV. 669, 695 (1979) (noting that perhaps society learns what to value in
part through the legal systems descriptions of our protected spheres); Eric A. Posner,
Law, Economics, and Inecient Norms, 144 U. PA. L. REV. 1697, 1731 (1996) (laws
inevitably strengthen or weaken social norms by signaling an ocial stance toward
them).
Blair & Stout, supra note 66, at 1809.
Id. at 178586.
Id. at 1787.
Iman Anabtawi, Secret Compensation, 82 N.C. L. REV. 835, 837 (2004).
Michael B. Dor, Softening Pharaohs Heart: Harnessing Altruistic Theory and
Behavioral Law and Economics to Rein in Executive Salaries, 51 BUFF. L. REV. 811,
82829 (2003).
Donald C. Langevoort, Organized Illusions: A Behavioral Theory of Why Corporations
Mislead Stock Market Investors (and Cause Other Social Harms), 146 U. PA. L. REV.
101 (1997).
Frank H. Easterbrook & Daniel R. Fischel, THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF
CORPORATE LAW 93100 (1991).
See Hal R. Arkes & Cindy Schipani, Medical Malpractice v. the Business Judgment Rule:
Dierences in the Hindsight Bias, 73 OR. L. REV. 587 (1994).
This discussion largely tracks a discussion contained in Robert A. Prentice, Whither
Securities Regulation? Some Behavioral Observations Regarding Proposals for its Future,
51 DUKE L.J. 1397 (2002).
Abolaa, infra note 80, at 187.
Frank Partnoy, F.I.A.S.C.O.: BLOOD IN THE WATER ON WALL STREET (1997),
at 6061.
Michael Lewis, LIARS POKER: RISING THROUGH THE WRECKAGE OF
WALL STREET 16470 (1989).
See Dean Witter, Ocials Face NASDR Charges Over Sales of Risky Bond Trust
Investments, BNA SEC. L. DAILY, Nov. 21, 2000. [See also Mitchel Y. Abolaa,
MAKING MARKETS: OPPORTUNISM AND RESTRAINT ON WALL STREET
4 (1996) (noting a seemingly unending stream of recent scandals involving professional stock traders).
See Ellen Kelleher, Brokers Face Action Over Annuity Advice, FINANCIAL TIMES,
June 10, 2004, at 20.
Mitchell Pacelle, Republic New York Pleads Guilty to Fraud, Agrees to Pay Restitution,
WALL ST. J., December 18, 2001, at C10.
Hersh. M. Shefrin & Meir Statman, Explaining Investor Preference for Cash Dividends,
in ADVANCES IN BEHAVIORAL FINANCE 393, 408 (Richard Thaler, ed. 1993).
G. Richard Shell, Opportunism and Trust in the Negotiation of Commercial Contracts:
Toward a New Cause of Action, 44 VAND. L. REV 221, 269 (1991) at 269.
108
85. Thus, one prominent study shows evidence of a reputational constraint, but also evidence that the constraint is hardly a strong one. See Willard T. Carleton, et al., Optimism
Biases Among Brokerage and Non-Brokerage Firms Equity Recommendations: Agency
Costs in the Investment Industry, 27 FIN. MGMT. 17 (Spring 1998). Carleton, Chen, and
Steiner studied thousands of stock recommendations made by national brokerage rms,
regional brokerage rms, and nonbrokerage rms. The brokerage rms have an incentive to give more positive recommendations than nonbrokerage rms because they want
to stay on good terms with the issuers whose business they would like to cultivate. And,
indeed, the studys ndings were that brokerage rms recommendations were more optimistic than those of nonbrokerage rms. Id. at 19. On the other hand, they found that
regional brokerage rms, which have less reputational capital to protect, tend to inate
their recommendations as compared to national brokerage rms. Id. at 1920. Thus, the
nonbrokerage rms which had less self-interest at stake had more accurate recommendations than the brokerage rms. Id. at 20. But among the brokerage rms, the national
rms with more reputational capital to protect proered more accurate recommendations than the regional rms. Id.
86. Stephen M. Bainbridge, Mandatory Disclosure: A Behavioral Analysis, 68 U. CIN. L.
REV. 1023 (2000).
87. Id. at 1026.
88. Id. at 103741.
89. Id. at 104143.
90. William Samuelson & Richard Zeckhauser, Status Quo Bias in Decision Making, 1 J.
RISK & UNCERTAINTY 7 (1988).
91. See Jean C. Bedard, An Archival Investigation of Audit Program Planning, AUDITING:
A J. OF PRAC & THEORY 57, 5758 (Fall 1989).
92. Bainbridge, supra note 86, at 104953.
93. See Robyn M. Dawes, Social Dilemmas, 31 ANN. REV. PSYCHOL. 169, 187 (1980).
94. The following material is summarized from a much longer treatment contained in Robert
A. Prentice, Contract-Based Defenses in Securities Fraud Litigation: A Behavioral
Analysis, U. ILL. L. REV. 337 (2003).
95. William M. Landes & Richard A. Posner, THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF TORT
LAW 28081 (1987).
96. Larry E. Ribstein, Market vs. Regulatory Responses to Corporate Fraud: A Critique of
the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002, 28 IOWA J. CORP. L. 1, 2223 (2002).
97. Nothing But the Truth About Why We Tell Lies, FINANCIAL TIMES, May 28, 2004
(citing Michael Berry, a senior lecturer in forensic psychology at Manchester
Metropolitan University who notes that people who lie in business have no emotional
attachment to the business lie, so most lie detection systems would not discover them.).
98. See G. Richard Shell, Fair Play, Consent and Securities Arbitration: A Comment on
Speidel, 62 BROOK. L. REV. 1365, 1368 (1996).
99. See Stephen Choi & Mitu Gulati, Innovation in Boilerplate Contracts: An Empirical
Examination of Sovereign Bonds, 53 EMORY L.J. 929 (2004).
100. Hillary A. Sale, Gatekeepers, Disclosure, and Issuer Choice, 81 WASH. U. L. Q. 403,
406 (2003) (noting that the market did not adequately discount even for risks that
were fully disclosed and questioning whether investors could accurately process information about which issuers chose pro-investor regimes and which chose anti-investor
regimes).
101. Stephen J. Choi, Promoting Issuer Choice in Securities Regulation, 41 VA. J. INTL. L.
815, 825 (2001).
102. See generally Stephen C. Choi & A.C. Pritchard, Behavioral Economics and the SEC, 56
STAN. L. REV. 1 (2003).
103. Richard H. McAdams, An Attitudinal Theory of Expressive Law, 79 OR. L. REV. 339,
389 (2000).
104. Joel Seligman, THE TRANSFORMATION OF WALL STREET 17879 (rev. ed. 1995)
(noting long-term impact of the SECs revolution in nancial morality accomplished
in the 1930s).
109
105. Elaine Welle, Freedom of Contract and the Securities Laws: Opting Out of Securities
Regulation by Private Agreement, 56 WASH. & LEE L. REV. 519, 541 (1999).
106. See id. at 56162. See also Jerey J. Rachlinski, The Limits of Social Norms, 74
CHI.KENT L. REV. 1537, 1544 (2000) (even in the absence of enforcement the mere
act of criminalizing conduct can reduce its prevalence).
107. Robert A. Prentice, Enroll: A Brief Behavioral Autopsy, 40 AM. BUS. L. REV. 417,
44344 (2003).
BASIC LAW
There is little controversy regarding the importance for an economys prosperity of respect for the rule of law, a reliable court system, and basic
110
111
contract, property, and tort law. As early as the twelfth century, monarchs
in parts of Europe began providing security and dispute resolution to their
subjects, thereby paving the way for predictability and trust in commercial
relationships. Over time, development of the basic bodies of law preceded
and paved the way for economic growth.
Contract Law
Certainly familiarity and trust facilitate commercial relationships. But
without some governmental enforcement mechanism, historically people
trusted and dealt with few beyond friends and family. True, in the eleventh
century, the Maghribi, Moroccan traders, built a trading system in the
Mediterranean area by creating a system of collective sanctions that it
applied to entire groups. If one trader from Genoa breached an agreement
with a trader from Morocco, all Genoans were punished.4 This created an
incentive for all Genoan traders to band together and self-police their
members conduct. While this system created an atmosphere that extended
trade beyond friends and relatives, it was not as eective as modern
government-enforced rules carrying surer enforcement mechanisms and
more targeted remedies.
From a modern vantage point in a developed nation, it is dicult to
fathom why legal systems all over the world had diculty developing theoretical bases for enforcing commercial promises, even though rudimentary
contractual arrangements date back at least 5000 years to Mesopotamia.
In the Western tradition, Roman law initially developed the notion that a
promise may give rise to an enforceable duty, but never advanced
suciently to broadly enforce executory promises.5 Written codes promulgated by European rulers before 1100 A.D. or so seldom contained any but
the most eeting reference to commercial law. The English common law of
contracts emerged in the twelfth century, borrowing heavily from Roman
law, especially Justinians Corpus Juris Civilis. Common law courts initially
enforced only formal promises known as covenants that were made in
writing and sealed with wax. These formalities stultied development as
commercial arrangements became more numerous and complex.
Economic actors required a method of enforcing informal promises
without resorting to the time-consuming and expensive process of putting
all arrangements in writing and sealing them with wax.
Through the tort of assumpsit, the English common law courts slowly
began to allow recovery against parties who failed to carry out a formal
contractual promise. However, for a long time even this promising new
avenue allowed no remedy for a party who simply failed to perform an
informal promise. Then, the common law courts extended their willingness
112
113
banks are willing to make such loans because they know that they can gain
legal ownership of the house if the loan is not repaid. In this way, homes
and other possessions are used to nance most small businesses, which are
the engines driving a substantial portion of economic growth even in
economies apparently dominated by large multinational corporations.
By contrast, in developing nations that lack a property rights system,
aspiring entrepreneurs cannot prove they own their homes, cannot bind
themselves to transfer title, and therefore cannot induce potential lenders
to take a chance on making a loan. At Americas birth, a sophisticated
modern property rights system was not yet in place, but soon thereafter
Americans and Europeans established widespread formal property law that
allowed owners to convert their property into capital, launching capitalism
on a rapidly rising trajectory.10 Simply put, for developing nations weak
property rights are a bigger problem than limited access to external nance
because they discourage entrepreneurs from reinvesting their retained earnings.11 Capitalism triumphed in Western nations in large part because property law allowed people to cooperate and produce under a single integrated
system in an expanded market.12 Even among Western nations, dierences
in legal systems caused dierential economic growth. In the seventeenth
century England and the Netherlands surpassed France and Spain in part
because they did the better job of establishing and securing property
rights.13 Since the fall of the Berlin Wall, one of the most signicant impediments to many formerly communist nations economic revival has been an
absence of doctrines, institutions, and traditions needed to adequately
protect property rights. As Nobel laureate Mancur Olson notes, secure
and well-dened rights for all to private property and impartial enforcement of contracts14 is essential to economic success.
Ronald Coases famous theorem assumes zero transaction costs and concludes that in such a world, rational self-interested parties will inevitably
bargain to the most ecient solution. In addition to the errors inherent in
an assumption of rationality pointed out in the previous chapter, there is
no world without transaction costs, as Coase conceded when he gave his
Nobel laureate address:
If we move from a regime of zero transaction costs to one of positive transaction costs, what becomes immediately clear is the crucial importance of the legal
system in this new world . . . While we can imagine in the hypothetical world of
zero transaction costs that the parties to an exchange would negotiate to change
any provision of the law which prevents them from taking whatever steps are
required to increase the value of production, in the real world of positive transaction costs such a procedure would be extremely costly, and would make
unprotable, even when it was allowed, such a contracting around the law.
Because of this, the rights which individuals possess, with their duties and
114
privileges, will be to a large extent what the law determines. As a result the legal
system will have a profound eect on the working of the economic system and
may in certain respects be said to control it.15
In short, property law protects property, which is the most signicant incentive that exists to motivate people to generate wealth and prosperity.
Most empirical studies indicate that countries with legal systems that
protect property rights have economies that regularly outperform the
economies of countries that do not.16 In todays information age, a particular form of property lawthat protecting intellectual propertyis
arguably the single most important factor in the transition to modern
growth because it increases the fraction of output paid to compensate creative minds for the fruits of their labor.17 The rst known patent law was
passed in Venice in 1474, and some have linked the beginning of the
Industrial Revolution to the fact that England and France concluded in the
1700s that patent rights were protectable property rights. There is evidence
that during the 1800s Americas economic development outstripped
Englands because America had more advanced patent law and thereby
granted more patents and encouraged more inventiveness by its citizens.
Tort Law
In addition to ecient enforcement of contracts and protection of property rights, one other foundational feature of an ecient economy is needed
promotion of fair play. Capitalism, it turns out, is not a naturally occurring system. It requires rules, laws and customs to protect private property,
enforce contracts and ensure fair play. Until those are in place you dont get
a free market but a free-for-all, which quickly becomes the rule of the
strong.18 Fraud leads to inecient allocation of resources and discourages
economic actors from participating in markets, so the legal systems of all
nations attempt to provide remedies for defrauded buyers and sellers.
Simple fairness is valued by humans in every society. Rules that punish
deceit not only provide remedies for unacceptable conduct but also signal
commercial actors as to what standards they will be held to. In so doing,
tort rules benecially shape nations commercial atmospheres.
The basic law of deceit in common law nations is grounded in the earliest English law. As early as 1201, English common law recognized a very
limited writ of deceit, which slowly evolved from what today we would consider breaches of contract into an independent tort. Both civil and criminal remedies for fraud in commercial transactions have been staples of the
common law for centuries. Similarly, civil law nations have long punished
fraud. For example, the Napoleonic Code from early on contained several
115
116
enforce them or the right of injured individuals to sue for their breach, and
without eective legal processes to reach fair results in these actions, the
substantive rights themselves mean little. The quality of courts is important, as is the substance of the law. The US common law judge-made system
derives from English tradition, while most continental European nations
use a civil law system of statutory codes.
CORPORATE LAW
Although the rst semi-comprehensive corporate codes date back less than
two hundred years, the roots of business organizations can be traced back
at least to Mesopotamia in 3000 BC. Ancient Phoenicians and Athenians
developed early forms of partnership. In medieval times, shipping businesses aggregated capital and distributed shares in a form closely resembling modern partnerships. Although some trace the origin of corporations
to the ancient Greeks,25 Blackstone concluded long ago that the honor of
inventing companies belonged to the Romans, for they devised the notion
of a corporation having an identity separate and apart from that of its
owners and the concept of limited liability.
The development of the corporation was critically important. Around
1000 AD both the Chinese and the Arabs had important trading and commercial advantages over the West, but many suggest that because their legal
systems were not conducive to developing companies,26 they lost the commercial advantage that they enjoyed.27 Rather, in the twelfth century in
Venice and Florence, in the sixteenth century in England and soon thereafter in France, in the early seventeenth century in Holland, and in the late
1700s in America, the modern legal notion of a corporation began to
evolve and ourish, sparking economic development that outstripped that
of nations without the legal structures to create such entities.
These proto-corporations initially took two basic forms. One was the
unincorporated joint-stock company that slowly evolved to contain more
and more corporate-like features and to resemble less and less the partnership form. The other was the specially-chartered corporation that was often
privately nanced but featured government participation and was often a
government-sheltered monopoly. In the late 1700s and early 1800s in
England, France, and America, such special charters were often granted to
corporations formed for public works projects that governments did not
wish to undertake via tax revenues, such as canals and roads.
Until the nineteenth century, governments in these nations required promoters to receive special government permission for their enterprises to
assume the corporate form. During the 1800s, however, todays developed
117
118
While it is possible for large organizations to be operated in the partnership form, as large accounting rms proved for a time, it was exceedingly
rare for businesses to amass huge quantities of assets, to employ thousands
119
of workers, or to take on truly large projects before the modern corporation began to evolve.
As noted, because of the very novelty of the corporate form, fear of great
accumulations of assets, sovereign worry about loss of control, and even
undue greed by government ocials, for quite a time in most nations the
law required a specic act of government to create a corporation. Placed in
historical context, it is not surprising that governments imposed these
requirements, but it is also clear that such requirements retarded corporate
formation, presented opportunities for corruption when promoters were
tempted to bribe government ocials, and even enabled fraud by promoters who collected assets while promising to form a corporation that they
knew the government would likely not approve. The need for government
approval also restrained economic development by sometimes requiring
intrepid entrepreneurs to accomplish their goals through less satisfactory
forms of business organization including partnerships and unincorporated
joint-stock companies. For example, although Englands Bubble Act of
1720 is typically referred to as one of the earliest securities regulations, its
most signicant provision made it illegal to sell shares in joint-stock companies that had not received Parliamentary permission to form. Until it was
repealed in 1825, this Act may have inhibited evolution of the modern corporate form in England (although the Act did not apply to Scotland, and
joint-stock companies did not ourish there either).34 Many believe that a
turning point in American corporate development occurred with the postRevolution formation of a strong federal government which made it clear
that the Bubble Act no longer applied in America. Formation of corporations exploded thereafter in the former colonies.35
With the decision in Fletcher v. Peck36 that a legislative grant to a private
company was a contract under the American Constitutions Contract
Clause, and in Dartmouth College37 that a corporations state charter was
also a contract that could not be altered by the legislature unless the right
to do so had been specically reserved in the charter, the safe existence of
the corporation relatively free from legislative interference was armed
and capital owed to corporations in amounts ensuring that they would be
the preeminent vehicles for economic growth in America.38
Only as the laws of England, France, Germany, and the United States
(which have served as a model for the corporate laws of most other nations
around the world) dispensed with the requirement of special governmental
approval for corporate formation did the modern corporation begin to
ower. Allowing large numbers of articial corporate entities to enjoy corporate personhood, to own property, to sue in their own name, to (in
America) enjoy substantial Constitutional rights, provided exibility and
continuity unmatched by other forms of business enterprise.
120
Perpetuity
An important aspect of the new corporate form was the potential perpetuity of its existence. Sole proprietorships obviously ended with the death of
their owner (although an heir or another might take up the burdens of the
business). The default common law position was that partnerships also dissolved upon the death or other departure of any of the partners. Early
joint-stock companies, such as those in England, often were formed for the
purpose of collecting capital to stock a ship for trading in newly discovered
lands. Typically, the merchants who chartered the ship with their pooled
capital would have an accounting after each journey. The next trade
mission would involve an entirely new enterprise.
Thus, the notion of a truly long-term business enterprise was rare in
private business ventures. The concept of perpetual existence of a corporate form may have evolved in ecclesiastical organizations as a way to
enable churches to own property over time even as parishioners, priests, and
others came and went. Obviously, such an ability could be useful to private
business enterprises as well.
In 1623 the Dutch East India Company was granted the right of perpetuity. It collected capital to fund not just one voyage, but a potentially
endless series of voyages. In 1654 the British East India Company followed
suit. These entities paved the way for creation of large accumulations of
capital that could be used to advance business endeavors over long periods
of time. Owners could come and go. Managers could come and go. But the
enterprise would continue, making binding commitments to employees, to
suppliers, to customers, and to creditors of a character that sole proprietorships and partnerships could not make. The corporate form could more
easily undertake long-term endeavors than any preexisting form of enterprise. And the corporate entity itself could establish a reputation in the economic communityseparate and apart from that of its individual owners
or managersthat would assist it in achieving commercial success. Simple
contract law could never accomplish such progress.
Limited Liability
Many believe that corporate laws most signicant contribution to the development of capitalism is limited liability. More than any other single concept,
limited liability encourages people to invest in enterprises operated by
strangers, enabling business enterprises to grow to substantial size and enjoy
economies of scale, the benets of perpetuity, and other advantages of size.
In earlier times, sole proprietorships tended to employ family members and
neighbors. Partnerships were necessarily small because partners needed to
121
know much about the reliability of their fellow investors/partners for the
simple reason that if other partners defaulted, then the personal liability of
the nondefaulters could skyrocket. For many years, partners who were
unable to pay their obligations faced debtors prison or even the prospect of
being sold into slavery. Such a state certainly discouraged any person from
casting his economic lot with strangers.
While it is perhaps theoretically possible for partnerships to contract for
limited liability for their partners when negotiating contracts (just as it is
possible for shareholders to contractually forfeit their limited liability as
they often do in close corporations), in matters of tort law such is not possible. The owners of a company could not contract for limited liability with
unknown and possibly unforeseeable victims of the tortious actions of their
companies managers and employees. The corporate form can provide such
protection for liabilities in tort as well as contract, thereby facilitating
investment because a shareholders total potential liability is generally
unaected by the personal reliability or solvency of other shareholders.
Limited liability solves an agency problem. Without it, shareholders would
have to monitor much more closely and expensively their corporate managers. Limited liability protects shareholders from liability, shifting the risk
to the corporate entities creditors who often are better equipped and more
intensely motivated to monitor than shareholders of a corporation whose
ownership is widely dispersed.39
Limited liability was initially recognized for government-sponsored corporations, such as the Dutch East India Company. Slowly, it began to
become a more common feature of private corporations, especially as
general corporation statutes spread. Britain in 1855 formally recognized
limited liability; Germany did so in 1861 and France in 1863. Over the
course of the nineteenth century, limited liability became the default rule in
American jurisdictions as well (although not in California until 1931).
Limited liability came in stages and was likely not as important to shareholders in the early 1800s as it later became, but virtually every relevant legislative change in the developed countries during the nineteenth century
strengthened and broadened the shield of limited liability and thereby gave
added incentive to the investment that is critical to economic development.
Limited liability is arguably a near prerequisite for broad investor participation in company ownership.40 With the advent of modern tort liability
for on-the-job injuries, for automobile crashes, and for product defects,
limited liability has become so important that even the law governing small
entities stresses its importance. In America in recent years state legislatures
have created all manner of new organizational forms (limited liability partnerships, limited liability companies, and limited liability limited partnerships, for example) to provide limited liability for almost all entrepreneurs.
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
that it cannot be easily withdrawn. Over the course of the twentieth century
in America, repeated changes in the law aimed at tightening this connection, which was recognized as early as 1824 in Wood v. Dummer57 where
Judge Story explicated the trust fund doctrine.
Corporate law works comparably in other nations, facilitating large
accumulations of capital that can be held in place for long periods of time
and applied by professional managers. By providing limited liability and
protecting investors from exploitation by managers and majority shareholders, the corporate form should also encourage investment.
Conclusion
While the history of corporate law certainly highlights important dierences among the various nations in addressing very basic issues such as
stakeholder rights, shareholder remedies like derivative suits, and other
issues, there has been substantial convergence toward the common law
model as evolved in England, and especially America. Even before 2002,
experts had pointed to the substantial convergence toward the American
model in terms of black letter law around the world.58 Whether nations had
the will, resources, and institutions necessary to eectuate the protection of
minority shareholders deemed a critical priority in every nation was
another matter, of course. Those that succeeded in producing those institutions seemed to prosper more than those that did not.
After the 2002 enactment of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act, in which the
American Congress largely mandated that corporations formed in other
nations but accessing American capital markets must adopt important
aspects of American-style corporate governance, that convergence was hastened. Although there was immediate resistance by European and Japanese
companies, there is now increasing acceptance that Sarbanes-Oxleys
requirements of independent directors, strong audit committees, stringent enforcement of disclosure and antifraud requirements, and the rest,
constitute worldwide best practices insofar as the current state of knowledge goes.
Although the EU will not adopt the Sarbanes-Oxley Acts requirements in
toto, many European commentators have recognized the wisdom of emulating the core Sarbanes-Oxley requirements. Germany, France, the United
Kingdom, and other EU nations on their own impetus have for the past
decade moved toward more independent boards, greater use of audit committees, more vigilant auditors, and more realistic and uniform accounting
standards. While some argue that governance reforms of this type should not
be imposed from the top down, but should be evolutionary and marketdriven,59 they admit the desirability and inevitability of such changes.
129
SECURITIES REGULATION
Having corporate and other ecient forms of business organization will
have little impact if those organizations cannot raise the funds necessary to
pursue entrepreneurial ventures. The three basic business inputs are, after
all, land, labor, and capital. As noted in the previous discussion, corporate
law can induce investment by oering limited liability and can bond those
funds to the corporate purpose. But perhaps other legal features can help
as well, especially those oered by securities regulation.
William Bernstein pointed out in his recent book The Birth of Plenty:
How the Prosperity of the Modern World was Created, that world economic
growth was essentially at from as far back as we can measure until around
1820, when sustained growth began in some parts of what we now consider
the developed world. Based on the preceding thousand years, one would
have projected perhaps a doubling of per capita GDP in the 172 years following 1820. Instead, Englands increased tenfold and Americas twentyfold.60 What accounts for this recent, sustained development? Bernstein
maintains that such rapid development requires the coalescence of four
factors. Two have little to do with our story: scientic rationalism (so that
ideas can be created for eventual commercialization and development), and
fast and ecient communications and transportation (as Stephen Ambrose
pointed out, in Thomas Jeersons time, no goods or information could
move faster than the fastest horse).61 Bernsteins third factor was discussed
abovethe development of property rights that encourage men and
women to work hard and to create by allowing them to keep a fair portion
of the fruits of their labor and not worry about arbitrary conscation by
the government or others.
The fourth and nal factor necessary for economic progress, Bernstein
maintains, is capital markets. Before 1820 or so, few of even the most entrepreneurial minds with the best business ideas had access to the amounts of
money needed to bring their ideas to market.62 This section traces the
historical development of modern securities regulation and explores the
ways in which it may have assisted the development of ecient modern
capital markets, focusing on four areas of law: (a) disclosure requirements,
130
(b) misrepresentation provisions, (c) insider trading rules, and (d) tender
oer rules.
The discussion necessarily draws articial distinctions between securities
regulation and corporate law. As noted earlier, had Englands Bubble Act
simply stated that no corporation could be formed without the special
authorization of Parliament, it would have been viewed as a corporation
law. But by providing that no one could sell securities of corporations
formed without such authority, the Act appeared more like a securities law.
Insider trading rules similarly address an agency problem at the heart of
corporate law and tender oers are one of a variety of forms of corporate
organic change that are central to many corporate law concerns. Proxy rules
embedded in US securities laws represent an attempt to give meaning to an
important corporate law rightthe shareholder right to vote. Even
Englands original securities disclosure rules were embedded within its corporate law in the Company Acts, and Americas recent Sarbanes-Oxley Act
took dead aim at corporate governance practices even though it is viewed
essentially as a securities law. So, clearly, these bodies of law are closely
related and any distinction between them is necessarily arbitrary.
The history of capital market development is largely a Western story
rather than a Middle Eastern story, for Islamic law eventually came to be
interpreted as largely prohibiting the charging of interest (although it was
not so interpreted originally). With no interest there are few loans. Without
loans there is little investment. And, of course, without investment there can
be no capital markets.63 Additionally, these nations lacked clearly dened
property rights. Only in 2004 did nanciers in the Muslim world receive
Koranic permission to form the rst Islamic hedge fund, for example. Nor,
until quite recently, is this a story of the Far East, for Japan, China, Korea,
and other nations had the resources but lacked the institutions (especially
property rights) necessary to create capital markets until they began to
adopt Western ideas. Their emulation of Western laws over the past century
is a testament to a broad worldwide consensus that Western nations have
generally the correct approach to stimulating broad capital investment.
General Background
For many centuries and in many parts of the world, commercial instruments that meet modern denitions of securities have been sold and
traded. Venice had a secondary market in securities as early as the fourteenth century. The Amsterdam Bourse was created in 1530, though it is
largely famous today for the Tulip Mania of 163637. The Dutch also
invented investment banking, allowing the risk of loans to be distributed
among thousands of investors in the seventeenth century.
131
132
133
case in the entire eighteenth century and therefore had minimal impact on
the practice of securities trading,70 although it likely discouraged to at least
a minor degree the evolution of joint-stock companies.
Although Parliament often debated serious reforms over the following
century, with the exception of a 1722 law that harshly punished (by death)
the forging or counterfeiting of a power to transfer securities, the only securities measure enacted in England during this time was Sir John Barnards
Act in 1834. Barnards Act was entitled An act to prevent the infamous
practice of stockjobbing, and aimed primarily at the more speculative
forms of securities trading, those involving time bargains (options). Its
primary remedy was to make such deals unenforceable. Because of the
general benet of options trading, Barnards Acts primary eect was not
to eliminate such trading, which apparently continued apace, but to impose
upon legitimate dealers losses caused by others who occasionally chose to
refuse to live up to their contracts. The evidence indicates that Barnards
Act had little impact on actual market practices, especially because courts
generally construed its application narrowly.71 Whatever impact it did have
was probably negative, restricting the ability of investors and others to
manage risk. By the 1770s, there was little or no active regulation of the
British nancial markets, as a philosophy of self-regulation took hold.
Markets did not ourish in this regulatory vacuum. Because of the high
risk and lack of information regarding private companies, investors preferred to put their money in government debt instruments.72
After more than a century of ineective regulation, Barnards Act was
repealed in 1860 at a time when large corporations were nally becoming
common, especially those building railroads. For the rst time, corporate
securities were becoming the most important investment instrument and
the need for a body of securities law was becoming evident. The United
Kingdom led the way. Other nations eventually followed, with the United
States adopting the rst fully comprehensive body of securities law in the
1930s. That body of law addressed issues of disclosure, fraud prevention,
insider trading, and, as amended 35 years later, tender oers.
Disclosure
Mandatory disclosure is a critical part of the securities laws of most developed nations. Before securities laws began requiring disclosure by corporations, corporate promoters and managers typically disclosed relatively
little information to either potential investors or current shareholders.73
Mahoney makes a persuasive case that the earliest forms of disclosure rules
were aimed at protecting investors from the multitude of ways in which promoters and managers could exploit information asymmetries to prot
134
unfairly. This lack of reliable and timely disclosure undoubtedly discouraged investment and thereby retarded development of broad capital
markets.74 Institution of mandatory disclosure has simultaneously mitigated this agency problem and created the conditions for the evolution of
large, ecient capital markets.
While the Italians invented double-entry bookkeeping, the British are
most responsible for modern nancial reporting. After the Bubble Act of
1720 was rescinded in 1825, joint-stock companies in England proliferated.
Unfortunately, these unregulated entities committed a noticeable amount of
fraud, so via the Joint-Stock Companies Registration, Incorporation and
Regulation Act of 1844, Parliament sought to minimize abuses by requiring
certain minimal disclosures and the ling of semi-annual audited balance
sheets with the Board of Trade. The Companies Clauses Consolidation Act
of 1845 further required rms to prepare a balance sheet 14 days prior to
any ordinary meeting of shareholders. However, these requirements were
soon allowed to lapse and were replaced by exhortations that companies
voluntarily make similar disclosures. This experiment with a system of voluntary disclosure, unfortunately, soon proved inadequate to protect
investors.75
The Overend Gurney bank collapse, which led to the Panic of 1866,
made it clear that corporate laws imposition of duciary duties upon promoters was insucient to protect investors. Parliament reacted in 1868 by
requiring promoters to disclose in their prospectuses information about
prior contracts entered into by the company, its promoters, directors, or
trustees. The Overend Gurney debacle ignited a debate over the mandatory
disclosure issue that lasted for 35 years. Parliament enacted laws that
required disclosure by railroads (1868), utilities (1871, 1882), and banks
(1879). Ultimately, this trend culminated in passage of the Companies Act
of 1900 that for the rst time required most public corporations to provide
audited nancial statements to their shareholders. A 1908 revision required
the statements to be led with the Board of Trade, but not until the
Companies Act of 1928 were requirements for the form and content of
nancial statements and for distribution to shareholders prior to meetings
fully in place.
As in England, American corporations made minimal disclosure in the
early 1800s.76 One observer wrote in 1840 that directors endeavor to keep
the stockholders and the public in the dark respecting the condition of the
corporation, while they are themselves in the light . . . They make no exhibit
to the stockholders of the actual condition of the market.77 The reasons
were quite clear and very self-serving. Because corporations made no
disclosures, their declarations of dividends were the clearest signal they sent
to the market regarding their progress.78 If a company was progressing well,
135
its directors could declare a small dividend, sending a negative signal to the
market. The stock price would drop and they could buy the shares up,
becoming major owners of a successful corporation. If the company was
struggling, the directors could declare a large dividend. The stock price
would rise, and they could sell their shares on favorable terms and thereby
bail out of a failing enterprise.79
Although in the late 1800s regulators required railroads and utilities to
make regular reports of their nancial condition, most of Americas other
leading corporations maintained the utmost secrecy, either as a matter of
tradition, or on the grounds of competition.80 The prevailing corporate
philosophy was publicly displayed in testimony before the Industrial
Commission in 1899 by Henry O. Havemeyer, president of the American
Sugar Rening Company, who was asked whether he believed that the
public had no right to know what his companys earning power was and no
right to inspect its books before blindly buying his companys stock. His
response was:
Yes; that is my theory. Let the buyer beware; that covers the whole business. You
cannot wet-nurse people from the time they are born until the day they die. They
have got to wade in and get stuck and that is the way men are educated and cultivated.81
Between the turn of the century and 1933, some companies began to disclose more information, largely because they faced being compelled to do
so if they did not do so voluntarily. Indeed, in 1905, the Equitable Life
Assurance Society announced that it was adopting a new policy of having
its nancial statements audited, giving as reasons a desire to restore
investors condence and to avoid restrictive regulation.82
While voluntary disclosure improved somewhat and the New York
Stock Exchange (NYSE) started to impose disclosure requirements on its
listing companies before the federal securities laws were passed,83 these
changes were motivated by a series of state and federal investigations and
proposals for legislation that the companies and the NYSE were attempting to forestall. Absent credible threats of government regulation, it is not
clear at all that companies disclosure practices would have improved or
that the NYSE would have increased its disclosure requirements for listed
companies.
Unfortunately, the NYSE indierently enforced the disclosure rules that
it did adopt.84 For example, one of the most infamous scandals of the time
involving Ivar (the Match King) Kreuger that began before and ended
after the great crash of 1929was made possible by Kreugers total
secrecy.85 When auditors questioned him, he simply refused to answer any
136
of the questions or provide any of the information that would have disclosed his Ponzi scheme. Kreuger, Samuel Insull, and other great fraudsters
of the time had no fear that independent auditors would be called in.86
The NYSE was not keen to delist some of its most popular companies.
Notwithstanding the voluntary eorts of companies and the
requirements of the NYSE, Laurence Sloans exhaustive study of the
nancial disclosures of major American corporations right before the 1929
crash concluded that industrial nancial reports were woefully inadequate, lacking uniformity and meaningful explanation.87 Indeed, he concluded that [i]n several important respects, no criticism of the abuses that
exist can be too harsh.88 The typical oering circular before passage of the
1933 Act contained get rich quick promises, but very little useful information about the securities, the planned use of proceeds, or even the background of the issuer itself.89
After the 1929 stock market crash, Congress held hearings which indicated that various state eorts at securities regulation, dating back to
Kansass 1911 adoption of the rst blue sky law, had been truly inadequate. In response, Congress passed six major securities laws, two of which
the Securities Act of 1933 and the Securities Exchange Act of 1934
contained particularly important disclosure requirements that laid the
predicate for much of todays regulatory philosophy. As noted, these two
Acts together constitute the rst truly comprehensive securities regulation
scheme ever enacted.
As noted earlier, the 1933 Securities Act regulated the initial oering
process. When corporations issued securities to the public, they were
required by the Act to either t the transaction within one of several available exemptions or to le a registration statement with the SEC. The contents of the registration statement would be distributed to potential
investors in preliminary and nal prospectuses that would contain more
useful information than those used before. The required contents of the
new prospectuses were patterned on the United Kingdoms Companies
Acts of 1928 and 1929 and focused on the nature of the company, its
nancial status, the background of its principals, the characteristics of the
instruments to be issued, and other relevant information.
Next, Congress enacted the 1934 Securities Exchange Act which, among
many other provisions, regulated disclosure in the secondary securities
markets. The 1934 Act came to require periodic disclosure in the form of
annual, quarterly, and interim reports. It also required disclosure at the
time of corporate directors elections and votes regarding signicant
organic changes to the corporate form. In 1968, it was amended to require
further disclosure in the event of a tender oer. In 2002, Congress passed
the Sarbanes-Oxley Act that had several provisions aimed at ensuring the
137
138
antifraud rules led the Neuer Markt to collapse in a wave of scandals and
go out of business.
Although European companies and countries (particularly Germany)
have complained about the Sarbanes-Oxley Acts international applications, in their own EU studies and decisions they have been moving in the
same direction. For example, the recently-promulgated Organization for
Economic Co-operation and Developments (OECDs) Principles of
Corporate Governance recommend a US-style system of mandatory disclosure.90 In Asia, Japan and China have both increased mandatory disclosure in recent years as they have sought to move toward the transparency
of Western markets. Korea as well has adopted disclosure provisions patterned after both the 1933 Act and the 1934 Act.
While it is certainly possible to require ineciently comprehensive corporate disclosures, the trend in all successful modern capital economies has
been toward more and prompter required disclosure by corporations.
Experience has taught all sensible governments that voluntary disclosure
will generally be inadequate. Less successful capital markets have emulated
more successful capital markets by moving in the direction of requiring
substantial corporate disclosure.
While some academics have been engaged in an ideological debate
regarding whether mandatory disclosure is really needed, governments
worldwide have uniformly concluded that comprehensive and comparable
corporate disclosure facilitates international capital ows. For example, an
important part of disclosure is accounting. It is costly for companies that
sell their securities in several nations to have to disclose their nancial situation in several dierent accounting formats. It is also inecient for
investors to have to compare statements that are presented in dierent
formats. Therefore, by 2005, all European-listed companies must use the
international accounting standards (IAS) and the SEC and EU are working
toward accounting convergence between these international standards and
American GAAP.
Misrepresentations
Both common law nations and civil law nations punished fraud in commercial transactions well before the creation of modern securities laws.
Nonetheless, a major feature of modern securities regulation has been an
increased emphasis on preventing and punishing fraud and misrepresentation in securities transactions. The Dutch may well have lost their preeminent position as nanciers of capital markets that they enjoyed during the
1600s and much of the 1700s by failing to create regulatory bodies or otherwise to protect investors from securities fraud and unfair dealing.91 Other
139
nations have learned from this apparent historical lesson. Again, the
United Kingdom and the United States, which have been the leaders in
developing deep and uid capital markets, were also the rst to put in the
legal infrastructure needed to accomplish that task.
After the 1825 repeal of the Bubble Act, joint-stock companies
ourished in England. Unfortunately, unscrupulous promoters used jointstock companies to launch fraudulent business enterprises.92 English
common law provided two basic remedies for a purchaser of securities who
relied upon an inaccurate representation93 a suit for deceit or one for
rescission. In Derry v. Peek,94 the House of Lords held that directors could
be liable for false statements in a prospectus only if the purchaser could
show their bad intent. Parliament thereafter enacted the Directors
Liability Act of 1890 which created liability for such misstatements even
absent scienter. However, investors were protected only by their own
civil actions, as the Board of Trade and its subsidiary, the Registrar of
Companies, were essentially sunshine agencies that could require the ling
of periodic nancial reports but had little enforcement power to cope with
fraud.95
Americas common law remedies were similar to Englands. In part
because of the perceived inadequacy of the common law fraud remedy as
applied to securities transactions, in 1911 American states began to enact
civil and criminal provisions in their blue sky laws in order to target fraud
involving securities specically. However, these state provisions were generally ineectively enforced for several reasons, including that the statutes
were typically riddled with exceptions, the state regulators lacked adequate
budgets and enforcement sophistication, and defendants knew that they
could usually evade the proscriptions by operating across state lines.
The weakness of the common law and state remedies made enactment of
comprehensive federal remedies in the 1930s particularly noteworthy.
When Congress passed the 1933 Act, it borrowed from Parliaments
Directors Liability Act of 1890 in enacting section 11, which made directors, underwriters, auditors, and others potentially liable on a negligence
basis for damages caused by false statements in a prospectus. These defendants have the burden of proving that they acted with due care. The issuing
company is liable for misstatements on a strict liability basis, similar to
Englands common law action for rescission. Section 11 was viewed as
potentially so onerous by securities professionals that they predicted in
1933 that it would cause grass to grow on Wall Street. This proved an exaggeration, especially because the rst major damages action under the provision did not reach the courts for 30 years. However, after the mid-1960s,
section 11 reliably provided injured investors with a damages remedy for
false statements, at least in initial public oerings.
140
141
142
143
b.
144
145
made it much harder for oerors to eectuate these takeovers. For example,
some of these laws required oerors to warn targets substantially in advance
of launching a takeover and to hold the oers open much longer than the
federal minimum of 20 business days. Both provisions had the eect of
making the takeover more expensive for the oeror and giving the oeree
substantial extra time to implement legal defenses. These state laws were
declared unconstitutional by the US Supreme Court under the American
Constitutions Supremacy Clause because in a clash between federal law and
state laws, federal law is to prevail.96 However, the states passed more rounds
of legislation, this time framing their laws as corporate laws rather than
securities laws and eliminating provisions that nakedly contradicted
Williams Act provisions. Corporate law has always been traditionally within
the states bailiwick in the American system whereas since 1933 federal law
has dominated the securities eld (although, as noted above, any boundary
between the two is necessarily articial). These second generation state
takeover laws have passed Constitutional muster.97
These new state rules, coupled with preexisting state corporate law rules
regarding mergers and other organic corporate changes, clearly aected the
takeover landscape. Consider Delaware, as one example of a variety of
dierent state approaches. Delaware law discourages takeovers by imposing several requirements upon an oeror that make it dicult to complete
a takeover. For example, any oeror seeking more than a certain percentage of shares cannot complete a freeze-out merger for at least three years.
This is cumbersome and discouraging to the oeror. However, the law contains exceptions and allows immediate eectuation of a freeze-out merger
if, for example, a high percentage of shares are purchased and all shareholders, including those whose shares are purchased in the freeze-out
merger, receive the same premium over market price. This provision
advances fair treatment.
Although judicial interpretation of the duciary duty owed by target
company directors to shareholders currently forbids Delaware directors in a
takeover from considering any goal other than attaining the highest price for
shareholders once they have decided a change of control of some type should
occur, the statutes of many states allow (and of at least one state requires)
target directors to consider the interests of other constituencies as well when
plotting strategy. Thus, target directors could consider the interests of their
employees, their customers, and the communities in which they have operations in deciding whether a tender oer should be accommodated or resisted.
Takeovers were much less frequent in Europe than in the United States,
so takeover law there is less developed. However, the Vodafone hostile
tender oer for control of Mannesmann in 2001 is symbolic of a new era.
Hostile takeovers have come to the Continent and, as in America, few
146
147
to whether the capital markets are bettered or undermined by liberal treatment of hostile takeovers. Most interested observers support giving tender
oerors a free rein, for hostile bids provide market discipline to managers
of corporations. If they do not do a good job, their companys market price
will drop, leaving the rm particularly vulnerable to a tender oer. Others
believe that waves of takeovers are typically followed by waves of divestitures, because most acquisitions do not work out well. Shareholders of the
target corporation prosper; shareholders of the acquiring rm suer.
Investment bankers do well both in the takeover transaction and in the
divestiture. There is some evidence that hubris by ocers of the acquiring
corporation is an important factor in hostile takeovers. In any event, the
evidence is inconclusive and the debate is complex and ongoing. The
general trend, as with mandatory disclosure, fraud prevention, and insider
trading, has been toward the American model that is at least marginally
facilitative of hostile takeovers.
CONCLUSION
If a benevolent, enlightened ruler of a developing nation were granted just
one wish by a magic djinn, he or she should not choose natural resources,
or a brace of modern manufacturing plants, or a plethora of Western management consultants. Rather, the enlightened wish would be for the rule of
law. History demonstrates that nothing is more important to economic
development than a stable legal system that enforces contracts, preserves
property rights, and punishes fraud.
Once economic actors are protected by the rule of law, they can begin to
realize their dreams. If they dream big, they will need corporations. These
are a critical institution for coordinating large economic enterprises.
Corporate law authorizes and, if properly drafted, enables corporate formation and growth. Governments constantly tweak their corporate law to
strike a proper balance between limited liability for investors and fair protection for creditors, between discretion for managers and control by shareholders, between adequate compensation and incentives for managers and
protection from looting for shareholders. History has not written the nal
chapter on the proper mix of incentives and protections in corporate law,
but increasingly, there is a consensus that with substantial cultural variation, best practices in corporate governance will include strong protection for minority shareholders, active monitoring of the day-to-day
managers by a relatively independent board of directors, and some additional mix of devices that will allow minority shareholders an eective
voice in corporate aairs or an ecient and fair means of exit.
148
Well before Enron or the Sarbanes-Oxley Act, the Vienot Report (1999)98
in France concluded that French law provided insucient protection for
average investors and that French capital markets could be strengthened by
implementing a series of recommendations that resemble Sarbanes-Oxleys
prescriptionsmore independent directors, a board committee to deal
with critical subjects such as audit and compensation, increased information and responsibility for directors, and more disclosure for shareholders to increase their involvement in company decisions.99 The previous
Marini Report also recommended French adoption of Anglo-Saxon style
reforms.100 Various EU studies have recommended European harmonization of prospectus liability, insider trading rules, tender oer rules, and
other areas, and that harmonization has almost always converged upon
current American legal practice. France can outlaw insider trading and
create a French SEC, but when the United States has scores of enforcement
actions annually and France has only the occasional one, markets are going
to be more inviting to investors in the United States. History shows that the
content of the law is not sucient to stimulate markets, but it certainly is
necessary.
NOTES
1. O. Lee Reed, Law, the Rule of Law, and Property: Foundations for the Private Market and
Business Study, 38 AM. BUS. L. J. 441, 449 (2001).
2. Douglass North, INSTITUTIONS, INSTITUTIONAL CHANGE AND ECONOMIC PERFORMANCE 46 (1990).
3. Reed, supra note 1, at 441 (quoting Davis).
4. Avner Greif, Contract Enforceability and Economic Institutions in Early Trade: The
Maghribi Traders Coalition, 83 AM. ECON. REV. 525 (1993).
5. E. Allan Farnsworth, CONTRACTS 1112 (1982).
6. Id. at 2021.
7. Philip M. Nichols, A Legal Theory of Emerging Economies, 39 VA. J. INTL. L. 229,
26465 (1999).
8. James Surowiecki, THE WISDOM OF CROWDS: WHY THE MANY ARE
SMARTER THAN THE FEW AND HOW COLLECTIVE WISDOM SHAPES
BUSINESS, ECONOMIES, SOCIETIES, AND NATIONS 121 (2004).
9. Id. at 124.
10. Hernando de Soto, THE MYSTERY OF CAPITAL: WHY CAPITALISM TRIUMPHS IN THE WEST AND FAILS EVERYWHERE ELSE 510 (2000).
11. Simon H. Johnson, John McMillan, and Christopher Woodru, Property Rights and
Finance, Stanford Law and Economics Olin Working Paper No. 231 (March 2002).
12. De Soto, supra note 10, at 71.
13. Douglass North, STRUCTURE AND CHANGE IN ECONOMIC HISTORY 14757
(1981).
14. Charles Cadwell, Forword to Mancur Olson, POWER AND PROSPERITY viii (2000).
15. Ronald H. Coase, The Institutional Structure of Production, in NOBEL LECTURES IN
ECONOMIC SCIENCE 11, 17 (Torsten Persson ed. 1997).
16. Reed, supra note 1, at 459.
149
17. Charles I. Jones, Was an Industrial Revolution Inevitable? Economic Growth Over the Very
Long Run, 1 ADVANCES IN MACROECONOMICS 1028 (No. 2, 2001).
18. Fareed Zakaria, Lousy Advice Has Its Price, NEWSWEEK, September 27, 1999, at 40.
19. Jean Domat, I THE CIVIL CODE IN ITS NATURAL ORDERS (1850 William
Strahan (trans.), republished Fred B. Rothman & Co., Colorado Springs, CO, 1980).
20. Stuart Banner, ANGLO-AMERICAN SECURITIES REGULATION: CULTURAL
AND POLITICAL ROOTS, 1690860, 117 (1998).
21. Id. at 236, citing Bacon v. Sanford, 1 Root 164, 165 (Conn. 1790).
22. (1789) 100 Eng. Rep. 450.
23. PROSSER AND KEETON ON TORTS 728 (5th ed. 1984).
24. Banner, Supra note 20, at 117.
25. Joseph Angell & Samuel Ames, TREATISE ON THE LAW OF PRIVATE CORPORATIONS AGGREGATE (1832, reprint, N.Y. Arno Press, 1972), cited in Douglas
Arner, Development of the American Law of Corporations to 1932, 55 SMU L. REV.
32 (2002).
26. Timur Kuran, WHY THE ISLAMIC MIDDLE EAST DID NOT GENERATE AN
INDIGENOUS CORPORATE LAW 30 (2004).
27. John Micklethwait & Adrian Wooldridge, THE COMPANY: A SHORT HISTORY OF
A REVOLUTIONARY IDEA 56 (2003).
28. Id. at xxi.
29. Id. at xx (quoting Butler).
30. John Kay, CULTURE AND PROSPERITY: THE TRUTH ABOUT MARKETS:
WHY SOME NATIONS ARE RICH BUT MOST REMAIN POOR 322 (2004).
31. Quoted in Anthony Sampson, COMPANY MAN: THE RISE AND FALL OF CORPORATE LIFE 19 (1995).
32. Margaret M. Blari & Lynn A. Stout, A Team Production Theory of Corporate Law, 85
VA. L. REV. 247 (1999).
33. Margaret M. Blair, Locking in Capital: What Corporations Law Achieved for Business
Organizers in the 19th Century, 51 UCLA L. REV. 387, 395 (2003).
34. Ranald C. Michie, THE LONDON STOCK EXCHANGE: A HISTORY 17 (1999).
35. Douglas Arner, Development of the American Law of Corporations to 1832, 55 S.M.U.
L. REV. 23, 44 (2002).
36. 10 U.S. (6 Cranch) 87 (1810).
37. 17 U.S. (4 Wheat ) 518 (1819).
38. Arner, supra note 35, at 49, citing R. Kent Newmyer, Justice Joseph Storys Doctrine of
Public and Private Corporations and the Rise of the American Business Corporation, 25
DEPAUL L. REV. 825, 828 (1976).
39. Henry Hansmann & Reinier Kraakman, THE ANATOMY OF CORPORATE LAW
10 (2004).
40. William J. Bernstein, THE BIRTH OF PLENTY: HOW THE PROSPERITY OF THE
MODERN WORLD WAS CREATED 150 (2004).
41. Blair, supra note 33, at 393.
42. Id. at 441.
43. Micklethwait & Wooldridge, supra note 27, at 82.
44. Adam Smith, 2 AN INQUIRY INTO THE NATURE AND CAUSES OF THE
WEALTH OF NATIONS 733 (Oxford University Press, 1976).
45. Adolph A. Berle, Jr. & Gardiner C. Means, THE MODERN CORPORATION AND
PRIVATE PROPERTY (1932).
46. Alfred F. Conard, The Supervision of Comparative Management: A Comparison of
Developments in European and United States Law, 82 MICH. L. REV. 1459 (1984).
47. James A. Fanto, The Role of Corporate Law in French Corporate Governance, 31
CORNELL INTL L.J. 31, 53 (1998).
48. John C. Coee, Jr., Privatization and Corporate Governance: The Lessons from Securities
Market Failure, 25 IOWA J. CORP. L. 1, 2829 (1999).
49. Bernard Black, et al., Liability Risk for Outside Directors: A Cross-Border Analysis
(2004).
150
151
89. Thomas A. Halleran & John N. Calderwood, Eect of Federal Regulation on Distribution
of and Trading in Securities, 28 GEO. WASH. L. REV. 86, 94 (1959).
90. See Ad Hoc Task Force on Corporate Governance, OECD Principles of Corporate
Governance (April 16, 1999), available at www.oecd.org/daf/governance/principles.htm.
91. Bernstein, supra note 60, at 146.
92. Baskin & Miranti, supra note 67, at 140.
93. Mahoney, supra note 73, at 1088.
94. 4 App. Case 337 (HL 1889) (Halsbury opinion).
95. Baskin & Miranti, supra note 67, at 161.
96. Edgar v. Mite Corp., 457 U.S. 624 (1982).
97. CTS Corp. v. Dynamics Corp. of America, 481 U.S. 69 (1987).
98. Assn Francaise Des Entreprises Privees AFEP, Recommendations of the Committee on
Corporate Governance 39 (1999), available at www.ecgi.org/codes/countrydocuments/
france/vienot2 en.pdf.
99. Fanto, supra note 47, at 8687.
100. Philippe Marini, La modernisation du droit des societes, Rapport au premier ministre,
Collection des rapports ociels, La documentation francaise (1996). See generally
Nicholas H.D. Foster, Company Law Theory in Comparative Perspective: England and
France, 48 AM. J. COMP. L. 573 (2000).
152
153
154
law and other variables appeared to play at best a modest role in nancial
markets, signicant positive results were associated with mandatory disclosure requirements and with the provision for easier private enforcement
of the securities laws. They found that securities law requirements might be
more signicant for markets than the corporate law protection of investors.
Other Studies
Numerous other authors have studied the eect of various aspects of the
law on capital markets, often using La Portas measures for the legal variables to be analyzed. This category of studies has burgeoned in the last ve
years, both as published articles and working papers, and they have
enhanced our understanding of the role of the law, primarily through crosssectional studies of national laws. This section highlights some of these
studies.
Researchers at the World Bank have done extensive analyses of capital
markets and the eects of legal institutions. Ross Levine, after studying the
importance of capital markets to overall economic growth, examined the
eect of the law on nancial markets and economic growth.7 His analysis
considered legal variables involving the eciency of contract enforcement,
treatment of creditors and accounting standards, including the data from
La Porta, et al. and other sources. Levine found that contract enforcement,
legal creditor protections, and nancial disclosure all contributed to greater
private nancial markets.
With his World Bank colleagues, Levine has also sought to measure the
relative eects of legal systems, politics, and national endowments (such as
geography) for national nancial development.8 To capture the law, they
used the La Porta, et al. standard of national legal origin, as well as their
measure for shareholder rights and property rights protection. The authors
found that the legal variables dominated the alternative explanations for
nancial development. In particular, legal origin was the strongest determinant, even after controlling for the other possible explanations of
nancial development, though there was some association for the political
and endowment variables. Levine has also traced the chain of connections
from original legal origin to greater nancial development and economic
growth.9 Another study found that countries with greater corporate shareholder rights provided higher valuations for banks.10 Other research by this
group has conrmed this nding. For example, they have found that rms
in countries with French legal origin face signicantly higher obstacles in
accessing external nance than rms in common law countries.11
A separate World Bank study tackled the question from a dierent
angle. This study took a nancial organizations measure of the corporate
155
156
157
found little association between the law and nancial measures. These
ndings, though, could simply reect a failure to capture quantitatively the
true inuence of the law, which can be a daunting endeavor.
158
for the existence or absence of a particular legal rule and even combine
them for a continuous variable, but there is no assurance that this procedure truly measures the law, especially as it functions in courts. Absent
any clear measures for the law, we will deploy a diversity of scales.
To measure the basic law, most existing studies have used legal origin
as a variable, distinguishing between the English common law system and
the various families of civil law. Although this variable has often produced
signicant results, it is theoretically troublesome. First, the variable largely
tracks colonial heritage and might simply measure some other residual
eect of the colonizing nation, rather than the source of law itself. Second,
the signicance of the variable today lacks some plausibility, because the
dierences in the common and civil law systems have been muted over time.
The systems have converged, as common law nations are increasingly governed by statutory prescriptions, while civil law nations adopt common law
principles such as reliance on precedent.23 Perhaps most troubling for this
association is the historic nding that in 1913, before the convergence of the
systems, the common law nations did not have greater nancial development than civil law nations.24 This surely calls into question whether legal
origin is truly the best measure for the foundational law and its eect on the
economy.
There are some alternative measures for the nations foundational legal
systems, but these too are rather crude. There are several groups who have
sought to code national property rights, such as the Heritage Foundation
and Fraser Institute series.25 International investment advisory groups,
such as the Business Economic Research Intelligence and the International
Country Risk Guide, have also given ratings for legal tools such as property rights, contract enforcement, and the rule of law. While helpful, these
sources provide a narrow range of distinctions and typically do not directly
measure legal rights. For example, a Heritage property rights scale incorporates the overall size of government as a component. While the size of
government may be economically relevant, it does not truly measure protection of property from taking. Available measures for contract enforcement are even weaker. An interesting indirect measure of property rights
and contract enforcement is contract-intensive money (CIM). Research
has found this measure is signicantly associated with higher levels of
nancial development.26 This captures the percentage of national currency
placed in contract-dependent investments, such as banks. Though not a
direct measure of the law, it would seem to measure the societal functioning of the legal system.
When measuring corporate law, researchers have relied on the La Porta,
et al. cross-country scaling of national legal content, with generally good
results. The scale is facially valid, and the construction of any alternative
159
160
traditionally used La Porta, et al. variables but also employ other measures
for the law, including measures of the functioning of the legal system generally and survey measures about the actual operation of the law. The breadth
of variables will both enable us to assess the robustness of associations and
also may allow us to disaggregate the results and identify particular laws of
importance.
Legal origin is taken as a binary variable, English or civil law. This fails to
capture the nuances of dierent civil law systems set out in La Porta, et al., but
does measure the common law eect. Contract-intensive money is a quantitative nancial variable that is theoretically derivative of the legal system. The
other variables are all perceptual measures, though some are from surveys of
international businesspersons and others are scales created by international
experts. They attempt to measure the rule of law (using three dierent sources),
the protection of property rights, judicial independence, and the relative political risk of property expropriation or failure to enforce contracts.
The variables for corporate law are primarily those of La Porta, et al.
They are binary measures of whether a countrys legal corporations code
contains a particular provision. The one share-one vote variable is a protection of a particular interest of minority shareholders, by preventing the
sale of non-voting stock. The oppressed minority standard simply recognizes some mechanism to protect these rights beyond a fraud action. Voting
by proxy reduces the costs of investor control of the corporation, as does
a rule that shareholders are not required to deposit their shares prior to
shareholders meetings. Cumulative voting better enables minorities to
obtain board representation, and preemptive rights protect against the
dilution of ownership. While La Porta, et al. consider mandatory dividend
laws a form of shareholder protection, this is debatable, as it can constrain
reinvestment and enhancement of corporate market capitalization.
Antidirector rights are a cumulation of the individual binary variables
other than the mandatory dividend requirement. The nal corporate law
variable that we employ is a generalized perceptual survey measure from
the World Competitiveness Report that measures the eectiveness with
which the nation denes and protects the rights of shareholders.
For securities law, La Porta, et al. also provide measures. These variables
are not simple binary ones but scaled based on a number of criteria. For
example, the measure for the disclosure requirements of a nations securities law is based on a prospectus requirement, requirements regarding disclosure of ocer compensation, equity ownership structure, insider
ownership, material contracts, and transactions with insiders. Most of the
securities law variables are procedural ones, though. The burden of proof
variable measures the diculties in recovering under the laws. Private
enforcement incorporates the disclosure and burden of proof variables.
161
162
Financial Variables
The nancial dependent variables of interest must also be determined. The
data on such nancial variables is much more available and more precise.
For example, nancial data on the size and trading in nancial markets is
regularly and reliably reported. There remains a question about which of
these nancial variables to use as a test for the eect of the law. Many
dierent variables have been employed, including stock market value to
GDP ratio, volatility ratings, capitalization to sales ratio, and others. Each
of these measures has a legitimate claim of importance. Because there is no
single variable of concern, we employ a number of dierent dependent
nancial variables from various sources.
The relatively new World Bank database adds new valuable information
on the status of the worlds nancial markets.27 We use several variables
from the dierent categories of the database. The ratio variables of bank
and nancial institution credit and liquid liabilities to GDP measure
the overall role of nancial institutions in the economy. They include
both banking and equity markets. The overhead costs and net interest
margin variables provide measures of the eciency by which nancial
intermediaries such as banks can channel funds to investors and are
primarily measures of the eciency of the banking system. The remaining variables of stock market capitalization, value traded, and turnover
are measures specic to the national equity markets and their relative
liquidity.
In addition to variables from the World Bank database, we use two central
variables from La Porta, et al. on overall market capitalization, two purely
perceptual measures of capital markets taken from surveys of businesspersons, and two more quantitative variables drawn from research by Laura
Beny.28 The rst two La Porta variables are similar to those of the World
Bank, as measurements of nancial market capitalization relative to
total sales and cash ow. The third of these variables, the ratio of
Worldscope database rms to domestic rms, is meant to capture the
degree of public shareholding in the market. The cost of capital and
adequacy of stock market capital variables are survey measures. While
they have the shortcomings of any perceptual survey measures, they have
the corresponding advantage of measuring business perceptions and potentially controlling for nation-specic factors such as the need for capital. The
nal variables, from Beny, are cash ow to price ratio, measuring the sum of
earnings and depreciation over the companys market value of common
equity.
163
Financial variables
Market capitalization/sales (La Porta) (mcap/s)
Market capitalization/cash (La Porta) (mcap/c)
WLD domestic rms (La Porta) (wldomes)
Liquid liabilities/GDP (World Bank) (ll/gdp)
Bank and nancial institution credit/GDP (World Bank) (bvic/gdp)
Overhead costs (World Bank) (ohc)
Net interest margin (World Bank) (nim)
Stock market capitalization/GDP (World Bank) (mcap/gdp)
Stock market value traded/GDP (World Bank) (smv/gdp)
Stock market turnover/GDP (World Bank) (smt/gdp)
Cost of capital (WCR) (coc)
Adequacy of stock market provision of capital (WCR) (adeqcap)
Cash ow/price ratio (Beny) (cash/price)
Market volatility (Beny) (mvol)
Intermediate Variables
One further general set of variables is analyzed in this chapter the intermediate variables. The hypothesized eect of the law on markets operates
indirectly. Corporate laws, for example, are intended to overcome agency
problems, and securities laws are, inter alia, intended to enhance the frequency and reliability of corporate disclosures. These eects on the relative
magnitude of agency problems and relative amount of disclosure then theoretically translate into a larger or more eciently functioning capital
market. When studies nd that the law translates into thriving capital
markets, they have not tested the intermediate variables to determine that
the eect is as hypothesized. By examining certain intermediate variables,
we can better check for the possible spuriousness of the relationship and
better understand the precise nature of the eects of the law.
Unfortunately, data on the intermediate variables is only rough, like measures of the legal variables. The best source for quantitative measurement
of the intermediate variables is international surveys of businesspersons,
like that of the WCR discussed above in the context of the legal variables.
These surveys measure answers to questions such as the degree to which
managers eectively maximize shareholder value or prevent improper practices. For some other variables of interest, there are also expert rating scales,
such as accounting standards or eective corporate governance. Once
again, absent any unambiguously optimal intermediate variable measure,
we use a number of dierent ones.
These intermediate variables are meant to capture the processes through
164
which the legal variables inuence nancial outcomes. There are two distinct
types of processes at issue. The rst is a measure of the quality and honesty of
management in the presence of the agency problem. While this is the ultimate
measure of concern, its measurement is inevitably amorphous and of uncertain reliability. The category can only be measured through survey variables.
The second somewhat more reliable variable is a measure of disclosure. For the
disclosure variables, the Centre for International Financial Analysis Research
(CIFAR) provides several relevant measures.29 These include nancial disclosure intensity, corporate governance disclosure intensity, aggregate disclosure,
and the timeliness of nancial reporting. La Porta, et al. supply a national
rating of accounting standards. These variables can help capture the
eectiveness of corporate disclosure among the nations of the study.
Intermediate variables
Board prevention of improper practices (WCR) (bpip)
Board management of shareholder value (WCR) (bmsv)
Corporate ethics (WCR) (ethic)
Accounting standards (La Porta) (accst)
Financial disclosure (CIFAR) (nd)
Governance disclosure (CIFAR) (govd)
Aggregate disclosure (CIFAR) (aggd)
Timeliness of disclosure (CIFAR) (timed)
Governance opacity (PriceWaterhouseCoopers) (govo)
Governance quality (McKinsey) (govq)
The legal, intermediate, and ultimate nancial variables in these lists may
not perfectly capture the eect of the law on corporate nance. They rely
on perceptions and are undoubtedly inuenced by various extralegal
national considerations. However, they have the benet of being direct
measures of the behavior that the law is meant to inuence, and there is
good evidence that companies who score higher in these governance and
disclosure rankings are valued higher in the stock market.30 Corporate law
is intended in large part to resolve agency problems and its benets should
appear in governance quality and the maximization of shareholder value.
Securities law is intended in large part to ensure that corporate disclosures
are comprehensive, timely, and accurate. Hence, one would expect the laws
eect to appear in measures such as the intermediate variables.
Methodological Questions
Even if the independent legal variables could be perfectly measured, there
would still be questions about how to test for their eects. A great number
165
of dierent scales are available for measuring the nancial markets, with no
single scale conclusively preferable. Other questions include the directionality of the association (for example, might nancial development inuence
the nature of the law) and the appropriate external control variables that
should be incorporated in measurement. The very nature of cross-country
comparisons runs the risk of producing spurious associations. Such comparisons also present a signicant risk of false ndings of no signicant
association, simply because of the great stochastic noise associated with
comparing dierent national markets.
A very important question, often unanswered in the research, is the
means by which the legal variables operate. For example, some research has
found that statutory disclosure requirements are associated with greater
investment in equity markets. While it seems logical that they do so by providing greater actual disclosures or reliability of disclosures to investors,
this eect has gone largely untested. The failure to measure such intermediate variables leaves the logical assumption uncertain and raises a concern
that some unmeasured third variable, perhaps unrelated to the law, might
explain the conclusions. Testing for the intermediate variables better
enables us to assess the role of the law in corporate nance.
The choice of control variables is another dicult question for this
research. The outcomes might be explained by some extralegal factor that
happens to be collinear with our legal variables. As noted above, the existing studies have employed various dierent control variables, which provides some assurance about the validity of the identied associations but
leaves open the possibility that some unmeasured factor explains the
results. This is especially a concern for reliance on legal origin as a measure,
because it is highly collinear with the culture of the former colonial power.
The failure to test for intermediate variables complicates this concern. Of
course, the failure to fully capture other variables of inuence could also
obscure a true relationship and mean that the eect of the law on nancial
development is understated by this research.
Once again, we have no easy solution to these methodological problems,
which must inevitably complicate cross-country analyses of the type typically employed. Since the problem cannot be precisely cured, we employ
numerous dierent variables, independent, intermediate, and ultimate. This
does not answer all the methodological concerns but can provide some
degree of greater assurance about the validity of results and can expose alternative explanations for those results. With more variables and more separate
tests, there is obviously some risk of spurious results, by random chance. The
randomness eect can be ruled out, though, if the statistically signicant
associations are relatively frequent, and if they consistently operate in one
direction, we can be condent in the nature of the association. Random
166
eects are just as likely to show a negative eect for the law as a positive
one.
Not only will we use a large number of variables, we will run a large
number of correlations and regression analyses. We do not follow a precise
path, testing particularized hypotheses, but instead cast a wide net to nd
signicant associations. We have a generalized theory; that legal rules
including restrictive legal rules can serve to strengthen nancial markets in
various ways. They can reduce investment risk, particularly risks that
cannot be eectively cured through diversication, and facilitate ecient
trading markets by reducing the transaction costs associated with investing. Our null hypothesis is that the laws do not have this eect, so that measures of statistical signicance can be used to reject that null hypothesis.
Before reporting results, some additional explanation is required. For
simple space reasons, reporting of the results will be brief. The number of
observations in the regressions is generally around 50, and we will note
when this is not the case. We will also explain when the R2 term is
signicantly large or small. When reading the results of these studies, it is
important to keep in mind that the scales are not normalized. The independent variable scales run the gamut from binary to quite precise (out to
three decimal places). Hence, one cannot simply seize on the signicant
variable with the largest correlation coecient as the most substantively
important determinant. The important results are the existence of statistically signicant relationships and the strength of those relationships, as can
be measured by a R2 term. With these background principles and caveats
in mind, we now turn to statistical analysis.
167
We begin the simple regression with a consideration of the basic foundational legal variables. Because the basic law and its enforcement governs
and theoretically facilitates all business transactions, one might expect that
the recognition and enforcement of property rights and contracts would
associate with richer nancial markets. Similarly, one would expect that the
actual operation of the rule of law, with consideration for judicial eciency
and judicial independence, might also yield stronger nancial markets,
because they presumably mean that the law on the books is better translated into practice. And regardless of the substantive content of the law on
the books, the rule of law should provide economic benets by creating
some stability and avoiding costs associated with corruption.
The rst analysis involves the correlation among the basic foundational
legal variables themselves. Dierent studies have used dierent combinations of these variables, but collinearity between the scaling of the variables
may obscure the truly signicant determinants. Intercorrelations among
the variables should be identied as a threshold matter. Bivariate Pearson
correlations were taken for the paired foundational legal variables, and
Table 5.1 reports their statistical signicance. Those positive correlations
signicant at 0.01 are marked with , those signicant at 0.05 were
marked with , and insignicant associations were marked with . In this
analysis, none of the correlations were signicant in a negative direction.
Plainly there is a high intercorrelation among the foundational legal variables, with most signicant at the 0.01 level. The procedural legal variables
(such as judicial independence, judicial eciency, and rule of law) not only
signicantly correlate with one another, they also signicantly correlate with
the more substantive legal variables (such as property rights and enforcement
of contracts). The one foundational legal variable that is not signicantly
associated with the others is English origin, which, ironically, is the variable
Table 5.1
origin
riskprop
riskcon
prop
cim
rol
wbrol
icrgrol
jude
judindep
168
Table 5.2
origin
riskprop
riskcon
prop
cim
rol
wbrol
icrgrol
jude
judindep
bvic/gdp
ohc
nim
mcap/gdp
smv/gdp
smt/gdp
that has been most widely used in the cross-country studies of the eect of
the law. This gives some reason to question whether legal origin best captures
the role of the foundational law but also gives some condence that its
signicance can indeed be isolated from other measures of the law, so that
the true practical importance of legal origin can be assessed.
The next analysis continues the simple regressions of the foundational
basic legal variables but introduces nancial measures as independent variables. Each of the foundational legal variables is regressed as an independent variable against the World Banks measures for nancial markets as
dependent variables. These variables are all traditional quantitative measures of nancial markets. Again, statistically signicant bivariate correlations are reported with or . For each result, a better performance
(that is, lower overhead costs) merits a .
The table demonstrates a consistent and strong statistical association
between most of the basic foundational legal variables and sundry measures
of nancial markets. The associations were highly signicant and consistently positive in direction. The only independent legal variable lacking in
consistent positive signicance was English legal origin. None of the variables explained the relative degree of stock market turnover, though. Both
the substantive legal measures and the purely procedural assessments of the
legal system showed a signicant association with larger and more ecient
nancial markets, as measured by the World Bank variables. This nding is
especially signicant, because the foundational law would also be expected
to aect the overall GDP, which is the denominator in many of these ratios.
It appears the law has a positive eect on nancial markets that surpasses
its general economic value to GDP. The next analysis considers the eect of
the same basic foundational variables on other non-World Bank nancial
variables from a variety of sources, reported in Table 5.3. These sources
Table 5.3
origin
riskprop
riskcon
prop
cim
rol
wbrol
icrgrol
jude
judindep
169
mcap/c
wldomes
coc
adeqcap
cash/price
mvol
include both the La Porta, et al. measures and international business survey
responses on the cost of capital and adequacy of national capital markets.
The eect of the basic foundational legal variables on these measures is
not as strong as was the case with the World Bank variables, but the results
are typically positive and relatively consistent in their pattern. The vast
majority of the variables had a strong positive association with perceptions
of lower cost of capital and adequate supply of capital, with lessened
market volatility and with the increased proportion of Worldscope rms to
domestic rms. None of the variables were signicantly associated with the
measures of market capitalization to sales or cash ow or cash ow to price.
The latter absence of an association is rendered much less troubling,
though, by the consistent signicant positive associations of these variables
with the quantitative World Bank measures of markets in Table 5.2. While
the reason for the lack of association in this table is not perfectly clear, it
might be that the foundational variables are aecting both the numerator
and the denominator in the same positive direction and similar amount, so
that they do not show up as a signicant determinant of the ratio.
Because these are simple regressions, and because the independent legal
variables are highly intercorrelated, one should be cautious about drawing
any signicant conclusions at this point. A signicant association with one
legal variable might be attributable to another collinear legal variable or to
some yet unmeasured third factor. In addition, the absence of an association of the basic foundational law with some measures of nancial markets
leaves some doubt about the nature of the positive eect from this law.
On balance, though, the evidence on the nancial value of the basic foundational law is strong. None show any signicant negative association, and
all but legal origin and contract-intensive money have a pattern of highly
signicant positive associations for a majority of the nancial variables of
170
interest. For these variables, we reach some preliminary tentative conclusions. First, we nd that legal origin is not a fruitful test for legal systems
eect on nancial markets, at least given the available alternative measures.
Second, we nd that both the substantive and procedural basic foundational legal rules strengthen national nancial markets, though the high
association between procedural protection and substantive protection
leaves the independent importance of each in some doubt.
Table 5.4
171
bvic/gdp
ohc
nim
mcap/gdp
smv/gdp
smt/gdp
osov
oppm
pbm
snbbm
cumv
preem
mand
adr
shr
Table 5.5
osov
oppm
pbm
snbbm
cumv
preem
mand
adr
shr
mcap/s
mcap/c
wldomes
coc
adeqcap
cash/price
mvol
172
disc
bofp
priv
pub
enfo
crim
nr
ll/gdp
bvic/gdp
ohc
nim
mcap/gdp
smv/gdp
smt/gdp
173
disc
bofp
priv
pub
enfo
crim
nr
mcap/s
mcap/c
wldomes
coc
adeqcap
cash/price
mvol
174
175
theory about the common dimension of these variables, our factor analysis is essentially exploratory.
The descriptive intercorrelation matrix among the basic foundational
legal variables has already been presented in Table 5.1. The next step is to
identify the communality which measures the proportion of the variance
in the particular legal factor that can be explained by the common factors.
All initial communalities are one, and Table 5.8 reports the extraction communalities of the factor analysis for the basic foundational legal variables.
From this table, we can see that the common dimension appears to be
closely related to our measures of rule of law. This might be expected, as
rule of law is not an input into the legal system but instead a measure of
its general eectiveness. Of the other variables, only contract-intensive
money is relatively unrelated to the common dimension. While use of one
of the rule of law variables might successfully capture the commonality of
all the basic foundational legal variables, the factor analysis procedure
enables the creation of a separate factor variable or variables that better
capture the common dimension.
There are a variety of ways in which to develop this variable, and we
employ principal component analysis, though the results are extremely
similar under principal factor analysis. For results, the analysis gives
eigenvalues, which measure the dispersion of data points around a given
access and try to determine the pattern of least dispersion. The factor
analysis yields one component with an eigenvalue of 6.683, explaining over
66 percent of the common variance, as opposed to other components. The
second-best component has an eigenvalue of only 1.173, which is not materially dierent from the third component at 0.859. Examination of the
associated scree plot shows that the elbow of the curve occurs at the
second component, so we use only the initial clearly superior factor in our
Table 5.8
origin
riskprop
riskcon
prop
cim
rol
wbrol
icrgrol
jude
judindep
extraction
1.000
1.000
1.000
1.000
1.000
1.000
1.000
1.000
1.000
1.000
0.831
0.909
0.875
0.748
0.321
0.923
0.867
0.923
0.692
0.766
176
analyses. This yields a factor variable that tries to capture the common
dimension of the basic legal foundational variables. The factor variable
captures both the substantive and procedural aspects of the foundational
law and serves as a good measure for the overall eect of this law.
For a corporate law variable, the statistically signicant results were
somewhat spotty and concentrated around the variables of protection
against oppression of minority shareholders, the cumulative La Porta, et
al. index of antidirector rights, and the survey variable of dened and protected shareholder rights. The antidirector rights measure includes the
oppressed minority scale, so our initial reduction of independent variables
will be the La Porta, et al. scale of antidirector rights (adr) as a proxy for
the strength of corporate law.
For securities law, the basic regressions showed more consistent positive
statistical signicance, but most of the associations came from disclosure
requirements, the burden of proof in enforcement actions, private enforcement, and the survey variable of stringency of nancial regulation, though
there were some important associations with public enforcement. The
measure for private enforcement combines the scores for disclosure and
burden of proof, so use of those variables becomes unnecessary. The initially reduced independent variables used for securities law are private
enforcement (priv) as a proxy for the strength of securities law. Signicantly
neither adr nor priv is closely correlated with the factor score measure for
basic foundational law. The data reduction gives us one variable as a proxy
for each of the three main families of law.
We considered using the survey variables of shr and nr as measures of the
strength of corporate and securities law in practice. Clearly, the measures for
adr and priv capture only a portion of the eect of corporate and securities
law, by their own formulae. The survey measures might better capture the
entirety of a nations corporate and securities law. However, both shr and nr
are signicantly correlated, at the 0.01 level, with our factor variable for basic
law. Thus, it appears possible that the executives responding to the survey
asking about the protection of shareholder rights and stringency of nancial
regulation were implicitly factoring in the eect of the basic law in their estimates. Consequently, these variables hold little promise for our next
endeavor identifying the discrete eects of the dierent categories of law.
177
mcap/gdp
factor
adr
priv
R2
n
0.453
(0.002)
0.066
(0.698)
0.380
(0.034)
0.409
38
smv/gdp
0.394
(0.009)
0.028
(0.875)
0.357
(0.056)
0.348
38
mcap/s
coc
adeqcap
0.352
0.842
0.663
(0.018) (0.000) (0.000)
0.409 0.107 0.094
(0.026) (0.349) (0.521)
0.234
0.163
0.325
(0.185) (0.161) (0.032)
0.419
0.754
0.577
33
34
35
cash/price
mvol
0.237 0.592
(0.193) (0.000)
0.168
0.086
(0.482) (0.603)
0.560
0.236
(0.021) (0.159)
0.434
0.431
24
37
178
179
0.450
(0.053)
0.053
(0.762)
0.341
(0.069)
0.133
(0.436)
0.096
(0.693)
0.420
38
0.423
(0.084)
0.021
(0.911)
0.334
(0.091)
0.086
(0.634)
0.023
(0.928)
0.353
38
mcap/s
coc
adeqcap
0.202
0.700
0.528
(0.351) (0.000) (0.006)
0.363 0.087 0.080
(0.050) (0.446) (0.593)
0.323
0.136
0.301
(0.089) (0.252) (0.057)
0.216 0.002
0.016
(0.233) (0.985) (0.914)
0.311
0.199
0.194
(0.208) (0.173) (0.335)
0.460
0.773
0.592
33
34
35
cash/price mvol
0.773 0.681
(0.449) (0.501)
0.179
0.032
(0.475) (0.827)
0.564
0.113
(0.031) (0.459)
0.084 0.201
(0.671) (0.168)
0.778 0.720
(0.440) (0.002)
0.452
0.586
24
37
180
proved signicant in only one of the 14 possible instances. This illustrates the
great statistical noise associated with any cross-country comparisons and the
diculty in nding signicant associations at the more rigorous levels of statistical signicance. It is noteworthy that securities law (priv) was a relatively
more important determinant of nancial outcomes than was secondary education, in ve of the seven equations. Securities law was signicant at the
relaxed 0.10 level for ve of the nancial dependent variables (more than
even for the basic foundational law). This nding of the relative importance
of securities law is consistent with the results of a study of transition
economies, which found that of dierent indexes for shareholder protection,
the securities regulation scale was the only one to show signicance.33
The association for securities law, and only securities law, on the
cash/price variable is important. The prior studies showing that the basic
foundational law increased the valuation of rms and equity markets may
be due to the eect of legal systems on cash ow. For example, the greater
valuation could be due to reduced risk of expropriation or greater opportunities for sales. This eect is independent of that of the risk premium
demanded by investors, to account for agency problems. Our results for this
variable suggest that the latter concern is directly addressed by securities
law, rather than basic or corporate law.
At this point in our analyses, it appears clear that the basic foundational
law and securities law have an important, if not entirely consistent, eect in
strengthening equity markets. The association for corporate law, at least the
antidirector rights measure, is much less clear. The lack of positive eect
for corporate law is somewhat surprising, given the theory and some of the
past empirical ndings on antidirector rights measures of corporate law.
The prior empirical research has not combined corporate law and securities law, though. It may be that extensive securities law envelops the eects
of corporate law, that the positive eect of corporate law disappears when
broader antifraud protections of securities law are adopted. To consider
this possibility, the next analysis considers only those nations whose securities laws are below the median for the private enforcement variable of
signicance, to test for the eect of corporate law when securities laws are
relatively weak. Table 5.11 reports the results of the multiple regression
with control variables and absent the eect of securities laws.
The antidirector rights measure does relatively worse as a determinant of
stock market size and eciency in nations with weaker private enforcement
of securities laws. Only the continued anomalous results for mcap/s are
signicantly positive, as they were for the full sample of nations.
Table 5.11 contains one other suggestive, potentially very signicant
nding. The correlations for our factor variable of basic foundational law
lose much of their signicance in nations with weak securities laws. This at
181
0.005
(0.989)
0.060
(0.806)
0.155
(0.664)
0.507
(0.212)
0.400
18
0.029
(0.936)
0.164
(0.497)
0.689
(0.065)
0.028
(0.943)
0.416
18
mcap/s
0.309
(0.457)
0.891
(0.028)
0.430
(0.354)
0.369
(0.507)
0.541
12
coc
adeqcap cash/price
0.560
0.227
(0.001) (0.500)
0.057 0.136
(0.519) (0.557)
0.012 0.356
(0.925) (0.302)
0.478
0.309
(0.004) (0.379)
0.945
0.620
14
14
0.681
(0.140)
1.029
(0.050)
0.608
(0.243)
0.407
(0.395)
0.659
9
mvol
0.350
(0.336)
0.024
(0.910)
0.260
(0.404)
1.192
(0.005)
0.610
16
least hints at the prospect that it is the substance of securities laws that is
most important for securities markets, rather than the substance of basic
property and contract law. However, with substantive securities laws in
place, it appears that the procedural attributes of the basic law (for example,
judicial independence and eciency), show a greater eect. Those legal procedural variables would be of relatively little value to markets, absent some
eective substantive law to implement. However, the signicance of the
foundational variables assumes importance in the presence of securities regulation, which demonstrates their contribution under those circumstances.
With the limitation to nations with below average securities law, the sample
size in this regression grows small, so one should be cautious about drawing
any conclusions from the results. The ndings certainly do not support the
hypothesis that corporate law is more important in the absence of strong
securities law. Indeed, our results show that it is securities law that has particular value, comparable to that of basic foundational law.
The next analysis focuses on public enforcement of the securities laws. As
noted above, the strong associations for securities law are associated
with private, not public, enforcement of these laws. Theoretically, public
enforcement should show some positive eect, though, if the securities laws
themselves contribute to ecient capital markets. To consider this eect in
a multiple regression with control variables, we repeat in Table 5.12 the
analyses reported in Table 5.10 above, but use public enforcement (pub)
rather than private enforcement for our securities law variable.
Public enforcement of securities laws is not a signicant determinant of
any of our nancial dependent variables. However, it is noteworthy that the
direction of the association is benecial in every one of the measures of the
public enforcement variable, which hints at some positive eect.
182
factor
adr
pub
ethn
secon
R2
n
mcap/gdp
smv/gdp
0.485
(0.047)
0.115
(0.493)
0.062
(0.712)
0.211
(0.228)
0.196
(0.469)
0.264
38
0.454
(0.072)
0.101
(0.562)
0.146
(0.406)
0.155
(0.392)
0.138
(0.605)
0.309
38
mcap/s
coc
adeqcap
0.269
0.518
0.697
(0.214) (0.007) (0.000)
0.429 0.028 0.075
(0.015) (0.844) (0.480)
0.255
0.237
0.133
(0.153) (0.114) (0.230)
0.135
0.070
0.017
(0.441) (0.635) (0.870)
0.114
0.356
0.278
(0.640) (0.089) (0.061)
0.443
0.505
0.774
33
35
34
cash/price
mvol
0.668
(0.512)
0.514
(0.059)
0.074
(0.768)
0.017
(0.939)
0.167
(0.511)
0.298
24
0.638
(0.534)
0.199
(0.844)
0.119
(0.390)
0.216
(0.129)
0.794
(0.001)
0.588
37
Moreover, it is important to recognize that the public enforcement variable does not truly capture the value of the regulatory actions of the
Securities and Exchange Commission. A central part of the SECs role is
the establishment of regulations for disclosure and otherwise, which are
enforceable through private actions. These regulations considerably facilitate private enforcement and their value would be expressed through the
private enforcement variable as well. The public enforcement variable captures just that, enforcement, and not the rule creation function of the SEC.
It does seem fair to conclude that in the securities law enforcement context,
it is the private right of action and not government prosecution which has
the greatest nancial value. This is unsurprising, because the remedy for
private violations can be many billions of dollars of damages to the harmed
investors, while public enforcement actions typically result in lesser sanctions, and because private enforcers may be more ecient in their choices
of the actions to be pursued.
INTERMEDIATE VARIABLES
The studies reported above, as well as a considerable body of other research,
indicate that legal variables are important to the size and eciency of equity
markets and the cost of capital in a nation. It is important to investigate
empirically how this eect takes place. The primary theoretical justication
for corporate law is its attempted correction of managerial agency problems.
The primary theoretical justication for securities law is its regime of
183
184
factor
adr
priv
ethn
secon
R2
n
bpip
bmsv
ethic
govq
govo
0.854
(0.000)
0.174
(0.271)
0.143
(0.379)
0.127
(0.419)
0.128
(0.542)
0.549
35
0.736
(0.001)
0.140
(0.386)
0.003
(0.987)
0.330
(0.047)
0.035
(0.871)
0.524
35
0.917
(0.000)
0.121
(0.384)
0.069
(0.625)
0.240
(0.089)
0.077
(0.676)
0.650
35
0.534
(0.022)
0.002
(0.992)
0.075
(0.728)
0.264
(0.168)
0.401
(0.112)
0.468
24
0.961
(0.019)
0.020
(0.947)
0.725
(0.067)
0.400
(0.219)
0.162
(0.219)
0.142
19
185
factor
adr
disc
ethn
secon
R2
n
nd
govd
aggd
timed
accst
0.413
(0.061)
0.093
(0.591)
0.339
(0.064)
0.028
(0.869)
0.028
(0.903)
0.408
35
0.586
(0.013)
0.301
(0.102)
0.050
(0.786)
0.125
(0.489)
0.267
(0.271)
0.362
35
0.501
(0.011)
0.187
(0.219)
0.324
(0.044)
0.032
(0.835)
0.074
(0.714)
0.540
34
0.500
(0.037)
0.252
(0.171)
0.080
(0.666)
0.196
(0.294)
0.005
(0.986)
0.373
34
0.504
(0.007)
0.033
(0.828)
0.461
(0.005)
0.122
(0.407)
0.046
(0.809)
0.582
34
The results are roughly as might be expected. The factor measure for
basic foundational law is highly associated with the disclosure variables,
and the securities law disclosure requirement shows a signicant association for at least the nancial disclosure measures. Corporate law is not
signicant, though it approaches signicance for disclosures about corporate governance measures, which might be anticipated.
The analyses of the intermediate corporate governance and disclosure
variables generally conrm our broader ndings on the ultimate measure
of eects on nancial markets overall. The basic foundational law is consistently correlated with better quality corporate governance and better
quality corporate disclosures. Securities law shows some association with
disclosure quality, and these are the two variables that also demonstrated
the strongest association with larger and more ecient nancial markets.
Corporate law shows very little eect on the intermediate variables of interest and likewise shows very little eect on the broader ultimate nancial
market variables.
CONCLUSION
The empirical evidence conrms that the law matters, in a benecial way,
for nancial markets. We examined many dependent variables of nancial
signicance, both ultimate and intermediate, and the law frequently was
associated with better economic results. Table 5.15 summarizes the results
of the four multiple regressions (Tables 5.9, 5.10, 5.13 and 5.14) that used
186
18 positive, 1 negative
2 positive, 0 negative
12 positive, 0 negative
the three basic independent legal variables (factor, adr, priv, or disc).
Twenty four separate dependent variables were tested in these regressions.
These results are powerful, given the complicated context of crosscountry regressions. Despite the noisy nature of our dependent variables,
the basic law was signicant in the multiple regressions at the 0.10 level
three-quarters of the time, and securities law was signicant half of the
time. The simple regressions had an even greater frequency of statistical
signicance for the legal variables. Nearly all of the signicant associations
were in a benecial direction, with the prominent exception of the odd
regression on mcap/s, which was negative for the basic law but positive for
corporate law. The positive eect for the law was conrmed by the studies
of intermediate variables, which display the pathways through which the
law provides economic benets. The real world signicance of this frequency of positive statistical signicance is shown by the fact that ethnic
fractionalization and secondary education, two widely used cross-country
variables of obvious societal importance, were statistically signicant
determinants in only four of 24 regressions in which they were used. This
fact is ample evidence of the clarity of laws eect.
The basic foundational law appears to be especially important, as might
be surmised. Without this law, deals become unreliable and trust becomes
riskier. The foundational legal system creates rules protecting property and
enforcing contracts and establishes an adjudicatory structure to implement
those rules. As the rules and structure improve, the risk of investment and
other transactions decline, and the quantity and eciency of such transactions increase as theory projects.
Securities law is also very important to the success of nancial markets. It
is associated signicantly with larger and more ecient markets, at least as
captured by the private enforcement measure, which incorporates the disclosure requirements of securities law. This nding provides support for the theoretical hypotheses of Chapter 2, about the ability of even restrictive laws to
reduce transaction costs and create external economic information benets,
and the hypotheses of Chapter 3, about the systematic biases of behavioralism and the economic eciency values of addressing them through the legal
system. The substantiality of this benet can be roughly calculated.
187
We now estimate a very rudimentary calculation of the value of securities laws. Chapter 2 showed that the cost of going public for NYSE-listed
companies was around US$12.2 billion. This probably overstates the costs
of securities law itself by a considerable degree, but we use it for our
measure of costs for such laws. For benets, we employ the results of Table
5.9 above for the ratio of market capitalization to GDP, for which the best
point estimate for a unit change of priv was 0.341, and for which the 2000
ratio for the United States is 1.4344. If we apply these numbers to the contemporary capitalization of the NYSE, it suggests that the value of the
Exchange would be US$2.28 trillion lower, absent the securities laws, giving
a positive cost/valuation ratio for those laws of nearly 2000:1 for listed companies. This is only a rough estimate, of course, and it calculates the overall
value of the private enforcement of those laws, not marginal changes in the
requirements of the securities laws. This nding and our other results do
counter the claim that restrictive securities laws cause economic harm and
should at least put the onus on those who criticize securities law to justify
their position with something more than a generalized defense of private
ordering and criticism of government intervention in nancial markets.
Corporate law showed relatively little eect on nancial markets or the
intermediate variables. This is not a basis for dismissing the value of corporate law, as only the most dramatic eects will appear signicant in such
cross-national studies. Perhaps the variables used to measure corporate law
do not capture the essence of corporate law as well as for the other variables. The economic value of corporate law is apparent from rms consistent choice to incorporate themselves in Delaware and take advantage of
its legal system. If corporate law were trivial, there is no reason for such
concentration of locus of incorporation. However, the results suggest that
the corporate law variables are not a primary determinant of our nancial
variables.
While the reason that corporate law shows little signicant market eect
cannot be proved, it is possible to speculate. Possibly, corporate law is too
strong and overly empowers minority shareholders in corporate governance, thereby undermining good management by directors. Given the generally permissive nature of corporate law, though, this seems likely.
Corporate law may instead be overly permissive, and insuciently mandatory, thereby failing to reduce transaction costs and inecient behavioral
tendencies of managers and shareholders and leaving serious agency problems unaddressed. The greater positive results for the much more restrictive
securities law measures lends some credence to this theory that corporate
law may be insuciently restrictive. Mark Roe provides an alternative
explanation, that corporate law may fail because of opaque businesses or
social mistrust that impedes professionalization of management, and
188
suggests that the failure of corporate law in some nations is in its inability
to prevent mismanagement, even as it successfully prevents self-dealing.36
As the earlier theoretical chapters have discussed, there is a relatively
common economic presumption in favor of private ordering, without governmental restraint. This theory favors governmental action insofar as it
enforces private deals, thereby empowering such transactions, but disfavors
any governmental constraints on such deals. While there is little doubt that
the empowering functions of law, as reected in basic foundational law,
have considerable economic benet, restrictive securities law rules may also
produce signicant economic benets, measured in the trillions of dollars.
The pure private ordering paradigm is not optimal for securities markets.
NOTES
1.
2.
3.
4.
5.
6.
7.
8.
9.
10.
11.
12.
13.
14.
15.
16.
17.
189
Randall Morck, Bernard Yin Yeung, & Wayne Yu, The Information Content of Stock
Markets: Why Do Emerging Markets have Synchronous Stock Price Movements, 58
J. FIN. ECON. 215 (2000).
Edward Glaeser, Simon Johnson, & Andrei Shleifer, Coase versus The Coasians, 116
Q. J. ECON. 853 (2001).
Luzi Hail & Christian Leuz, International Dierences in the Cost of Equity Capital: Do
Legal Institutions and Securities Regulation Matter, Wharton Financial Institutions
Center Working Paper 0406 (November 2003).
Stijn Claessens & Luc Laeven, Financial Development, Property Rights, and Growth, 58
J. FIN. 2401 (2003).
Stulz & Williamson, Culture, Openness and Finance, NBER Working Paper No. 222
(2001).
See Ugo Mattei, COMPARATIVE LAW AND ECONOMICS (1997).
See Raghuram G. Rajan & Luigi Zingales, The Great Reversals: The Politics of Financial
Development in the 20th Century, NBER Working Paper No. 8178 (July 2002).
See James Gwartney, Robert Lawson, & Walter Block, ECONOMIC FREEDOM OF
THE WORLD 19751995 (1996); Gerald P. ODriscoll, Jr., Kim Holmes, & Melanie
Kirkpatrick, INDEX OF ECONOMIC FREEDOM (2000).
See Christopher Clague, et al., Contract-Intensive Money: Contract Enforcement,
Property Rights, and Economic Performance, 4 J. ECON. GROWTH 185 (1999).
See Thorsten Beck, Asli Demirguc-Kunt, & Ross Levine, A New Database on the
Structure and Development of the Financial Sector, 14 WORLD BANK ECON. REV.
597 (2000).
See Laura Nyantung Beny, Do Shareholders Value Insider Trading Laws? International
Evidence, Harvard John M. Olin Series Discussion Paper No. 345 (December 2001).
Robert Bushman, Joseph Piotrosi, & Abbie Smith, What Determines Corporate
Transparency?, 42 J. ACCTG. RES. 207 (2004).
Art Durnev & E. Han Kim, To Steal or Not to Steal: Firm Attributes, Legal Environment,
and Valuation (March 2004).
Data for this variable come from Albert Alesina, et al., FRACTIONALIZATION
(2003).
Data for this variable come from World Economic Forum, THE GLOBAL COMPETITIVENESS REPORT 312 (1999).
Katharina Pistor, Martin Raiser, & Stanislav Gelfer, Law and Finance in Transition
Economies, European Bank for Reconstruction and Development Working Paper No.
48 (February 2000).
Ole-Kristian Hope, Disclosure Practices, Enforcement of Accounting Standards, and
Analysts Forecast Accuracy: An International Study, 41 J. ACCTG. RES. 235 (2003).
Mark H. Lang, Karl V. Lins, & Darius P. Miller, ADRs, Analysts, and Accuracy: Does
Cross Listing in the United States Improve a Firms Information Environment and Increase
Market Value?, 41 J. ACCTG. RES. 317 (2003).
Mark J. Roe, Corporate Laws Limits, 31 J. LEGAL STUD. 233 (2002).
190
191
INSIDER TRADING
The 1934 Exchange Act prohibitions on securities fraud and other securities law provisions outlaw insider trading in securities. Such insider trading
centrally involves prohibitions on corporate insiders, such as ocers and
directors and others privy to secret internal information, from selling or
buying stock based upon their private information gleaned from their positions. For example, these insiders usually have access to nancial information, such as quarterly prot reports, before the information is made public.
If such information is negative (worse than the market expects), an insider
could sell shares in his or her company before the market incorporates this
information in the companys value and prot from specialized nonpublic
knowledge. Of course, the law does not eectively prohibit all insider
trading, but it surely reduces the practice. The SEC cannot catch all wrongdoers, but by outlawing insider trading the law actually changes peoples
minds regarding the morality of insider trading and in that way, among
others, reduces its incidence.1 Research suggests that the legal prohibitions
prevent more blatant insider trading on advance knowledge of nancial
reports but do not prevent trading on more subjective inside information,
such as the future value of corporate research and development activities.
Intuitively, such insider trading seems unfair to most market investors. It
is unethical because it allows insiders to prot at the expense of outsiders
who cannot trade on equal footing no matter how diligently they follow the
market.2 It allows managers to appropriate for their own purposes information that rightfully belongs to their principals. Beyond these equitable
instincts, economic analysis suggests that insider trading puts outside
investors at greater risk and thereby discourages equity investments and
undermines capital markets.
Some, however, have suggested that parties be allowed to trade on inside
information. The legalization of insider trading is generally associated with
arguments initially made some time ago by a leading law and economics
scholar, Henry Manne.3 His theory was that because corporate insiders
were generating the inside information, they might therefore be given some
sort of property right in it. This would supposedly encourage insiders to
generate more useful information and, in the process, make the market
more informative and ecient. Manne even suggested that prots from
insider trading constitute the only eective compensation scheme for
entrepreneurial services in large corporations.4 Manne argued that this
eciency can benet other traders. For example, by driving down the price
of shares of a failing company through insider trading, insiders may
protect other investors from buying the shares at an inated price. Some
economists and others have agreed with Manne and argued that eciency
192
193
at low prices and release the accurate, positive information about the
company, which would produce a rise in share price from which the insider
would prot. The key to such a schemes success is purposeful dissemination of inaccurate information that is only later corrected. Insiders can reap
the most prots when a share price is very volatile, and they can manipulate and benet from the volatility by the selective release of accurate or
inaccurate positive or negative information. Because the information in
question is nonpublic, outside investors have no idea whether the original
negative or later positive information represents the true and accurate
report of the companys situation. This creates inecient markets and obviously makes outsiders reluctant to invest in capital markets. More rigorous
theoretical analyses have shown the ineciency of allowing insider trading,
for it can drive capital out of the market, increase the costs of funds and
thereby damage overall economic welfare.9
The prevailing rules of insider trading encourage management to
promptly supply relevant information to the market. The basic rule of insider
trading is disclose or abstain,10 that is, insiders must either refrain from
buying or selling stock in their company or disclose all material information
to the market. Insiders have a considerable incentive to trade shares in their
company. Many have large shareholdings resulting from options or other
incentive compensation and need to sell those shares to diversify their portfolios. This encourages insiders to fully release all material nonpublic information in order to be able to legally trade in their companys stock. To allow
insider trading would reverse the incentives and discourage such public disclosures. One study conrmed this intuition, nding that more trading by
insiders was linked to lesser information content in quarterly earnings
reports.11
Insider trading is also a poor method of compensating ocers.
Shareholders want to pay ocers for doing a good job and making the
company thrive. Thus, companies provide stock or options that will prot
the insider if share prices increase or bonuses based on corporate performance. Insider trading compensation, by contrast, would allow an ocer
to prot greatly from corporate failure. The insider could sell short the
companys shareholdings while running the company into the ground and
then disclose the companys collapse and prot from plummeting share
prices. Because it is no doubt easier to make a corporation fail than succeed
in a competitive market, this corporate destruction scheme might be the
most protable strategy for insiders.
Insider trading is also an ineective method of encouraging employees
to do their jobs well. Professor Manne only assumes that allowing insider
trading encourages the production of benecial information. A perusal of
litigated insider trading cases makes it clear that most insider trading is
194
done by people other than those who actually produce the information, and
that insider trading is just as protable when the news created is bad as
when it is good.
Allowing insider trading could also signicantly disrupt corporate management.12 Ocers might prot from trading on inside information, absent
prohibitions. The potential magnitude of their prots will be greater if they
are the only ones trading on the information. This creates an incentive for
ocers not to share information internally, at least not promptly, in an
internal competitive drive to prot from the information. Alternatively,
they might manipulate information submitted to coworkers in order to
advance their personal investment objectives.
The considerations raised in our prior chapters also counsel against the
legalization of insider trading. Given the well-established agency problems
associated with shareholder control of ocers, the fact that a company may
voluntarily permit insider trading does not establish that the authorization
is an ecient one in the interest of shareholders. Because there is substantial evidence that current compensation schemes in major public companies
are anything but ecient,13 there is no reason to believe that insider trading
compensation schemes would be either. Again, while one might hope that
insiders would not sacrice the companys interests to advance their own in
so naked a fashion, during the dot.com boom more stock option compensation for ocers tended to create more earnings management14 and more
nancial restatements.15
There is reason to believe that true arms length bargaining, absent
agency problems, would privately prohibit insider trading. One study found
that insider trading prots for ocers were smaller in companies with institutional shareholders and where the board chairman was not the chief
executive ocer.16 Because the latter features are closely associated with
better corporate control over ocers, the nding suggests that insider
trading does represent a manifestation of agency problems, with ocers
taking advantage of the shareholders they are supposed to be serving.
Allowing insider trading also increases transaction costs for investors.
Investors might reasonably have varying views of the value of allowing
insider trading and prefer to invest in rms that prohibit, or dont prohibit,
the practice. Before investing in a company, parties would have to identify
the corporations practices. If this were simply a binary (allow/disallow)
matter, this investigation would be simple, but companies are likely to
adopt more rened rules that permit insider trading by some insiders but
not by others, and under some circumstances but not in others. The need
to identify particular corporate practices would add cost (or risk) to investing. Even if Manne were correct that insider trading carries some benets,
they might not outweigh these increased transaction costs.
195
196
sample of more than one hundred nations and found that most had some
formal prohibition on insider trading but that only a minority had actually
enforced those prohibitions.21 They compared these nations on various
measures, including the mean returns and liquidity of rms, the value of
the companies, the cost of equity, and country risk measures. They found
that the mere presence of a prohibition had little eect on the cost of capital
but that the active enforcement of the prohibition had a substantial positive eect in decreasing the cost of equity. Another study combined the
LaPorta measures for securities law with the Bhattacharya and Daouk
insider trading enforcement measures and found that the combined variable was associated with statistically signicant benets.22 After insider
trading is restricted, analyst following of companies increases.23
Other research also seems to contradict the claimed benets of insider
trading. A study using a dierent measure found that countries with more
insider trading had more volatile stock markets.24 A study of the Polish
stock market found that insider trading did not make the market quantitatively more ecient by reducing earnings surprises, as Manne assumed
would occur. Two reasons for this result were that outsiders misinterpreted
the meaning of insiders trading and that independent analysts showed less
interest in following rms with substantial insider trading.25
While Manne and others have made a purely theoretical case for eliminating insider trading prohibitions, the theory assumes optimal private
eciency in decisionmaking. That assumption is dubious given the presence of agency problems and transaction costs, added to the behavioral
nance considerations. The empirical evidence now consistently arms the
economic benet of insider trading prohibitions. The proposal to legalize
insider trading is not in the best interest of capital markets. When Manne
made his original argument in favor of insider trading 40 years ago, the
United States was virtually alone in outlawing the practice. Over this
period, virtually every developed nation in the world has rejected Mannes
arguments and outlawed insider trading. Not a single nations experience
with these laws has led it to reconsider and reauthorize insider trading.
197
198
199
ISSUER DEREGULATION
The US securities law system is primarily built around the regulation of
issuers, the companies whose stock is traded. These are the entities that
must make periodic lings with the SEC, reporting such information as revenues and prots. The public disclosure requirements tested in Chapter 5
involve disclosures by issuers. A recent article by Stephen Choi has called
for a major restructuring in this system, which deregulates issuers in favor
of investor regulation.30
Choi argues that the current model of regulating issuers is an inecient,
indirect regulation of investors that prevents them from making certain
investments that they wish to make. He suggests that many rational
investors inevitably lose out on desirable opportunities but recognizes that
investors have various degrees of sophistication. He would recognize four
dierent categories of investors, based on their level of knowledge. Then he
would impose a sliding scale of restrictions on their investment choice,
depending on the degree of their knowledge and sophistication. Wellinformed investors would face relatively little regulation of their investment
choices. They could freely bargain for just the level of disclosure and fraud
protection that they desired, presumably paying more for their securities if
they desired more protection and less if they were willing to take their
chances. Unsophisticated investors would not be permitted to invest in any
instruments other than passive mutual funds.
The underlying basis of Chois creative proposal is that government rules
inevitably interfere with ecient free markets. However, Choi largely
ignores the ability of uniform rules to minimize transaction costs and create
valuable network eects, or perhaps he just too casually assumes it away.
Choi acknowledges that too many separate private fraud protection rules
200
201
202
prerequisites for strong securities markets are laws that give minority
shareholders (1) good information about the value of a companys business; and (2) condence that the companys insiders . . . wont cheat
investors out of most of the value of their investment.37 Issuer deregulation undermines both objections and thus would be an unwise modication
to the current system of securities law. As Black stated elsewhere, [i]ts
magical, in a way. People pay enormous amounts of money for completely
intangible rights. Internationally, this magic is pretty rare. It does not
appear in unregulated markets.38
COMPETITIVE REGULATION
A relatively new reform proposal contends that competition among regulators can produce superior securities law. Competition could arise from
various sources, but the primary proposal has involved creating competitive state securities regulation regimes. Securities regulation began at the
state level with legislation commonly known as blue sky laws that were
discussed in Chapter 4. The national securities laws and regulations were
adopted precisely because this existing competitive state law regime was
sorely inadequate. Some wish to restore states to primacy, though.
Roberta Romano has argued that securities regulation should be
returned to the states in order to create competitive regulatory systems.39
This approach would parallel current corporate law, in which companies
may choose in which state to incorporate and thereby choose the rules that
govern them. While Romano has suggested that states are closer to the
aected bodies, the focus of her proposal stresses the benets of competition among the producers of securities law.
Competition among states, Romano argues, gives regulators an incentive
to be accountable and responsive to the demands of the regulated. By creating better securities regulations, the theory suggests that states will attract
more companies and capital that adopt their rules. This would also act to
spur innovative regulatory improvements. Attracting more companies
could in turn attract more revenue through fee payments to the states. The
states would engage in a competitive race to the top in pursuit of the best
rules. The spur of competition would make the state actions preferable to
those of the federal government.
One fundamental theoretical problem with this approach is its presumption that states will behave in an economically ecient manner in structuring their governing rules. Gillian Hadeld and Eric Talley have challenged
this premise that states behave like prot-maximizing rms, choosing laws
and regulations that maximize state prots.40 State legislators gain some
203
benet from creating ecient laws, and regulated parties have an opportunity to aect their decisions. Agency problems certainly infect governmental responses to public interest, as collective interests and lobbyists are
certainly inuential.
The operationalization of this competitive regime is also somewhat
unclear, even if state governments did operate eciently. A states incentive
to produce optimal securities law supposedly involves the receipt of fees.
Yet there is no obvious reason why a company would be required to pay a
fee to use a states law. A company need not be located in a state, or even
have any connection to a state, to use that law. Choice of law clauses in
contracts are commonplace, and could adopt any states law in connection
with their share issuances. Such clauses would not necessarily extend to
private secondary market sales of shareholders, but there is no obvious way
that a state could prot from use of its law in such transactions. Indeed, the
use of law in these sales would presumably raise choice of law issues beyond
the control of the corporations that are supposedly selecting the laws, a
problem discussed further below.
Even if the state governments did not engage in eective competition for
optimal securities laws, competitive state regulation could theoretically
still yield benets by enabling companies to vote with their feet and
choose the states with the best laws. They would have a menu of 50 laws
from which to select. Assuming at least one of the state laws provided a
better system than the current federal law, the ability of businesses to
choose that better system could provide better regulation. Or perhaps
dierent regimes better t dierent types of companies, so the exibility
would be ecient.
The most obvious problem with this theory of state competition is that
it allows the regulated entity to choose its regulator, which is akin to allowing the fox to guard the henhouse. The purpose of the securities laws is to
protect investors, but they will not be choosing the state regulatory regime.
Rather, this choice will inevitably be made by corporate management,
which is the entity to be constrained by securities regulation. A management that wishes to defraud investors or simply wishes to preserve its
exibility would not choose the optimal system of securities regulation, it
would choose the least constraining system. Rather than a race to the
top, we could have a race to the bottom, with inecient laws that fail to
protect against fraud.41 The adoption of anti-takeover statutes, provisions
protecting directors from liability for their managerial shortcomings, and
other recent changes in state corporate law are more consistent with a race
to the bottom than one to the top.
Of course, management decisions are constrained to some degree by
investors, as ocers need to attract capital. Investors might prevent a true
204
race to the absolute bottom, with management choosing the weakest securities regulations, but this does not eliminate the basic agency problem discussed in Chapter 2. For investors to constrain management in the choice
of regulatory regime, they would have to familiarize themselves with the
functioning of 50 state regimes. Managers are likely to forgo some investment and share price gain, in order to be able to immunize themselves (and
their lucrative salaries) from oversight. This is another of the greatest shortcomings of the competitive state regulation approach, the transaction costs
that it imposes.
Competitive state regulation would lose the foremost font of the benets
of securities regulation, which derive from reduced transaction costs and
network eects. Investors would have signicantly increased transaction
costs under a competition program. They would have to familiarize themselves with the laws of 50 states. The laws could vary in innumerable ways,
such as accounting standards, substantive fraud rules, procedural enforcement rules, and others. The investor eort would involve not only investigation of the legislation itself but also implementing administrative rules
(which may change over time) and judicial interpretations of the law. Not
only may these judicial interpretations change, but they also depend on the
nature of the states judicial system, the investigation into which represents
yet another transaction cost. Moreover, investors would have to discern
which states law governs their potential lawsuit, a determination that could
be quite complicated in practice. In the process, all the ecient simplifying
network eects of a single fraud governance system are lost.
The choice of state laws that apply to a given case is an extraordinarily
complex eld of law. The general standards for such choice of law involve
the state where the underlying events took place and the state with the
greatest interest in its resolution. The underlying events in a securities fraud
action would be the actual purchase or sale (which might be the location of
the stock exchange on which the shares were traded) or the fraudulent
actions complained of. The latter might well be the corporate headquarters
where the primary ocers were located but not necessarily, as the fraud
might involve revenue recognition by lower level ocers at various locales
about the country or the state in which the company was incorporated (the
source of its corporate governance law rules). This creates a substantial
problem insofar as the applicable securities law will neither be clear to
investors nor within the control of the corporation purportedly seeking the
optimally ecient law to govern transactions in its securities. This problem
substantially enhances both the transaction costs and risks for investors
and undermines the claimed benets of the competitive law selection
system. The problem might be overcome by an arbitrary choice of law rule
based on the companys adoption of particular securities laws but this
205
would be a substantial departure from prevailing rules, losing their established benets, and would also be dicult to enforce (as any given state
would have the right to reject this standard).
The competitive system is also questionable in the light of behavioral
decisionmaking analysis. The managers who make the decisions about
choice of securities law will make self-serving decisions. If they did not do
so, there would be no agency problem and no need for law whatsoever, and
we could count on voluntary disclosure. Unfortunately, the reality is that
even honest managers will be inuenced by unconscious self-serving biases
that infect their decisionmaking.
Behavioral considerations also aect the ability of investors to respond
to managerial choices to use the securities laws of a particular state. Putting
a market price on the dierence between two state laws would be extremely
dicult, especially when those laws may change and are substantially
inuenced by unknown future administrative interpretations and judicial
rulings. It is dicult to imagine how an investor would be able to judge the
eectiveness of dierent regulatory regimes, much less quantify that knowledge in a manner allowing the investor to change the purchasing or selling
price of a particular security.42 Without this ability, investors are necessarily economically at sea, forced to make investment judgments they
cannot accurately value or, if they are risk averse, avoid many investments
due to the valuation uncertainty.
There is no empirical experience with competitive state securities laws by
which this competitive regulation proposal may be tested, but there are
some slightly analogous contexts to examine. Corporate law, for example,
is largely left to state governance. In corporate law, Delaware has become
the overwhelmingly preponderant source of law for major national corporations. This state primacy might be due to the fact that Delaware law is
optimal, but this seems unlikely. More likely, the decision is attributable to
network eects. Reincorporation to change the law of corporate governance is an extremely rare event, suggesting that the market is not truly
competitive, and the predominance of Delaware law refutes suggestions
that dierent rms could benet from dierent laws. Moreover, other states
have generally not even sought to compete with Delaware, because the tax
receipts from being the locus of incorporation are quite small.43 Instead,
they have typically piggybacked upon such law, with limited exceptions
such as anti-takeover laws, which are a dubious defense for state choice.
Additionally, the corporate law context is unaected by the substantial
choice of law problems, as the widespread internal aairs doctrine provides that corporate law cases are governed by the state of incorporation.
When state corporate laws do change, state legislators appear to act to
satisfy local constituencies, such as the demands of major employers, rather
206
than in an eort to attract more corporations.44 Delaware has become dominant, and network eects ensure that it preserves this position. Other states
have largely adopted Delawares law, rather than competing with it, and
Romano concedes that the substantive content of the 50 state corporation
laws is substantially uniform.45 Ninety-seven percent of new incorporations choose either Delaware or their home state, which does not suggest
the presence of any meaningful competition.46 In short, competition
among states to provide corporate law is largely a myth and therefore provides no reasonable basis for arguing that a similar regime of competition
to provide securities law could succeed. If there is no meaningful competition to provide corporate law, a realm where the states have been the
primary providers for decades, how much less likely is it that there will be
meaningful competition to provide securities law where the states have
played only a supporting role (and have no obvious means of proting)?
Europe has provided something of a natural experiment for such choice.
While the continent has some coordinated governance, individual nations
persist and historically established their own securities laws. This was a competitive system, though evidence indicates that it was not working
eciently.47 This system recently changed as the European Union adopted
uniform securities disclosure requirements in order to bring more consistency to regulation, as dierent standards were inhibiting cross-border
trading. Inconsistent international standards were limiting the number of
investors willing to purchase ownership from corporations governed by
dierent laws. The continent harmonized its laws in order to provide stronger
capital markets.48 The mere fact that European governments are moving
toward a centralized system and coordinated standards resembling the US
model refutes competitive regulatory proposals, because those proposals rely
on the assumption that governments will make ecient decisions.
In some respects, the competitive state regulation approach appears to
oer the worst of both worlds. While the purported benets of such competition arise from market-based checks on regulatory systems, it is inferior
to a purely private system. In a private system, companies could design any
investor protection scheme and implement it via contract. Regulatory competition loses much of this assumed competitive benet, because it limits
corporate choices to those oered by the states and requires formal government approval, legislative or bureaucratic, before any new systems could be
implemented. The disadvantage of the purely private system lies in transaction costs and network eects (addressed in Chapter 2) and inecient
behavioral decisionmaking heuristics (addressed in Chapter 3). Regulatory
competition suers these same disadvantages. While transaction costs
might be slightly reduced by the limit of regulations to 50 state systems,
they would not be much reduced, given the need to understand and monitor
207
208
SARBANES-OXLEY ACT
Perhaps the greatest current controversy in securities law (and corporate
law) involves the Sarbanes-Oxley Act (known colloquially as SOX). In
response to several huge corporate scandals (Enron, WorldCom, Tyco,
Adelphia, and so on) Congress passed SOX in 2002. While America has a
rich history of corporate scandals, the spate of corporate disasters that
prompted the Acts passage was remarkable for its magnitude. This law
209
210
211
high, much higher than the SEC had predicted. Current Commission
eorts have sent a message that they will take a reasonable approach to
assessing compliance to hold down costs.
Perhaps the greatest concern about SOX is the indirect cost associated
with regulatory direction of business decisionmaking and associated
ineciencies. One widely publicized study examined the market reactions
to legislative events during the passage of the statute and concluded that
SOX resulted in a loss of US$1.4 trillion in total market value.69 While this
would be a profound negative eect, it reected only the markets anticipation of SOX regulations and their eects, not the actual practice under the
law. In addition, a dierent study used the same methodology of examining market reactions to SOX and reached exactly opposite conclusions. It
found negative market eects while the application of the law was uncertain but signicantly positive market eects once the precise obligations of
those terms reached their nal form, indicating that investors expected the
Act to have a net benecial eect on the market.70 Another study found that
SOX had a positive and statistically signicant eect on the value of large
companies, but not small ones,71 while yet another indicated that its
benets exceeded its compliance costs.72
The contradictory event studies associated with enactment and implementation do not provide denitive guidance on the economic eect of
SOX but suggest that its eect may well have been benecial. The performance of the American stock market in the wake of the statutes passage
indicates that it was successful in restoring the condence of American
investors, which had been at a post-9/11 low. Empirical research indicates
that SOX restored investor condence in the markets and restored liquidity that had been greatly reduced by Enron-era scandals.73 Another postSOX study found that investors value information about internal controls
and that small investors beneted the most from disclosure of the information.74 A survey of public company directors found that more than 60
percent believed that SOX had been positive for their companies.75
A major concern about SOX has been the fear that its costly requirements may promote going private or going dark (reducing the number
of public shareholders below a certain threshold). If the costs of compliance were great, some companies might be expected to give up their publicly traded status and avoid those costs. There is evidence that this
occurred, with an increase in going-private transactions following SOX.
The increase was especially pronounced among smaller companies with
relatively higher compliance costs.76 This going private trend would be
evidence of a negative eect of SOX, though other research suggests that
the immediate increase in going-private transactions was unrelated to
the statute.77
212
Other relevant research involves the eect of SOX on cross-listing behavior of foreign companies. A decrease in cross-listing would suggest that the
additional compliance costs outweighed the bonding eects of this practice. Again, the evidence is conicting. One study found that passage of the
Act had a signicant positive value on cross-listing companies, in nations
with eective judiciaries.78 A more recent study of the eects of the Act
after a short time found that stocks of cross-listed companies declined
signicantly as compared to comparable companies in response to SOX.79
This is probably the best evidence questioning SOX as a whole, but it did
not address the eect of individual changes made by the statute. There is
thus some evidence of a negative eect of SOX in the going-private and
cross-listing evidence, but the case is not yet a conclusive one.
The evidence regarding SOXs most controversial provisions, those
dealing with internal nancial controls, especially section 404, is at this
stage quite mixed. The debate over whether the benets of these provisions
outweigh the costs cannot currently be settled. Indeed, it may never be
settled for the simple reason that although the costs of SOX in this regard
are largely measurable, measuring the benets is somewhat more elusive.
The primary benets of more eective internal nancial controls will relate
to the mismanagement, earnings management, frauds, and other crimes
that will not occur. It is easy to measure the cost of installing a metal detector in an airport, but it is impossible to determine how many attempted
hijackings or bombings its installation averted. The same is true with
Sarbanes-Oxleys internal control provisions.
It is worth remembering that shareholder losses in Enron-era scandals
totaled well over US$200 billion. The US$25 billion loss involving Enron
alone will substantially outweigh even the most exaggerated estimates of
total SOX implementation costs.80 If SOX could indeed prevent or minimize the nancial consequences of such scandals, it would have considerable benet. The internal control rules were a sensible approach to
preventing a reoccurrence of the Enron-era scandals, for empirical evidence
indicates that before SOX was passed, rms with poor internal controls
tended to have more restatements of their nancial statements and other
disclosure problems than did other rms.81 Firms with weak internal controls also tend to engage in more earnings management.82
Studies of the actual impact of SOXs internal control provisions are
somewhat encouraging. One study indicates that SOXs internal control
provisions are leading managers to report nancial results more conservatively.83 Another study found that since SOX was passed rms discovering
problems with their internal controls have tended to have poorer quality
disclosures than other rms, indicating that sections 302 and 404 of SOX
are appropriately helping identify the drivers of poor quality nancial
213
214
215
216
for smaller companies. SOX undoubtedly could benet from some tailoring that may relax some requirements, but such adjustments should be
grounded in the empirical evidence about the eects of the law and account
for the demonstrated benets of securities regulation for markets.
CONCLUSION
While the verdict is surely out for any particular change in US securities law,
including the particular changes of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act, this analysis
suggests that we should be wary of making deregulatory changes as to any
basic matters. The case for many proposed deregulatory reforms fails to
appreciate the value of the law. The reform proposals are all animated by a
devotion to private orderingallowing issuers and investors to dene the
scope of their obligations. Such private ordering is fundamental to the
value of free markets but should not be worshipped so religiously. Proper
legal structures not only do not hinder such private ordering, they are necessary for it to work eciently.
Among the legal structures that facilitate markets is uniform, mandatory
disclosure, and meaningful protection against securities fraud. Such a
system has classical economic benets by sparing investors the need to
undertake extensive transaction costs or substantial risks. It has behavioral
economic benets by giving investors some comfort that they will not
readily be defrauded and lack any remedy. By penalizing disclosure failures
and fraud, the system deters their commission, to some degree, making the
markets more welcoming and economically ecient. These claims are
amply conrmed by the empirical evidence, in various contexts such as
cross-country research and historical analyses. The empirical studies show
that, whatever the benets of the privatizing reforms, their costs to equity
markets are greater.
The general benets of securities regulation do not justify any and every
new requirement. But the prevailing system of US securities regulation is
working very well and has produced thriving markets. The corporate scandals that inspired SOX demonstrate that our system is awed but suggest
that past regulation may have been too weak rather than too strong.
Moreover, despite that fraud, the US economy and stock market have performed well both on an absolute basis and relative to other countries over
recent decades.113 The success story of US securities law has made it a
model for regulatory reforms in virtually all other developed nations.114
Given the demonstrable benets of securities regulation, reformers therefore should bear the burden of proving the value of any major proposed
modications to that system. This proof must at minimum involve grap-
217
pling with the transaction cost/network eect benets of uniform fraud protection rules, as well as some consideration of the behavioral factors
inuencing human decisionmaking. It should also draw on empirical evidence about the actual eect of the proposed reform. The advocates of fundamental reform in US securities laws have not even come close to meeting
those logical burdens for most of their proposed changes.
NOTES
1. Richard H. McAdams, An Attitudinal Theory of Expressive Law, 79 OR. L. REV. 339,
389 (2000).
2. See Alan Strudler & Eric W. Orts, Moral Principle in the Law of Insider Trading, 78 TEX.
L. REV. 375 (1999).
3. Henry G. Manne, INSIDER TRADING AND THE STOCK MARKET (1966).
4. Id. at 116.
5. See Dennis W. Carlton & Daniel R. Fischel, The Regulation of Insider Trading, 35 STAN.
L. REV. 857 (1983).
6. See Harold Demsetz, Corporate Control, Insider Trading and Rates of Return, 76 AM.
ECON. REV. 313 (1986).
7. Kimberly D. Krawiec, Privatizing Outsider Trading, 41 VA. J. INTL L. 693 (2001).
8. 401 F.2d 833 (2d Cir. 1968).
9. See Lawrence M. Ausubel, Insider Trading in a Rational Expectations Economy, 80 AM.
ECON. REV. 1022 (1990).
10. United States v. OHagan, 521 U.S. 642 (1997).
11. S.C. Udpa, Insider Trading and the Information Content of Earnings, 23 J. BUS. FIN. &
ACCOUNTING 1069 (1996).
12. See Robert J. Haft, The Eect of Insider Trading Rules on the Internal Eciency of the
Large Corporation, 80 MICH. L. REV. 1051 (1982).
13. Lucian Bebchuk & Jesse Fried, PAY WITHOUT PERFORMANCE THE UNFULFILLED PROMISE OF EXECUTIVE COMPENSATION (2004).
14. Qiang Cheng & Terry D. Wareld, Equity Incentives and Earnings Management
(November 2004), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=457840.
15. Jap Efendi, Anup Srivastava, & Edward P. Swanson, Why Do Corporate Managers
Misstate Financial Statements? The Role of In-the-Money Options and Other Incentives
(September 4, 2005), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=547922.
16. James S. Ang. & Don. R. Cox, Controlling the Agency Cost of Insider Trading, 10 J. FIN.
& STRATEGIC DECISIONS 15 (1997).
17. See Herbert Gintis, et al., Moral Sentiments and Material Interests: Origins, Evidence,
and Consequences, in MORAL SENTIMENTS AND MATERIAL INTERESTS:
THE FOUNDATIONS OF COOPERATION IN ECONOMIC LIFE 8 (Herbert
Gintis, et al eds. 2005).
18. See Robert A. Prentice & Jonathan J. Koehler, A Normality Bias in Legal Decision
Making, 88 CORNELL L. REV. 583, 60612 (2003).
19. Robert A. Prentice, Contract-Based Defenses in Securities Fraud Litigation: A Behavioral
Analysis, U. ILL. L. REV. 337, 376 (2003).
20. Laura Nyantung Beny, Do Insider Trading Laws Matter? Some Preliminary Comparative
Evidence, 7 AM. LAW & ECON REV. 144 (2005).
21. Utpal Bhattacharya & Hazem Daouk, The World Price of Insider Trading, 57 J. FIN. 75
(2002).
22. Pankav Jain, Institutional Design and Liquidity at Stock Exchanges Around the World
(January 2002).
218
23. Robert M. Bushman, Joseph D. Piotroski, & Abbie J. Smith, Insider Trading Restrictions
and Analysts Incentives to Follow Firms, 60 J. FIN. 35 (2005).
24. Julan Du & Shang-Jin Wei, Does Insider Trading Raise Market Volatility, 114 ECON. J.
916 (2004).
25. Tomasz P. Wisniewski, Reexamination of the Link Between Insider Trading and Price
Eciency, 28 ECON. SYSTEMS 209 (2004), available at www.sciencedirect.com/
science/article/B6W8Y-4CVX0YT-1/2/01c276b6edf476dfba6fe0ec26f321e9.
26. Carr v. CIGNA Securities, Inc., 95 F.3d 544 (7th Cir. 1996).
27. William N. Landes & Richard A. Posner, THE ECONOMIC STRUCTURE OF TORT
LAW 28081 (1987).
28. Lee Ross, et al., The False Consensus Eect: An Egocentric Bias in Social Perception
and Attribution Processes, 17 J. EXPERIMENTAL SOC. PSYCHOL. 279 (1977).
29. Joseph W. Rand, The Demeanor Gap: Race, Lie Detection, and the Jury, 33 CONN.
L.REV. 1, 3 (2000).
30. Stephen Choi, Regulating Investors Not Issuers: A Market-Based Proposal, 88 CAL. L.
REV. 279 (2000).
31. See Merle Erickson, Michelle Hanlon, Michelle, & Edward L. Maydew, Is There a Link
Between Executive Compensation and Accounting Fraud? (February 24, 2004), available
at http://ssrn.com/abstract=509505.
32. Robert A. Prentice, Chicago Man, K-T Man, and the Future of Behavioral Law and
Economics, 56 VAND. L. REV. 1663 (2003).
33. See Gary Belsky & Thomas Gilovich, WHY SMART PEOPLE MAKE BIG MONEY
MISTAKESAND HOW TO CORRECT THEM 152 (1999).
34. James A. Fanto, Were All Capitalists Now: The Importance, Nature, Provision and
Regulation of Investor Education, 49 CASE W. RES. L. REV. 105, 135 (1998).
35. Robert A. Prentice, Whither Securities Regulation? Some Behavioral Observations
Regarding Proposals for its Future, 51 DUKE L.J. 1397 (2002).
36. Matthew Josephson, Infrequent Corporation Reports Keep Investors in Dark, 36 MAG.
OF WALL ST. 302, 374 (June 20, 1925).
37. Bernard Black, The Legal and Institutional Preconditions for Strong Securities Markets,
48 UCLA L. REV. 781, 783 (2001).
38. Bernard S. Black, Information Asymmetry, the Internet, and Securities Oerings, 2
J. SMALL & EMERGING BUS. L. 91, 9293 (1998).
39. Roberta Romano, THE ADVANTAGE OF COMPETITIVE FEDERALISM FOR
SECURITIES REGULATION (2002).
40. Gillian K. Hadeld & Eric L. Talley, On Public Versus Private Provision of Corporate
Law 11, University of Southern California Law & Economics Research Paper No.
04118 (2004).
41. See e.g., William L. Cary, Federalism and Corporate Law: Reections upon Delaware, 83
YALE L.J. 663 (1974).
42. David S. Ruder, Reconciling U.S. Disclosure Policy with International Accounting and
Disclosure Standards, 17 NW. J. INTL L. & BUS. 1, 10 (1996).
43. See Marcel Kahan & Ehud Kamar, The Myth of State Competition in Corporate Law,
55 STAN. L. REV. 679, 68788 (2002).
44. Id. at 70124.
45. Romano, supra note 39, at 21.
46. Robert Daines, The Incorporation Choices of IPO Firms, 77 N.Y.U. L. REV. 1559, 1562
(2002).
47. Klause Heine & Wolfgang Kerber, European Corporate Laws, Regulatory Competition
and Path Dependence, 13 EUROPEAN J. LAW ECON. 47 (2002).
48. Eric Pan, Harmonization of U.S.EU Securities Regulation: The Case for a Single
European Securities Regulator, LAW & POLICY IN INTL BUS (Winter 2003).
49. Mahoney and Pritchard have made the most persuasive cases for an increased role for
securities exchanges in securities. Paul G. Mahoney, The Exchange as Regulator, 83 VA.
L. REV. 1453 (1997); Adam C. Pritchard, Markets as Monitors: A Proposal to Replace
Class Actions with Exchanges as Securities Fraud Enforcers, 85 VA. L. REV. 925 (1999).
219
50. Albert B. Crenshaw, SEC to Toughen Rule on Option Plans, WASHINGTON POST,
December 20, 2001, at E1.
51. Jenny Anderson, Should the Securities Industry Have Just One Set of Rules?, N.Y.
TIMES, January 25, 2006, at C3.
52. Romano, supra note 39, at 145.
53. Edward Rock, Securities Regulation as Lobster Trap: A Credible Commitment Theory of
Mandatory Disclosure, 23 CARDOZO L. REV. 695, 697 (2002) (noting numerous
limitations of the NYSE and other exchanges, especially an inability to impose criminal
sentences).
54. Roberta Romano, Empowering Investors: A Market Approach to Securities Regulation,
107 YALE L.J. 2359 (1998).
55. Frederick Tung, Lost in Translation: From U.S. Corporate Charter Competition to Issuer
Choice in International Securities Regulation, 39 GA. L. REV. 525, 59091 (2005).
56. One of the authors has addressed these matters in some detail. Robert A. Prentice,
Regulatory Competition in Securities Law: A Dream (that Should Be) Deferred, 66 OHIO
ST. L.J. 1155 (2005).
57. Lisa Bryant-Kutcher, Emma Yan Peng, & Kristina Zvinakis, Timeliness and Quality of
10-K Filings: The Impact of the Accelerated Filing Deadline (June 3, 2005). These
authors found that the quality of lings did not diminish after the SEC shortened the
deadline for ling 10-Ks from 90 days to 75 days, as critics had predicted. Therefore,
under the new rules, investors were receiving just as reliable information in a timelier
fashion.
58. Independent directors are those who are not ocers, nor controlled by ocers or controlling corporate shareholders.
59. Much of the blame in the major corporate scandals provoking SOX was placed at the
feet of outside auditors, who approved fraudulent nancial statements. The argument
was that the auditors did so in order to preserve their more lucrative income received
from providing consulting and other services to the very companies that they were
auditing.
60. Sarbanes-Oxley Act, S. 304.
61. Id S. 402.
62. See William W. Bratton & Joseph A. McCahery, The Equilibrium Content of Corporate
Federalism 12 (October 2004), ECGI Law Working Paper 23/2004, available at
http//ssrn.com/abstract=606481.
63. William J. Carney, The Costs of Being Public After Sarbanes-Oxley: The Irony of Going
Private 55 EMORY L.J. 141 (2006).
64. Larry E. Ribstein, Sarbanes-Oxley after Three Years, University of Illinois Law &
Economics Research Papter No. LE05016, 378 (2005).
65. Id. at 6.
66. Stephen Brown, et al., Management Forecasts and Litigation Risk (April 2005), available
at http://ssrn.com/abstract=709161.
67. See www.afponline.org/pub/res/news/ns_20051229_cs.html.
68. Larry E. Rittenberg & Patricia K. Miller, Sarbanes-Oxley Section 404 Work: Looking at
the Benets, Institute of Internal Auditors. Research Foundation (November 9, 2005),
available at www.theiia.org/?doc_id=5161.
69. Ivy Xiying Zhang, Economic Consequences of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002 (February
2005).
70. Haidan Li, Morton Pincus, & Sonja O. Rego, Market Reaction to Events Surrounding the
Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002 (January 11, 2006).
71. Vidhi Chhaochharia & Yaniv Grinstein, Corporate Governance and Firm Value : The
Impact of the 2002 Governance Rules (June 2004).
72. Zabihollah Rezaee & Pankaj K. Jain, The Sarbanes-Oxley Act of 2002 and Security
Market Behavior: Early Evidence (May 2005).
73. Pankaj K. Jain, Jang-Chul Kim, & Zabihollah Rezaee, The Eect of the Sarbanes-Oxley
Act of 2002 on Market Liquidity (March 2004), available at http://ssrn.com/
abstract=488142.
220
74. Gus De Franco, Yuyan Guan, & Hai Lu, The Wealth Change and Redistribution Eects
of Sarbanes-Oxley Internal Control Disclosures (April 17, 2005), available at
http://ssrn.com/abstract=706701.
75. Cynthia Harrington, The Value Proposition, J. ACCOUNTANCY, 77 (September 2005).
76. Stanley B. Block, The Latest Movement to Going Private: An Empirical Study, 14 J.
APPLIED FIN. 36 (2004).
77. Peter C. Hsu, Going Private : A Response to an Increased Regulatory Burden?, UCLA
School of Law-Econ. Research Paper No. 0416 (May 2004).
78. Philip G. Berger, Feng Li, & M.H. Franco Wong, The Impact of Sarbanes-Oxley on
Foreign Private Issuers (October 21, 2004).
79. Kate Litvak, The Eect of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act on Non-US Companies Cross-Listed
in the U.S., U. of Texas Law and Econ. Research Paper No. 55 (December 22, 2005).
80. Pamela MacLean, SOX inspires Backlashand Benets, NATL L.J. (April 22, 2005).
81. Hollis Ashbaugh-Skaife, Daniel W. Collins, & William R. Kinney, Jr., The Discovery and
Consequences of Internal Control Deciencies Prior to SOX-Mandated Audits,
McCombs Working Paper No. ACC-0205 (September 15, 2005), available at
http://ssrn.com/abstract=694681.
82. Kam C. Chan, Barbara R. Farrell, & Picheng Lee, Earnings Management and ReturnEarnings Association of Firms Reporting Material Internal Control Weaknesses Under
Section 404 of the Sarbanes-Oxley Act (June 2005), available at http://papers.ssrn.
com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=744806.
83. Gerald J. Lobo & Jian Zhou, Did Conservatism in Financial Reporting Increase after the
Sarbanes-Oxley Act? Initial Evidence, 20 ACCT. HORIZONS 57 (2006).
84. Jerey T. Doyle, Ge Weili, Ge, & Sarah E. McVay, Accruals Quality and Internal Control
over Financial Reporting, AAA 2006 Financial Accounting and Reporting Section
(FARS) Meeting Paper (August 2005), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=789985.
85. Jacqueline S. Hammersley, Linda A. Myers, & Catherine Shakespeare, Market
Reactions to the Disclosure of Internal Control Weaknesses and to the Characteristics
of those Weaknesses under Section 302 of the Sarbanes Oxley Act of 2002
(October 2005).
86. Gus De Franco, Yuyan Guan, and Hai Lu, The Wealth Change and Redistribution Eects
of Sarbanes-Oxley Internal Control Disclosures (April 17, 2005) available at
http://ssrn.com/abstract=706701.
87. See Roberta Romano, The Sarbanes-Oxley Act and the Making of Quack Corporate
Governance, 114 YALE L.J. 1521, 1542 (2005).
88. See Paul A. Grin & David H. Lont, Taking the Oath: Investor Response to SEC
Certication Under Sarbanes-Oxley (April 30, 2004).
89. Pankav K. Jain, Jang-Chul Kim, & Zabihollah Rezaee, Have the Sarbanes-Oxley Act of
2002 and the CEO Certications Made the Market Participants More Informed (January
2003).
90. Hsihui Chang, Jeng-Fang Chen, & Woody M. Liao, CEOs/CFOs Swearing by the
Numbers: Does It Impact Share Price of the Firm? (October 2003).
91. Hammersley, Myers, & Shakespeare, supra note 85.
92. Michael T. Burr, Corporations Caught in Rising Tide of FCPA Enforcement, CORPORATE LEGAL TIMES, November 2005, at 22.
93. See Romano, supra note 87.
94. Id. at 153032.
95. Id. at 153536.
96. April Klein, Audit Committee, Board of Director Characteristics, and Earnings
Management, 33 J. ACCT. & ECON. 375 (2002).
97. Anup Agrawal & Sahiba Chadha, Corporate Governance and Accounting Scandals, 48 J.
L. & ECON. 371 (October. 2005).
98. Mark S. Beasley, An Empirical Analysis of the Relations Between the Board of Director
Composition and Financial Statement Fraud, 71 ACCT. REV. 443 (1996).
99. Sonda M.Chtourou, Jean Bedard, & Lucie Courteau, Corporate Governance and
Earnings Management (April 21, 2001) available at http://ssrn.com.abstract=275053.
221
100. Lawrence J. Abbott, Susan Parker, & Gary F. Peters, Audit Committee Characteristics
and Financial Misstatement: A Study of the Ecacy of Certain Blue Ribbon Committee
Recommendations, 23 AUDITING: A J. OF PRAC. & THEORY 69 (March 2004).
101. Mark S. Beasley, et al., Fraudulent Financial Reporting: Consideration of Industry Traits
and Corporate Governance Mechanisms, 14 ACCT. REV. 441 (2000).
102. Jennie Goodwin & Tech Yeow Yeo, Two Factors Aecting Internal Audit Independence
and Objectivity: Evidence from Singapore, 5 INTL J. AUDIT. 107, 116 (2001).
103. Jean Bedard, et al., The Eect of Audit Committee Expertise, Independence, and Activity
on Aggressive Earnings Management, 23 AUDITING: A J. OF PRAC. & THEORY 13
(September 2004).
104. Dorothy A. McMullen & K. Raghundan, Enhancing Audit Committee Eectiveness, 182
J. ACCTCY. 79 (August 1996).
105. Andrew J. Felo, et al., Audit Committee Characteristics and the Perceived Quality of
Financial Reporting: An Empirical Analysis (April 2003), available at http://ssrn.
com/abstract=401240.
106. Sonda M.Chtourou, Jean Bedard, & Lucie Courteau, Corporate Governance and
Earnings Management (April 21, 2001), available at http://ssrn.com/abstract=275053.
107. Lawrence J. Abbot, et al., Audit Committee Characteristics and Financial Misstatement:
A Study of the Ecacy of Certain Blue Ribbon Committee Recommendations, 23
AUDITING: A J. OF PRAC. & THEORY 69 (March 2004).
108. Jayanthi Krishnan, Audit Committee Quality and Internal Control: An Empirical
Analysis, 80 ACCT. REV. 649 (2005).
109. Daniel A. Cohen, Aiyesha Dey, & Thomas Z. Lys, Trends in Earnings Management and
Informativeness of Earnings Announcements in the Pre- and Post-Sarbanes Oxley Periods
(February 2005).
110. See Bengt Holmstrom & Steven N. Kaplan, The State of U.S. Corporate Governance:
Whats Right and Whats Wrong, NBER Working Paper No. 9613, 18 (April 2003).
111. See Lina Saigol, Fewer Willing to Take Director Risk, FIN. ANCIAL TIMES,
November 24, 2004, at 22.
112. See Robert A. Prentice, The Inevitability of a Strong SEC, 91 CORNELL L. REV. 775
(forthcoming) (describing the popularity of American-style securities regulation in
Asian and European nations).
113. Bengt Holmstrom & Steven N. Kaplan, The State of U.S. Corporate Governance: Whats
Right and Whats Wrong, NBER Working Paper No. 9613 (April 2003) at Table 1.
114. See Gerard Hertig, Convergence of Substantive Law and Enforcement, in CONVERGENCE AND PERSISTENCE IN CORPORATE GOVERNANCE 33, 53 (Jerey
N. Gordon & Mark J. Roe eds. 2004).
Index
Titles of publications and legal cases are in italics.
Abbott, L.J. 21415
accounting firms as intermediaries
412
acquisitions, effect of corporate and
securities law 61
affective trust 389, 58
Akerlof, G. 33
America
corporate law 2, 1215
disclosure rules 1347
fiduciary duty 124
fraud prevention 13941
insider trading regulation 1423
securities law 2, 1519
see also Sarbanes-Oxley Act;
Securities Act; Securities
Exchange Act
securities law controversies 190217
takeover regulation 1435
anchoring and adjustment
and auditor failure 88
and decisionmaking 76
appraisal rights, minority shareholders
126
Asch, S. 75
assumpsit 11112
audit committee and Sarbanes-Oxley
Act 214
auditing costs and Sarbanes-Oxley Act
210
auditing firms as intermediaries 412
auditor failure, behavioral reasons
878
availability heuristic, and
decisionmaking 74
Azfar, O. 155
Bainbridge, S.M. 956
bank lending and company financing 5
Barberis, N. 81
Barnards Act 133
Barro, R. 152
basic law 1012
analysis of associations 16670
and behavioral decision theory 829
development of 11016
economic effects 156, 186
and trust 2931
Bedard, J. 214
behavioral decision theory 7079
and competitive regulation 205
and contracting around fraud 198
and corporate disclosure 947
and corporate law 8993
and efficient market hypothesis
7982
and insider trading 195
and issuer deregulation 200201
and securities law 93101
and stockbrokers 934
Benartzi, S. 80
Benston, G. 60
Beny, L. 195
Berle, A.A. 123
Bernstein, L. 11
Bernstein, W. 129
Bhattacharya, U. 1956
Birth of Plenty: How the Prosperity of
the Modern World was Created
129
Black, B. 54, 2012
Blair, M.M. 9091, 118
Bogle, J. 87
bonding assets 1278
bounded rationality 712
bounded willpower 79
Bowling Alone 29
Bubble Act 119, 130, 1323
223
224
Index
bubbles 1313
business judgment rule 48, 93
business xenophobia 367
Butler, N. 117
capital, costs of, effect of laws 156
capital market development 13033
and disclosure 1338
and insider trading 1413
and misrepresentation 13841
and takeovers 1437
Carr v. CIGNA Securities 197
cash/price variable and securities law
180
centralized control by managers 122
certification requirement, SarbanesOxley Act 213
China, takeover regulation 146
Choi, S. 100, 199201
Chtourou, S.M. 214
civil law countries
contract law development 112
fraud law 11415
securities law development 1378
class action fraud litigation 55, 140
Coase, R. 11314, 118
Coffee, J.C. 62
cognitive dissonance 723
and auditor failure 87
and stockbroker behavior 94
common law 9
economic effects 153
fraud rules 545
common law nations
contract law development 11112
tort law development 11415
see also America; England
communalities, factor analysis 175
community-based transactions 367
Companies Act 134
Companies Clauses Consolidation Act
134
company financing 45
compensation of executives
and behavioral theory 912
effect of insider trading 193
competitive regulation 2028
private securities exchanges 2078
state securities regulation 2027
compliance costs
Index
factor analysis 176
and World Bank financial variables
17071
corporate scandals 23, 867
corporations 11627
bonding assets 1278
development 11618
fiduciary duty of managers 1235
limited liability 12021
management control 122
minority shareholders 1257
perpetuity of existence 120
separate legal identity 11819
costs
of capital, effect of laws 156
of compliance, Sarbanes-Oxley Act
21011
compulsory corporate rules 48
corporate and securities law
compliance 645
credit-rating agencies 41
crime and contract enforcement 44
cross-country scaling of national legal
content 1589
cross-listing 613
effect of Sarbanes-Oxley Act 212
Daouk, H. 1956
Dartmouth College (case) 119
Davis, J. 110
deceit, see fraud
Dechow, P.M. 86
decisionmaking, see behavioral
decision theory
Delaware law 15, 51
and takeovers 145
Derry v. Peek 139
director independence and SarbanesOxley Act 214
disclosure 524
and behavioral decision theory
947
effect of regulation 60
regulation development 1338
variables, effect of law 1845
voluntary 534
disposition effect 81
Donaldson, T. 90
Drucker, P. 118
Dunfee, T.W. 90
225
226
Index
government
as monitoring intermediary 434
role in decisionmaking 1013
groupthink and decisionmaking 756
growth, see economic growth
Grubman, J. 40
Gulati, M. 100
habit heuristic and decisionmaking
78
Hadfield, G. 202
Havemeyer, H.O. 135
herding, and decisionmaking 76
history of law
basic law 11016
contract law 11112
corporate law 11629
property law 11214
securities regulation 234, 12947
tort law 11416
honesty of management, measurement
164
Hu, Chung 41
human capital variable 179
illusion of control
and decisionmaking 74
and fraud protection 99
inefficiency of corporate laws 49
information provision, private
intermediaries 42
insensitivity to information source
and auditor failure 88
and decisionmaking 75
and fraud protection 100
insider trading 1916
and Exchange Act 1718, 142
effect on markets 1956
legalization 1912
regulation development 1413
inspection rights, minority
shareholders 126
Institutional Shareholder Services
(ISS) 42
intellectual property rights 114
intermediaries, see private
intermediaries
intermediate agency problem, effect of
laws 1835
intermediate variables 1634, 1825
Index
internal financial controls and
Sarbanes-Oxley Act 21213
investment
company financing 45
effect of Securities Act 5960
and trust 31
see also Prisoners Dilemma of
investment
investor irrationality 8082
issuer deregulation 199202
Japan
corporate law development 129
takeover regulations 146
Jensen, M.C. 80
Joint-Stock Companies Registration,
Incorporation and Regulation Act
134
judicial systems 1011
Kahneman, D. 71, 77
Kaplow, L. 4
King, R. 5
Klausner, M. 56
Korea, takeover regulations 146
Korobkin, R. 84
Kraakman, R.H. 79
Kreuger, I. 1356
Krishnan, J. 215
La Porta, R. 1534, 160
La Porta financial variables 162
La Porta scale of national legal
content 1589
Langevoort, D.C. 92
law
economic effects measurement
15288
and economic growth 37
effect on financial markets 154
history of, see history of law
and transactions 379
and trust 2946, 85
see also basic law; common law;
contract law; corporate law;
property law; securities law
Law, J. 131
legal identity, corporations 11819
legal origin 9
as basic law variable 1578
227
228
Index
probability assessment
and decisionmaking 76
and fraud 99
property law development 11214
property rights
and economic success 11314
as measure of foundational law 158
prospect theory and decisionmaking 77
PSLRA (Private Securities Litigation
Reform Act) 15, 1617, 140
psychology and decisionmaking, see
behavioral decision theory
public companies, costs 645
Public Company Accounting Oversight
Board (PCAOB) 209
public enforcement of securities laws
1812
Putnam, R. 29, 36
quality of management, measurement
164
racism in transactions 367
Raghundun, K. 214
Rao, P.K. 57
rational choice 223
rational ignorance 712
and fraud 989
reference dependent utility 77
regret aversion 73
and insider trading 195
regulation, competitive, see competitive
regulation
relational contracts 30
relational xenophobia of trust 367
relationship investing, East Asian
economies 35
religious culture, influence on law 156
representativeness heuristic, and
decisionmaking 74
reputational capital loss, Enron 867
reputational constraint, stockbrokers
934
restrictive legal rules 89
Ribstein, L.E. 52, 81, 99
Ridley, M. 30
right to sue, minority shareholders
1267
risky shift 76
Roberts, J. 36
Index
Roe, M. 1878
Romano, R. 202, 207, 21314
rule of law, factor analysis 175
Sale, H.A. 100
salience of oral communication, and
fraud 100
Sarbanes-Oxley Act (SOX) 1819, 59,
92, 128, 1367, 20816
SEC, see Securities Exchange
Commission
SEC v. Texas Gulf Sulphur Co. 192
Securities Act 1516, 136
fraud provisions 140, 197
and return on investment 5960
Securities Exchange Act 1618, 1367
fraud provisions 140, 197
and insider trading 142
and mandatory disclosure 60
Securities Exchange Commission
(SEC) 2, 16, 1023, 182
securities law 8, 1519
America, see America, securities law
analysis of variables 1724
and acquisitions 61
and behavioral decision theory
93101
benefits 5963
costs 645
development 12947
economics of 5163
effect of public enforcement 1812
factor analysis 176, 180
and financial development 1534,
176, 18082, 186
fraud provisions 20, 546
government role 1013
and network externalities 57
studies 5963, 1534
valuation 187
variables 16061
Securities Litigation Uniform
Standards Act (SLUSA) 15,
1617
self-serving bias 72
and auditor failure 88
separate legal identity, corporations
11819
shareholder protection 1257
effect on company value 153
229
Shavell, S. 4
Shleifer, A. 81
Simon, H. 72
Sloan, L. 136
Smith, A. 123
social norms and corporate disclosure
96
social welfare, effect of financial
markets 6
South Sea Bubble 132
SOX, see Sarbanes-Oxley Act
state law 910
securities regulation 6061, 2027
status quo bias
and contract law 834
and corporate disclosure 956
and decisionmaking 78
and fraud protection 100
stock issuers, opportunism 40
stockbrokers and behavioral decision
theory 934
Stout, L.A. 90, 9091, 118
sunk cost effects and decisionmaking
78
sunk costs, private intermediaries
423
takeovers, regulation 1437
Talley, E. 202
Taylor, M. 2930
tender offer regulation, Williams Act
17
Thaler, R.H. 80
time delay traps and decisionmaking
789
tort law development 11416
transaction costs
and exchange competition 208
and insider trading 194
and law 22
transactions
effect of law 379
monitoring, private intermediaries
3944
and trust 289
trust
and basic law 2931
and commercial transactions 289,
845
and corporate governance 90
230
effect of law 3146, 85
and investment contracts 31
Tversky, A. 71, 77, 81
Index
Vishny, R. 81
voluntary disclosure 534
voting rights, minority shareholders
1256
United Kingdom
takeover regulation 146
see also England
underground economy 11
undue optimism
and auditor failure 878
and decisionmaking 734
and fraud protection 99
USA, see America
Zervos, S. 56
Welle, E. 103
Williams Act 17, 59, 144
Williamson, O. 38
World Bank studies 1545
World Competitiveness Report (WCR)
159