On the Heavens
By Aristotle
3.5/5
()
About this ebook
Aristotle
Aristotle was an ancient Greek philosopher and scientist whose works have profoundly influenced philosophical discourse and scientific investigation from the later Greek period through to modern times. A student of Plato, Aristotle’s writings cover such disparate topics as physics, zoology, logic, aesthetics, and politics, and as one of the earliest proponents of empiricism, Aristotle advanced the belief that people’s knowledge is based on their perceptions. In addition to his own research and writings, Aristotle served as tutor to Alexander the Great, and established a library at the Lyceum. Although it is believed that only a small fraction of his original writings have survived, works such as The Art of Rhetoric, Nicomachean Ethics, Poetics, and Metaphysics have preserved Aristotle’s legacy and influence through the ages.
Read more from Aristotle
The Basic Works of Aristotle Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Aristotle's Politics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAristotle's Art of Rhetoric Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Art Of Rhetoric Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Yale Required Reading - Collected Works (Vol. 1) Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Nichomachean Ethics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOrganon Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsRhetoric: With linked Table of Contents Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Tell a Story: An Ancient Guide to the Art of Storytelling for Writers and Readers Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Art of Rhetoric Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsAristotle: Complete Works (Golden Deer Classics) Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPocket Aristotle Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Related to On the Heavens
Titles in the series (100)
Demons Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5This Side of Paradise Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsTales of Dostoyevsky Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Narrative of Arthur Gordon Pym Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsStories of Leo Tolstoy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Beautiful and Damned Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Moneychangers Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSchiller's Poems Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSchiller's Poems Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Insulted and Humiliated Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Deluge Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPoems by Emily Dickinson Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSchiller's Poems Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSentimental Education Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Crocodile Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5The Gold-Bug and Other Stories Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Deluge Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsSentimental Education Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsFlappers and Philosophers Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe New Accelerator Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Tales From The Jazz Age Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPoems by Emily Dickinson Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsPoems by Emily Dickinson Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsDon Quixote Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5King Midas: A Romance Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsLigeia and Other Stories Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMadame Bovary Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsComplete Poems by Emily Dickinson Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe History of Mr. Polly Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5A Raw Youth Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Related ebooks
Fundamental Aristotle: A Practical Guide to the Physics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOn Sense and the Sensible Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Posterior Analytics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMetaphysics Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Timaeus Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato's "Letters": The Political Challenges of the Philosophic Life Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsMarriage In Free Society Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOn the Soul Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5An Introduction to Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe World as Will and Idea Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsWelfare and Rational Care Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Karman: A Brief Treatise on Action, Guilt, and Gesture Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsOn Benefits: (De Beneficiis) Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato's Phaedo Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsTopics Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Hegel's Philosophy of Mind Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsReligion Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Metaphysics Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Parmenides: "Death is not the worst that can happen to men" Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5THE COMPLETE WORKS OF PLATO: The Republic, Symposium, Apology, Phaedrus, Laws, Crito, Phaedo, Timaeus, Meno, Euthyphro, Gorgias Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Philosophy of Right & The Philosophy of Law: Hegel's Views on Legal, Moral, Social & Political Philosophy Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsEssential Aristotle Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsTHE CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Problem of Truth Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratingsThe Basis of Morality Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato's Theory of Knowledge: The Theaetetus and the Sophist Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Advancement of Learning Rating: 3 out of 5 stars3/5Xenophon's Socratic Education: Reason, Religion, and the Limits of Politics Rating: 0 out of 5 stars0 ratings
Philosophy For You
Plato and a Platypus Walk Into a Bar...: Understanding Philosophy Through Jokes Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sun Tzu's The Art of War: Bilingual Edition Complete Chinese and English Text Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Boy, the Mole, the Fox and the Horse Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Source: The Secrets of the Universe, the Science of the Brain Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Tao Te Ching: A New English Version Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Art of War Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Dictionary of Obscure Sorrows Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Meditations: Complete and Unabridged Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Meditations of Marcus Aurelius Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5The Four Loves Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Sapiens: A Brief History of Humankind Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Beyond Good and Evil Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Plato's Republic Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Courage to Be Happy: Discover the Power of Positive Psychology and Choose Happiness Every Day Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Little Book of Hygge: Danish Secrets to Happy Living Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Be Here Now Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5How to Think Like a Roman Emperor: The Stoic Philosophy of Marcus Aurelius Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Loving Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Inward Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Republic by Plato Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5Experiencing God (2021 Edition): Knowing and Doing the Will of God Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Egyptian Book of the Dead: The Complete Papyrus of Ani Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5How to Be Perfect: The Correct Answer to Every Moral Question Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Art of Communicating Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5The Denial of Death Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5How to Pray: Reflections and Essays Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5No Man Is an Island Rating: 4 out of 5 stars4/5
Reviews for On the Heavens
10 ratings2 reviews
- Rating: 5 out of 5 stars5/5Even if I didn't think this was great reading (and I do) it would be an essential book for the powerful influence (some would say stranglehold, and say it justly) it had on culture and science for two millenia. I doubt Aristotle would have agreed to becoming dogma.
- Rating: 2 out of 5 stars2/5A fairly straightforward Aristotelian text. I felt it wasn't as great as some of his others.
Book preview
On the Heavens - Aristotle
Aristotle
On the Heavens
Published by The Big Nest
This edition first published in 2016
Copyright © 2016 The Big Nest
All Rights Reserve
ISBN: 9781911495055
Contents
BOOK I
BOOK II
BOOK III
BOOK IV
BOOK I
Part 1
The science which has to do with nature clearly concerns itself for the most part with bodies and magnitudes and their properties and movements, but also with the principles of this sort of substance, as many as they may be. For of things constituted by nature some are bodies and magnitudes, some possess body and magnitude, and some are principles of things which possess these. Now a continuum is that which is divisible into parts always capable of subdivision, and a body is that which is every way divisible. A magnitude if divisible one way is a line, if two ways a surface, and if three a body. Beyond these there is no other magnitude, because the three dimensions are all that there are, and that which is divisible in three directions is divisible in all. For, as the Pythagoreans say, the world and all that is in it is determined by the number three, since beginning and middle and end give the number of an ‘all’, and the number they give is the triad. And so, having taken these three from nature as (so to speak) laws of it, we make further use of the number three in the worship of the Gods. Further, we use the terms in practice in this way. Of two things, or men, we say ‘both’, but not ‘all’: three is the first number to which the term ‘all’ has been appropriated. And in this, as we have said, we do but follow the lead which nature gives. Therefore, since ‘every’ and ‘all’ and ‘complete’ do not differ from one another in respect of form, but only, if at all, in their matter and in that to which they are applied, body alone among magnitudes can be complete. For it alone is determined by the three dimensions, that is, is an ‘all’. But if it is divisible in three dimensions it is every way divisible, while the other magnitudes are divisible in one dimension or in two alone: for the divisibility and continuity of magnitudes depend upon the number of the dimensions, one sort being continuous in one direction, another in two, another in all. All magnitudes, then, which are divisible are also continuous. Whether we can also say that whatever is continuous is divisible does not yet, on our present grounds, appear. One thing, however, is clear. We cannot pass beyond body to a further kind, as we passed from length to surface, and from surface to body. For if we could, it would cease to be true that body is complete magnitude. We could pass beyond it only in virtue of a defect in it; and that which is complete cannot be defective, since it has being in every respect. Now bodies which are classed as parts of the whole are each complete according to our formula, since each possesses every dimension. But each is determined relatively to that part which is next to it by contact, for which reason each of them is in a sense many bodies. But the whole of which they are parts must necessarily be complete, and thus, in accordance with the meaning of the word, have being, not in some respect only, but in every respect.
Part 2
The question as to the nature of the whole, whether it is infinite in size or limited in its total mass, is a matter for subsequent inquiry. We will now speak of those parts of the whole which are specifically distinct. Let us take this as our starting-point. All natural bodies and magnitudes we hold to be, as such, capable of locomotion; for nature, we say, is their principle of movement. But all movement that is in place, all locomotion, as we term it, is either straight or circular or a combination of these two, which are the only simple movements. And the reason of this is that these two, the straight and the circular line, are the only simple magnitudes. Now revolution about the centre is circular motion, while the upward and downward movements are in a straight line, ‘upward’ meaning motion away from the centre, and ‘downward’ motion towards it. All simple motion, then, must be motion either away from or towards or about the centre. This seems to be in exact accord with what we said above: as body found its completion in three dimensions, so its movement completes itself in three forms.
Bodies are either simple or compounded of such; and by simple bodies I mean those which possess a principle of movement in their own nature, such as fire and earth with their kinds, and whatever is akin to them. Necessarily, then, movements also will be either simple or in some sort compound-simple in the case of the simple bodies, compound in that of the composite-and in the latter case the motion will be that of the simple body which prevails in the composition. Supposing, then, that there is such a thing as simple movement, and that circular movement is an instance of it, and that both movement of a simple body is simple and simple movement is of a simple body (for if it is movement of a compound it will be in virtue of a prevailing simple element), then there must necessarily be some simple body which revolves naturally and in virtue of its own nature with a circular movement. By constraint, of course, it may be brought to move with the motion of something else different from itself, but it cannot so move naturally, since there is one sort of movement natural to each of the simple bodies. Again, if the unnatural movement is the contrary of the natural and a thing can have no more than one contrary, it will follow that circular movement, being a simple motion, must be unnatural, if it is not natural, to the body moved. If then (1) the body, whose movement is circular, is fire or some other element, its natural motion must be the contrary of the circular motion. But a single thing has a single contrary; and upward and downward motion are the contraries of one another. If, on the other hand, (2) the body moving with this circular motion which is unnatural to it is something different from the elements, there will be some other motion which is natural to it. But this cannot be. For if the natural motion is upward, it will be fire or air, and if downward, water or earth. Further, this circular motion is necessarily primary. For the perfect is naturally prior to the imperfect, and the circle is a perfect thing. This cannot be said of any straight line:-not of an infinite line; for, if it were perfect, it would have a limit and an end: nor of any finite line; for in every case there is something beyond it, since any finite line can be extended. And so, since the prior movement belongs to the body which naturally prior, and circular movement is prior to straight, and movement in a straight line belongs to simple bodies-fire moving straight upward and earthy bodies straight downward towards the centre-since this is so, it follows that circular movement also must be the movement of some simple body. For the movement of composite bodies is, as we said, determined by that simple body which preponderates in the composition. These premises clearly give the conclusion that there is in nature some bodily substance other than the formations we know, prior to them all and more divine than they. But it may also be proved as follows. We may take it that all movement is either natural or unnatural, and that the movement which is unnatural to one body is natural to another-as, for instance, is the case with the upward and downward movements, which are natural and unnatural to fire and earth respectively. It necessarily follows that circular movement, being unnatural to these bodies, is the natural movement of some other. Further, if, on the one hand, circular movement is natural to something, it must surely be some simple and primary body which is ordained to move with a natural circular motion, as fire is ordained to fly up and earth down. If, on the other hand, the movement of the rotating bodies about the centre is unnatural, it would be remarkable and indeed quite inconceivable that this movement alone should be continuous and eternal, being nevertheless contrary to nature. At any rate the evidence of all other cases goes to show that it is the unnatural which quickest passes away. And so, if, as some say, the body so moved is fire, this movement is just as unnatural to it as downward movement; for any one can see that fire moves in a straight line away from the centre. On all these grounds, therefore, we may infer with confidence that there is something beyond the bodies that are about us on this earth, different and separate from them; and that the superior glory of its nature is proportionate to its distance from this world of ours.
Part 3
In consequence of what has been said, in part by way of assumption and in part by way of proof, it is clear that not every body either possesses lightness or heaviness. As a preliminary we must explain in what sense we are using the words ‘heavy’ and ‘light’, sufficiently, at least, for our present purpose: we can examine the terms more closely later, when we come to consider their essential nature. Let us then apply the term ‘heavy’ to that which naturally moves towards the centre, and ‘light’ to that which moves naturally away from the centre. The heaviest thing will be that which sinks to the bottom of all things that move downward, and the lightest that which rises to the surface of everything that moves upward. Now, necessarily, everything which moves either up or down possesses lightness or heaviness or both-but not both relatively to the same thing: for things are heavy and light relatively to one another; air, for instance, is light relatively to water, and water light relatively to earth. The body, then, which moves in a circle cannot possibly possess either heaviness or lightness. For neither naturally nor unnaturally can it move either towards or away from the centre. Movement in a straight line certainly does not belong to it naturally, since one sort of movement is, as we saw, appropriate to each simple body, and so we should be compelled to identify it with one of the bodies which move in this way. Suppose, then, that the movement is unnatural. In that case, if it is the downward movement which is unnatural, the upward movement will be natural; and if it is the upward which is unnatural, the downward will be natural. For we decided that of contrary movements, if the one is unnatural to anything, the other will be natural to it. But since the natural movement of the whole and of its part of earth, for instance, as a whole and of a small clod-have one and the same direction, it results, in the first place, that this body can possess no lightness or heaviness at all (for that would mean that it could move by its own nature either from or towards the centre, which, as we know, is impossible); and, secondly, that it cannot possibly move in the way of locomotion by being forced violently aside in an upward or downward direction. For neither naturally nor unnaturally can it move with any other motion but its own, either itself or any part of it, since the reasoning which applies to