[go: up one dir, main page]

Academia.eduAcademia.edu

On the History of the Greek kosmos

1998, Harvard Studies in Classical Philology

Department of the Classics, Harvard University On the History of the Greek κοσμοσ Author(s): Aryeh Finkelberg Reviewed work(s): Source: Harvard Studies in Classical Philology, Vol. 98 (1998), pp. 103-136 Published by: Department of the Classics, Harvard University Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/311339 . Accessed: 29/09/2012 12:34 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. . Department of the Classics, Harvard University is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Harvard Studies in Classical Philology. http://www.jstor.org ON THE HISTORYOF THE GREEKKOXMOX1 ARYEH FINKELBERG Anaximander'sidea of the eternal power of Dike ruling natural phenomenaimplies the idea of a cosmos ... Thereforewe arejustified in describinghis conception of the universeas the spiritualdiscovery of the cosmos ... The idea of a cosmos ... conveniently symbolizes the whole influence of early natural philosophy upon the culture of the Greeks." These much cited words are from WernerJaeger'sessay "The discovery of the world-order,"publishedin 1933 as a partof his monumental Paideia,2 which played a significant role in stimulating the scholarly discussion of the history and meaning of the Greek x6<oto;, but seems to be responsiblealso for some of its essential shortcomings. Jaegersought to accountfor the emergenceof a new vision of the world which was broughtaboutby the Presocraticthinkers. His approachwas conceptual: in discussing the Presocratics' theories he did not argue from their use of xKo~to;,and therefore his conclusions are formally independentof terminologicalconsiderations. Yet in calling the emergence of the new vision of the universe "the discovery of the worldorder,"as well as in having defined it and systematically referredto it as "cosmos," he intimately linked the Presocratics' "spiritualdiscovery" with the term x6'aoto;, which was thus supposed to convey the very essence of this vision; the "idea of a cosmos" turnedout to be the In the subsequent discussion the terminological concept of xKr•to;. word has come to be treated as the acknowledgedPresocraticterm for the new and distinctive vision of the world, so that the ultimate objective of the study has been, not to determine the precise scope of the "... 1 An earlier draft of the first part of this paper was read at the annual meeting of the Israel Society for the Promotionof Classical Studies held at the Haifa Universityon 31 May-1 June 1995. 2 Quoted afterthe English translation:W. Jaeger,Paideia: TheIdeas of GreekCulture, trans.G. Highet (Oxford 1947) 1.160-161. 104 AryehFinkelberg application of the word, but rather-partly tacitly, but mainly explicitly-to explain how the word came to convey the conception of the "cosmos."3Of course, such an approachhas not favored a critical analysis of the evidence. The currentnotion of IxCdoogas "the combinationof order, fitness and beauty"4is the inexhaustiblesource of the scholarlytalk of the Presocratic vision of the universe as a structuredsystem exhibiting the beauty of a perfect arrangement.Unfortunately,the notion is speculative: the association of the derivativesense-"world"-of ic6ago with its other derivativesense "adornment,"and with its primarymeaning, "order,"has never been empirically proved, but is in fact an artificial semantic configuration. According to this logic the use of ix6ito; in the derivativesense of, say, "adornment"must also have preservedits link with the primarysense "order"5and have been closely associated in with the word's other secondarysenses, e.g., "government." x6"too; the sense of "order,"K6xoio;in the sense of "adornment,"and X6aoto; in the sense of "world"are homonymic uses, and the divergentsenses of a word do not produce a cumulative meaning. The vitality of this speculativenotion may be tracedto the mannerof implementation:the lack of evidence is compensated by question-begging speculative 3 The meaning of K?aoiogin the Presocraticswas briefly discussed by K. Reinhardt, Parmenidesund die Geschichteder griechischen Philosophie (Bonn 1916) 174-175; his conclusions were critically assessed by O. Gigon, Untersuchungenzu Heraklit (Leipzig 1935) 52-55. Subsequentto the publicationof Jaeger'sPaideia there came the full-scale as a terminological concept by W. Kranz: "Kosmos als investigations of K6•Ci•o philosophischer Begriff friihgriechischerZeit," Philologus 93 (1938/39) 430-448, and "Kosmos und Mensch in der Vorstellungfrihen Griechentums,"Nachrichten d. Gdtt. Gesellschaftder Wissenschaften,Ph.-hist. KI., 2.7 (1938) 121-161. The Presocraticuses were examined briefly by G. S. Kirk, Heraclitus: The Cosmic Fragments2 (Cambridge 1962; first edition: Cambridge 1954) 311-315 (on which see G. Vlastos's critical comments, "On Heraclitus,"AJP 76 [1955] 344-347) and at length by C. H. Kahn, Anaximanderand the Origins of Greek Cosmology(New York 1960) 219-230. The discussion culminatedin J. Kerschensteiner'scomprehensivestudy Kosmos. QuellenkritischeUnter(Munich 1962). The general uses of K6oatoghave been suchungenzu den Vorsokratikern in surveyed by H. Diller, "Der vorphilosophischeGebrauchvon K6otog;und KOagE~v," Festschrift Bruno Snell (Munich 1956) 47-60, and in the first chapter of Kerschensteiner's Kosmos 4-25. Relevant comments on the uses of Ka~tog; as well as concise summariesof the semanticdevelopmentof the word are found in some otherauthors. 4 W. K. C. Guthrie,A History of Greek Philosophy (Cambridge 1962-1981) 1.208 n. 1. 5 Which obviously is not the case, see, e.g., 11.4.145, or Hdt. 7.31. OntheHistoryof theGreekKOXMOX 105 assumptions,6and a circularway of reasoning runs from the supposed meaning of x6o(togoto an interpretationof the general purportof Presocratictheories, and from these theories to the meaningof xoGtog. While it is clear that we try not to read the later senses of x~oogto into the earlier uses, scholars often take the cosmological application for granted;the typical approachis to take the word at the outset as referring to the world and to construe the text in the light of this assumed meaning. A more critical attitude, adopted by Kirk, led to conclusions greatly differing from the currentviews; Kirk was attacked from the speculative positions7 and his approachcondemned as "too strict and narrow."8It does not, however, seem too strict to demand from those who claim certaintexts to be the first instancesof a new linguistic usage to take on themselves the onus probandi. It seems to me somewhat too liberal to grant conveniently the cosmological application of x6'rto; in a given Presocratictext without seriously checking the possibility of other meanings. The danger of the anachronistic rendering can be avoided only if the exclusive appropriatenessof the cosmological sense or, alternatively,the definiteinappropriatenessof all the other senses of the word may be shown. But when the cosmological applicationof the word in a given text is proved beyond reasonable doubt, it still remains to decide whether it 6 One of the most instructiveexamples is perhapsthe following, Jaeger (above, n. 2) 160: "We do not know whetherAnaximanderhimself used the word cosmos in this connection: it is used by his successor Anaximenes, if the fragmentin which it occurs is correctly attributedto him." This is a cautious and philologically conscious statement.Kahn (above, n. 3) 219: "As Jaeger has put it, the philosophy of Anaximanderrepresents 'the discovery of the cosmos,' and there is no good reason to suppose that this discovery was ever called by any other name." (Note that Kahndoes not believe that in AnaximenesB 2 the Koa6to; is genuine.) For another,no less conspicuous, example, see the following note. 7 By Vlastos (above, n. 3) 344, 345 n. 19: "[Kirk concludes that] the word Kratog; could only mean 'order,'not 'world,' at this [sc. Heraclitus']time.... I am not ... confident ... that was not used even in sixth century speculationfor 'world' ... the Ko•tog; Milesians would certainlyneed a substantiveby which to refer ... to the world(s) which issue from the arche ... such a need is bound to be met sooner or later, and ... it could be met very early by the use of i6Cogo;since the notion of the world as an orderly arrangementwas, of course, present from the beginning." (Vlastos's more specific argument, ibid. 345-346, against Kirk, namely that HeraclitusB 30 "is evidence that KoG?.og, though it implies, does not just mean, 'order,'for what is in question here is not merely that nobody made the order of the world, but that nobody made this orderlyworld [Vlastos's italics],"regrettablybegs the question.) 8 M. Marcovich,Heraclitus. Editio Maior (Merida 1967) 99. 106 AryehFinkelberg exhibits the usual or contextual meaning of the word. The failure to draw this fundamentallinguistic distinctionhas ensued in the artificial renderingof xo6a`ao;as "world-order,"assumed by scholars to be the transitional meaning between the primary sense "order" and the derivative"world."Yetjust as x6pagLo; used, for example, by Herodotus with referenceto Polycrates' furniture(3.123.1), does not mean "furniture-adornment,"so being used with reference to the world, the word does not acquire the hybrid sense "world-order."The conventional as "world-order"is to be discarded,and the word renderingof x6a•Lo; is to be rendered as either "order"or "world"dependingon whetherthe use is occasional, and thereforethe sense "world"is only contextual,or regular,and hence the meaningis usual.9It goes without saying thatthe should not be admitted unless the usual meaning "world"of x6a•Lo; character of the use can be argued. systematic This would seem to call into question the currentscholarly consensus. In what follows I propose a reexaminationof evidence on more critical grounds. I hope to show that a strict and open-mindedscrutiny of evidence, free of speculative presuppositions,leads to conclusions considerablydifferentfrom the familiarpicture. I In describing Socrates' philosophical interests at Memorabilia 1.1.11, Xenophon says: "he did not even discuss, as most others, the natureof all things, inquiringinto how what the men of wisdom call the runs and by what necessities each of the heavenly phenomena xoa6oo takes place." These words indicate that by the time they were written was already put to terminological use, but for Xenophon the •6•Loowas still a term peculiar technical idiom of a definite provenance,and the commentatorsgenerally agree that the usage must have been relatively new.10 If, for the purposeof the argument,we assume the earliest date of Memorabilia 1.1-2, viz. soon after the attack against Socrates published by Polycrates in 393/2 B.C., still the testimony remains incompatiblewith the currentview of the fifth- and even sixth-century 9 Thus, for example, Aristotle's oipav6;, when used with reference to the world, is renderedneitheras "heaven"nor as "world-heaven,"but "world." 10See, among others, Gigon (above, n. 3) 54; Kirk (above, n. 3) 314; Plato Gorgias, ed. E. R. Dodds (Oxford 1959) 308; Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 226 n. 5. OntheHistoryof theGreekKOXMOX 107 terminologicaluse of xdogog. It has been contended that Xenophon's phrase only means "that it is the philosophers who call the world ,doagog, not that they have started doing this fairly recently."" Yet Aristophanes'philosophical parodies demonstratethat until at least the twenties of the fifth century B.C. the Athenian public was well acquainted with contemporaryphilosophical writings, and Socrates' mentioning, in Plato's Apology 26D-E, a drachma as the price of Anaxagoras' book in the Athenian market place, even if ironically exaggerated, shows that the situation was not much different some twenty-five years later.12The fifth-centuryphilosophersaddressedtheir books to the general reader and their phraseology could hardly strike this reader as peculiar.13It has also been suggested that Xenophon's remarkmay have reflectedthe Athenianusage while elsewhere, notably in Ionia, the sense "world"was established much earlier. Yet except Archelaus,all the philosophersactive in fifth-centuryAthens were visitors from abroad, including Ionia. Easy explanations do not work; there must be something wrong with either Xenophon's testimony or, more probably,the currentaccountof the Presocraticusage. The beginning of the terminologicalcareerof xKogo; is traditionally associated with Pythagoras whom, it is generally maintained, Greek doxographycreditedwith using the word as "world." Yet the examination of the testimony hardlywarrantsthis view. We have two principal reports. AMtius2.1.1 (= DK 14, 21): Iua)0odpaxppro; y6axE xTil pt•obvjcThe ordinary Z;v r&)v reptoX~lv6Kaiov EiXrig ao)fo "x6EO.14 0,oov 11Vlastos (above, n. 3) 345; cf. Kahn (above, n. 3) 220; D. Lanza, Anassagora: testimonianzeeframmenti (Florence 1966) 217, ad B 8. 12The Athenianreadermust, then, have been well acquaintedwith Anaxagoras'usage, and thereforeO. Gigon's suggestion, Kommentarzum ersten Buch von XenophonsMemorabilien (Basel 1953) 17, ad loc., that Xenophon's "wise men" may refer to Anaxagoras, is hardlyplausible. 13Therefore Kranz's explanation (above, n. 3) 446-447, that "dem attischen Durchschnittsbuirgerwar noch un 400 Kosmos fiir Weltall ein Ausdruck der Gelehrten,"is ratherhe unconvincing. Besides, Xenophon definitely was not a "Durchschnittsbtirger"; was a literateperson with a wide range of interests, including the philosophical. Kranz's strong contrast between "learnedpeople" and "averagecitizens" seems to be somewhat anachronistic,but at any rate Xenophon did not addresshis writings to citizens who did not readbooks. 14 Photius, Bibl. 440a27, who draws on Stobaeus (see H. Diels, Doxographi Graeci4 [Berlin 1879] 44), glosses i1 z'v 6owv eEptox7 as 6 o'pctvy; and specifies AMtius' rdtit; as the perfection and beauty of the heaven. In Achilles Isag. 129d rz xx&vis a gloss on Stobaeus' 1irOv ~"ov For Achilles' dependence on Stobaeus see Diels, ibid. • Eptoxr. 327a; for his inaccuracyin transcribinghis sources see ibid., 21-26. 108 AryehFinkelberg sense of nrEptox i is "an enclosing, compass," and in its two other occurrencesin AMtiusthe word means "circumference,envelopment."15 This being so, the phrase l r'OvXiov rEptoxi most naturallyrefers to the (outer) heaven.16The other reportis D.L. 8.48 (= Dox. 492; cf. DK 28 A 44): ro'rov [sc. Pythagoras]6'axIopi'v6g ;rlotv ... KaiXtv o1pav(xv Rpfxrov6volitixoatKIdcov Ka xTIvyfiv oxpoyyAyXrjVb 8& OE)opao(To; HIapxpEvi8rl[sc. called the earthspherical], 0;q8E Z•v(ov 'Haiobov xrX. The opposition rbvo5pav6v --,rv yfiv suggests that the sense of the ouipav6; is "heaven"ratherthan "world.""17 The agreement between AMtius'and Diogenes' testimonies makes it likely that they come from a common source, and we have no special reason to question the Theophrasteanprovenanceof the information.18It should however be realized that the reportcannot be taken at face value. What is reportedis a Pythagoreantraditionwhich, we can infer, authorizedthe use of ic"aogo;in the sense of "heaven." Since the attributionof this terminological invention to Pythagorasconforms to the Pythagoreans' routine practice, it is impossible to know how old this use really was. The only historical evidence the reportfurnishes is the use of K61oto; for "heaven"by the Pythagoreansof the last generations. We shall returnto this meaningof the word later. Another reportthat has been adduced to prove the Milesian use of K6coo; in the sense of "world"is a phrase from the Theophrastean 15 [Plut.] Plac. 3.892E (=Diels [above, n. 14] 364a16), cf. LSJ, s.v. nrEptoxii,2; Stob. Ecl. 1.29.1 (= Diels [above, n. 14] 369b26 = DK 68 A 93). 16 Cf. Kranz (above, n. 3) 432 (who however is preparedto go beyond the report, 436-437); U. Hilscher, "Anaximanderand the Beginnings of Greek Philosophy"in D. J. Furley and R. E. Allen eds., Studies in PresocraticPhilosophy (London 1970) 1.297 n. 41 (first published in Hermes 81 [1953] 255-277, 385-417); J. Mansfeld, The Pseudoch. I-II and Greek Philosophy (Assen 1971) 42 6Pio6g&6ov Hippocratic Tract F•ept n. 26. 17Cf. Mansfeld (above, n. 16) 42 n. 26. 18As Gigon (above, n. 3) 54, points out, the reportwould fit with Theophrastus'characteristicinterestin the history of philosophicalterminology.The attributionto Pythagoras of the use of KoLo;ogfor "world"in Achilles' report(see above, n. 14) and in Schol. ov t6; at Hom. ad II. 3.1 (... i7 1ov rtn luv0ay6po Ei'prlyrat)is a result of the deteriorationof the tradition. TheKx••Lov Theophrasteanorigins of AMtius'informationhave for been disputed because the alleged attributionto Pythagorasof the use of xoaCtog the word. "world"does not conform to certainscholars' idea of the terminologicaluse of Thus, for example, Vlastos (above, n. 3) 345 n. 19, questions the attributionbecause this would be too late a date, while Kirk (above, n. 3) 313 and n. 1, 314, because the date would be too early. On the History of the GreekKOXMOX 109 account of Anaximander'sApeiron preservedin Hippolytus (Ref 1.6.1 = DK 12 A 11: tot; oiupavot? icactv and Simpliv a toi; icc'tot; Ev cius (Phys. 24.13 = DK 12 A 9: tot; oiupavo; K•ioov) avdrot; It has been supposed that the locution reflects AnaximanKo~6icoL)g). der's own words,19but the supposition is speculative.20Besides, in the account the pluraloi.pavo" refers to Anaximander'spluralworlds:Hipe vat, v ( auPpaivet yiv(ok toitco ivty pol. ibid., tpbS8E dcV&Stov 41.17 from DK): ?; [sc. t~i1 ro1; (absent Phys. oiUpavoi`;; Simpl. Oat K t Ti ?tv o~paov(v ittrav EFva a1~Epol) e(P t(TV o] X&i6toVIdvrItV cf. Ps.-Plut. Strom. 2 (DK 12 A 10): tob TCetpov yEV eo; e0,yev; ~XV tvExLV OlRtav)1bC Tj ; yeV&e(•o (pavat 'rTv Uoyav aitrav tE K ao ' the toi ij; ti6; tIvo; [sc. Consequently phrase (p0op~x.21 •paE(o•; ( n A &iravTo; &ienipov]y~veioat rol; oiupavol5; (Hippol. ibid.) / yveoOat rol; oiupavo6d;(Simpl. Phys. 24.13) speaks of the generation of worlds from the Apeiron, and hence icai tbv v a(rot; Kctiov / tot; Ev aXrot; 6outou; can scarcely mean other than "and the arrangementsin them." Incidentally,the translationof the ou.pavot as "heavens" would also result in rendering the / as •icogo; K•cogot "arrangement(s)":"the heavens and the arrangement(s)[enclosed] in them." The earliest philosophical text in which cK6ogo; occurs is Anaximenes B 2. Yet the fragmentshows unmistakablesigns of a late rewordingand the genuineness of o~iogo;has, with good reason, come under suspicion.22But even if the word is assumed to be genuine, the 19 Reinhardt (above, n. 3) 175, followed, among others, by Gigon (above, n. 3) 53-54, Kranz(above, n. 3) 433, and Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 29-38. 20 As Kirk (above, n. 3) 312, rightly comments, "thereis no suggestion thatTheophrastus is quoting Anaximander."Cf. Vlastos (above, n. 3) 345 n. 19; Guthrie(above, n. 4) 1.111, and others. 21 Zeller's suggestion, followed by F. M. Cornford,"InnumerableWorldsin Presocratic Philosophy,"CQ 27 (1934) 10-11, Kranz(above, n. 3) 433, and Kahn(above, n. 3) 46-53 (who abrogatedthis interpretationin the Preface to the 1985 reprint),that oljpavot refer to Anaximander's celestial rings, is untenable; cf. Mansfeld (above, n. 16) 45 n. 40; A. Finkelberg,"PluralWorlds in Anaximander,"AJP 115 (1994) 502-504. Kirk (above, n. 3) 312, is correct in pointing out that o-pavc6ois used in the regularPeripateticsense of "world." 22 See K. Reinhardt, Kosmos und Sympathie (Munich 1926) 209-211; cf. Gigon (above, n. 3) 54; and for a more balanced view: Vlastos (above, n. 3) 363 n. 55; G. S. Kirk, J. E. Raven, and M. Schofield, The Presocratic Philosophers (Cambridge 1983) 159; Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 77-83; Guthrie (above, n. 4) 1.131-132; G. Wihrle, Anaximenesaus Milet (Stuttgart1993) 63-66. 110 AryehFinkelberg fact thatits immediatecontext suffereda rewordingmakes the fragment worthless as evidence of Anaximenes' linguistic usage. Another text which for a long time has been referredto as an authenticwitness of a is the first two chaptersof the very early cosmological use of cK6aojo; De tract hebdomadibus.23However, as Mansfeld pseudo-Hippocratic has demonstrated,the entire tract,including the first two chapters,is of a much later date, most probablyfirst century B.C.24The earliest induin the philosophicalcontext is, bitably authenticoccurrenceof cK6aojo; in for the Heraclitus. However then, purposes of the argumentI postthe discussion of Heraclitus' fragmentsuntil we reachconclusions pone in the use of the the firsthalf of the fifth century. word regarding In the extant lines of Parmenides'poem appearstwice, but in B 8.52 exemplifies the both instances are irrelevant:K6aojovnkiov i6oto;S traditionaluse with reference to the order of a narrative,25and icara' in B 4.3 is the epic formulafor "in order,orderly."26 Nevertheio6otov less some critics wish to understandParmenides' icara 6icotaov as "throughoutthe world,"27but whatever sense modem commentators may suggest, the Greek audience must have taken the expression to mean "orderly,"and Parmenidescould not have been unawareof this.28 Of the two extant occurrencesof the word in Empedocles the first is in B 26: 23See Kranz(above, n. 3) 433, Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 54-55, and others. 24For the historyof the discussion of the date of the tractsee the firstchapterof Mansfeld (above, n. 16), esp. 16-30. 25See Diller (above, n. 3) 57; Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 9-10; see also A. H. Coxon, TheFragmentsof Parmenides(Assen 1986) 218. 26Cf. DK 1.232, ad loc.; Kirk (above, n. 3) 313; Diller (above, n. 3) 55; Kerschensteiner (above, n. 3) 119-122; M. Finkelberg, "Homer's View of the Epic Narrative: Some Formulaic Evidence," CP 82 (1987) 135-138; see also L. Tarain,Parmenides (Princeton 1965) 47-48; E. Heitsch, Parmenides (Munich 1974) 147; Coxon (above, n. 25) 189, and others. 27As, for example, G. Calogero, Studi sull' eleatismo (Rome 1932) 22 n. 1; U. H61lscher,Parmenides (Frankfurtam Main 1969) 47; or D. O'Brien in P. Aubenque ed., Etudes sur Parmdnide(Paris 1987) 1.21-22. 28On Parmenides'dependenceon the traditionalepics see W. Jaeger, The Theologyof Early GreekPhilosophers (Oxford 1947) 35-36, 92-96, 104; H. Schwabl, "Zur'Theogonie' bei Parmenidesund Empedokles,"WS 70 (1957) 278-289; id., "Hesiod und Parmenides. Zur Formung des parmenidischenProoimions,"RhM 106 (1963) 134-142; A. P. D. Mourelatos,The Route of Parmenides(New Haven 1970) 6-37; Coxon (above, n. 25) 7-17. On the History of the GreekKOYMOY (1) (2) (3) (4) (5) 111 ev &• Lpt RptcLnogivoto K-1CX0oto, KpwatrOt E•t ei; 0,CX Cccd ciS~ueoat ev gept ai'•f;. ic•d(pO•wt 3tL yp tv acura a'ria, &8 &t' 8e Oeovta ,a,•,(v EOvea ai &ov yivovtat 6vOpornotIre "t •O•Prlpv ei; icore gtvvtDtXotrlitaUVEPX6•,ev' ieva cK6aoov, i (6) •6•ore 69'aow•x' icaora(popoujeoVa ,,x0t, N••i•eo; r Inv 1neeVEpOE (7) eia6icev ev yeVrlltat. gPivto0v'ta Assuming that lines 4-6 are of cosmological ratherthan biological in line 5 does not designate the frame of purportand therefore K•otaog; of the word animal bodies, the rendering depends on whether the "now one refers to the Love into phrase coming together by K6acto;" of the of the unification viz. the elements, intermediaryperiod gradual manifold world, or to the ultimate condition of the perfect unity, viz. the Sphere. Now it is evident that line 7-"until, growing together into one, they [sc. the elements] are subdued and become the whole"29--describesthe ultimate condition of the perfect mixture, and this meaning is furthersupportedby the contrast with the first line of the fragment(Kpaerouaot-1ntvep0e y where the reference is to the ultimate condition of Strife.30But,vrlrat) if line 7 depicts the ultimatecondition ratherthan the intermediaryperiod, lines 5 and 6-"now coming togetherby Love into one K6ago;, // now again being borne apartfrom each other by the hatred of Strife"-must also describe the ultimate conditions, the reigns of Love and of Strife respectively. Consequently the "one icoaCo;o" in line 5 must refer to the perfect mixtureof the four elements, i.e., the Sphere.31The other Empedocleanfragmentin which Kct6og; is found is B 134: 29 Or, alternatively,"become totally subdued,"although J. Bollack, Empidocle 3: Les Origines: commentaire1 (Paris 1969) 131, seems correctin that the translationof to'rn&v as an adverbis contraryto Empedocles' usage, cf. M. R. Wright,Empedocles: TheExtant Fragments(New Haven 1981) 183. 30 The contrast is emphasized and correctly explained by Wright (above, n. 29) 183: ... the roots are 'underneath'in the opposite sense to their prevailing (cf. line 1), because they are not separateand dominantmasses but are in such a mixing ... that none of their characteristicsis visibly distinct." 31Cf. E. Bignone, Empedocle (Turin 1916) 420. Kirk (above, n. 3) 313, if I correctly understandhim, reaches a similar conclusion: "K6atov here means 'group,' or 'arrangement, organism'." J. Bollack, "Sur deux fragments de Parmenide,"REG 70 (1957) 61, argues that the x6Tog; in B 26.5 is not an equivalent of opitpo; og cKXorepig: he adduces as a parallel B 17.7 which, he infers, must indicate the general direction of the 112 AryehFinkelberg y KE(pxX11 1CItc 01)~c x0 XVAPOgie C yuiCOCOicxat, 6UoKXc•6Ot o0 C eV &ctovtot, XC&Rti v(Oxoto oiun6o&0,oi30o, yoiva,oC9•xaviiev9a, itr-i6a (pp v iepi~Jic apwro; •ETC Xo Uioivov, &XX, Kilov O•ml x aCrati sppovriot OavrIa ovxouaa 0 oftv. This descriptionof the spp~ivicpij should be comparedwith Empedocles' portrayal of the Sphere in B 29: oi y7p &cr vxtkoto 6•o ( , oU EToCLa hXlgiot&~ioovrato,// oi~i6Egn, oi~ ooiva( y• yTvvrievt~ , K The fact that the two xxi o oo;g E•rtv acix~. &•XXX&ipaqpo;g rl descriptions are practically identical suggests the identity of their respective subjects-the (ppi"viepi and the Sphere.32Nevertheless Empedocleanscholarsrefrainfrom the identification:takingfor granted that must mean "world,"they conclude thatthe (ppi~viepij must be a•c6o•og god contemporaneouswith the manifold world. Yet Empedocles' belief in a cosmic god contemporaneouswith the world is otherwise unattested, either in the extant fragments or in the doxographical reports,33and the whole idea rests on the rendering of K?ioo;S as "world." However this sense is unnecessary,for, as we have seen, in B 26.5 Empedocles uses the word to designatethe Sphere. This being so, it is obviously preferablenot to renderthe iK6ctog;as "world"and thus to avoid the unnecessary multiplicationof entities assuming an addicosmic developmentratherthan its final stage. Unfortunately,Bollack fails to quote the identical line B 20.2, which would hinder his argument.Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 128, says that since the Sphere is not an ordered structure,Empedocles could not have but this is to beg the question. Besides, the general presumption designatedit as K6YoLo;, that K6oYLo; 8&'OvZ~E necessarilysuggests the idea of an innerstructureis wrong: K•YJog ai zdiv •6riv (Hdt. 7.36.5). 32The more so as both fragmentsbelong to one poem, viz. On Nature. Diels' removal of B 134 to the Katharmoi was, not without reason, called by G. Zuntz, Persephone (Oxford 1971) 218, the abuse of evidence; see Bignone (above, n. 31) 631-649; C. Horna, "Empedocleum,"WS 48 (1930) 3-7; Zuntz, ibid., 214-218; N. van der Ben, TheProem of Empedocles' Peri Physios (Amsterdam1975) 11-15, 33 Kranz(above, n. 3) 443, refers to Sext. 9.127 (= DK 31 B 136), but if Sextus' words have a textual basis in Empedocles, it need not be other than B 134. K. v. Fritz, "NOYX, NOEINand Their Derivativesin Pre-SocraticPhilosophy(ExcludingAnaxagoras).PartI" in A. P. D. Mourelatosed., ThePre-Socratics.A Collection of CriticalEssays2 (Princeton 1993) 62 n. 125, compares the idea of the divine <ppilvsupposedly pervadingthe world with B 110.10, but there is a great distancebetween the unifieddivine mind and the statement that all things severally have intelligence and share in thinking, a view which is relatedto the perceptiveability of the "roots." On the History of the GreekKOWMOI 113 tional, and otherwise unattested, cosmic deity alongside the Sphere, similar to, and yet separatefrom it. Moreover it may be arguedthat if the four "roots"mixed in equal proportionmake blood which is the thought organ in men (B 98; B 105; Theophr.De sensu 10 = DK 31 A 86), the Sphere, which is the perfect mixture of the four elements in equal proportion(B 17.27 seems to state that the elements are of equal bulk), must in its entiretybe a thought organ34which is, of course, the .pp'v iep" of B 134; this must be the ultimate explanationwhy Empedocles "hymns"the Sphere "as god."35The ioagog, throughwhich the qpp1lv"dartswith swift thoughts,"must, then, be the Sphereratherthan the articulatedworld.36But if the K6dogo;is nevertheless admitted to refer to the developed world, the fact that Empedocles uses the word indifferentlyto denote the Sphere of Love and the world would entail the contextualcharacterof the meaning "world"in B 134.5. Anaxagoras B 8: o6 EX(pptorat XXhXhov'rchEv t61vi KdoygJ i to p oiit) t6 cna 'o•iC o06u: noVcIon7at o0h -6 Ogp~tv &iC x•uxpou Simplicius quotes the fragmentas illustrat&an6 Oepgo^. "toi •u•Xpbv ing Anaxagoras'doctrine"in everythinga portion of everything."If he is right, the specification "in the one world" becomes irrelevant37and even misleading, for it suggests that the "inseparability"of things is due, not to their intrinsic nature, but to their belonging to "the one world."38Now the phrase "the things ... are not separatedfrom one another ... neither the hot from the cold nor the cold from the hot" implies that "things"are opposites like the hot and the cold, and therefore these are opposites that cannot be separatedfrom each other.39The phrase 9v -oovi K6ogip, which qualifies t(A, viz. the opposite things, specifies what precisely opposites are meant to be inseparable, and Anaxagoras' illustration-the hot and the cold-suggests that "the one is "the one, the same order"to which complementaryoppoxo•tjog" 34Cf. Wright(above, n. 29) 238. 35 Simpl. De anima 70.17; cf. 68.2 and Phys. 1124.1. 36This would dispense with the anachronisticimmaterialityof the <ppriv,which, on the rendering ic6~ago as "world," scholars are compelled to allow; see, e.g., Reinhardt (above, n. 3) 143; Guthrie(above, n. 4) 2.260, and others. 37 Not mere "beinahepleonastisch"(Gigon [above, n. 3] 53). 38 Lanza (above, n. 11) 217, ad B 8, believes that the phraseconfirmsthe Anaxagorean doctrineof the uniquenessof the world, but does not explain how the supposedreference to this doctrinehere may be pertinentto Anaxagoras'meaning. 39 Schofield (above, n. 22) 371, aptly recalls Heraclitus' doctrineof the unity of opposites. 114 Aryeh Finkelberg sites belong: the things that, like the hot and the cold, in the one array are not separatedfrom one anothernor cut off with an axe.40If so, the sense of the phrase "one K6ctoog"here is precisely the same as in Empedocles26.5-"one arrangement."41 Melissus B 7: (2) ... Eiytxp E&rpototvrat, 6ioilov ov a&vaycrjl "t yi1l c t6 E &q o 6v 6v, yivs 0at ... •fvat, &XX &nt6XXaUOat lrp6aeOv t (3) &XX'o-08& yp lrp6aoiv K6aLo; 6 tEacoo'trljfjvat Gvixgo6v-6 t6Xrat ov ob~iC &n6 oiutre6"il Eov yivertat. Since Melissus' argument is directed against the changeability of 9b~6v and has nothing to do with cosmology, the sense "order,arrangement"of the K6a0io`is obvious: "noris it possible for it [sc. 'b i6v] to be rearranged,for the previously existing order does not perish, nor a nonexisting one come into being."42It seems evident that, if by the time of the composition of this text K6aogo;was alreadya currentterm for "world,"its use in the argument could mislead the reader into thinking that Melissus argues the unchangeabilityof the world.43Yet he does not seem to have consid40 Vlastos (above, n. 3) 345, objects to Kirk's construal(above, n. 3) 313, of Anaxagoas "the one group or category ... probably,the continuumformed by ras' "one is indeed a continuum,but a sineach pairio6atog" of opposites":". .. his [Anaxagoras']K6~oCtog gle one wherein 'everythinghas a portion of everything,'not the many continua of his multiple pairs of opposites, which would not be 'one world"' [Vlastos's italics]. Unfortunately,the argumentis a petitio principii, but apartfrom this Schofield (above, n. 22) 371, must be right in that the continuaof opposites were regardedby Anaxagoras"as providing the best illustrationof his general theory that 'in everything there is a portion of everything'." is 41 Euripidesfr. 910 (= DK 59 A 30: dav~r&ooti0cxOopav cotov &ayrjp•v) (<pi6aJE•g thoughtto be an echo of Anaxagoras'teaching. Kahn(above, n. 3) 220, says thatIc60otog here is an instance of the "philosophical"use of the word in the fifth century. Yet the phrasenot only allows the rendering"order,"it even suggests it: "perceivingthe unaging world of deathlessnature"does not make good sense. 42Reinhardt(above, n. 3) 174, contended that ico6atoomeans here "einen bestimmten Zustand,eine Phase dieser Welt ..." The construaldisregardsthe purportof Melissus' argumentand was rightly dismissed by Gigon (above, n. 3) 52; cf. Kirk (above, n. 3) 313; Vlastos (above, n. 3) 345; Guthrie(above, n. 4) 2.115; Schofield (above, n. 22) 396, and others. 43 As it has misled some critics (notablyH. Diller, "Die philosophiegeschichtlicheStellung des Diogenes von Apollonia,"Hermes 76 [1941] 365-366; cf. Kahn [above, n. 3] 229) into thinking that Melissus may have attackedthe idea of the changeabilityof the world maintainedby contemporaneousphilosophers. Now, regardless of whether these philosopherscalled the world ico6atog,it seems clear enough that whateverMelissus may intend to show to be unchangeable,he argues the impossibility of its alterationqua rt (= arrangement)of rb 6v that he demonstratesto be unalterd6v,and it is the •c6aJto able. On the History of the GreekKOXMOX 115 ered the possibility that his audience could hesitate to refer 6 K66ogo;6 to rbnup6~0(v 6v, for otherwisehe most probablywould pp6e0ev ~vhv the use have avoided of the word or would have specified it as 6 r t cp6oaOev 6oago;i6vrowvor d6vro;---cf. ••ralooGkrOVMv Ed6vzov in the next sentence.44 In all the instances examined thus far Kc60to;seems to be invariably used in the traditional sense "order,""arrangement."Only in one occurrence, at Empedocles B 134.5, the word may be, though not too likely, taken as applying to the world. If this is indeed Empedocles' referencehere,juxtaposed to the applicationof ICoGxo;to the Sphereat B 26.5, it attests to the occasional characterof the use and the ensuing contextual characterof the sense "world." Considering also that the established sense "world"most probablywould precludeMelissus' use of the word in his argument,we may infer that by the middle of the fifth century the word still did not acquire the cosmological sense. With this conclusion in mind we may turn now to Heraclitus. In his occurs in B 30, 89, and 124, though only in B 30 its fragments K6GJaoo is authenticity unquestionable.45 B 30: v o0ME (r6voe), a-rbyv a rv, o0re t? K•x6oov axx' t6v tadv Oet• i jv at fo delicai oativ ai MvOpnov inoiiEsv, *inp ai&,oov, gtpa icta &tnooe~vv-iegvovgrpa. The fragmentis gend&iro6gevov with reference erally held to be the first instance of the use of to the world, but this is not at all certain, fori6cotoa the reference to the ordered alterations of fire is equally possible: "This order[ed sequence],46the same of all [things], did none of gods or men make, but it ever was and is and shall be: everliving fire, kindling in measures and extinguishing in measures." Theoretically speaking, B 30 may be an instance of (a) the usual meaning "world,"(b) the contextualmeane?w Et 6vrowV, 6vrov Ei•l, Mullach; 44MS; aooCrLov xv CE•aiKOG•tjrEi* ioWV Heidel. 45 The word is found also in B 75, but Diels's assessment of it as a fragment,disputed by Reinhardt(above, n. 3) 194 n. 2, has been generally abandoned,see Gigon (above, n. 3) 52; Kirk (above, n. 3) 312-313; Marcovich (above, n. 8) 10; J. Bollack and H. Wismann, Hiraclite ou la Separation (Paris 1972) 234, C. H. Kahn, The Art and Thoughtof Heraclitus (Cambridge1979) 216, and others. 46 "Orderedsequence, series" is one of the most fundamental and well-established meanings of ic6'tog in Homer and afterwards, as for instance, in II. 24.622, Od. 13.76-77, or Hdt. 8.67; the same sense the word has in the epic formula in iact•r K6tov application to song. For further examples see Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 5-24; cf. Kranz(above, n. 3) 430-431. 116 Aryeh Finkelberg ing "world,"or (c) the usual meaning "order."Option (a) is hardlycompatible with our conclusion thateven some fifty years later "world"was not the usual meaning of Kop`og either in the Greek West (Empedocles) or, what is especially significant,in Ionia (Anaxagoras,Melissus). The decision is, then, between (b) and (c), and reasons in favor of the latteroption seem to be more cogent. If by Heraclituswished to refer to the orderof the world, he K•6itog would have had to clarify this because, as we have seen, this was not a customaryapplicationof the word. It has been repeatedlyarguedthat •SE specifies the K6oatogas that very order which we see aroundus, i.e., the orderof the world.47However since beside its deictic sense "8E has another principal meaning, that of referring forward, Heraclitus' supposed specification must have been misleading. Habituallytaking in the general sense of "order,"and naturallylooking for its K6ctgog specificationfirst of all in the text itself, Heraclitus'readerwould readvov pov pa the suitable ily find in &wr6A'gevov ptgtpa Iai &roope3vvCTP of the and of reference word consequentlywould understandthe point the to the orderedalterationsof as 66E proleptic, viz. relating fire. In other words, Heraclitus'x•6oog contemporariescould hardly understand 6og`og;as "the order of the world"; rather they would have understood it as "the order of the fire's kindling and extinguishing." Further, Heraclitean scholars regularly mistranslate -rv antbyv as "the same for all,"48because "this world [or as the word is &RntVtOWV artificiallyrendered,"world-order"],the same of all [things]"does not make sense.49But the phrase"thisorder,the same of all [things]"does, portrayingas it does fire's regularalterationsas changes of the global scale. Finally, the reference to the world would turn the phrase "none of gods or men made" into the denial of the view that the world was 47 Kirk (above, n. 3) 314; cf. J. Burnet,Early GreekPhilosophy4 (London 1930) 162; Reinhardt(above, n. 3) 175-176; Kranz(above, n. 3) 441, and others. 48Reinhardt(above, n. 3) 170 n. 1, followed by Kirk(above, n. 3) 308-309, and others, as a gloss. excises rov aurbyv •nicvryov 49 One may however wonder whether "this world-order,the same for all" is better. as the masculine and understands"one Vlastos (above, n. 3) 346-347, takes the nctivryov from "privatex6atCot"of those asleep (B of the waking as distinct and common oca•gog" 89). Apartfrom the questionableauthenticityof Kicago; in B 89, its grammardiffers from that of B 30. When the "common"is related to men, as in B 89 and also in B 113, the idea is conveyed by the dative ("the common [binding]for everybody"),but when it is related to things, as in B 114, by the genitive ("the common [principle]of everything"), and it is the latterconstructionwhich is found in B 30. OntheHistoryof theGreekKOXMO1 117 brought into existence by a creator, an idea which no Greek (at least until Plato's Timaeus)held, and the solemn rejection of which would have soundedto Heraclitus'audiencepointless and grotesque.50But the assertionthat the orderof fire's alterationswas not broughtaboutby an extraneous agent is an informativestatementof the self-sufficiency of cosmic fire.51Considering all this, the fragment seems to be properly understood as speaking of the ordered eternal sequence of the fire's measuredalterations,which is also the sequence of all things; the idea thus conveyed is comparablewith Anaximander's i toi Xpbpvou tr;tq (B 1).52 B 89: 6 'Hpdlhxt T6 (Plat rtot;~i yprlYop6atvwia ti Kotvbv 'vo IOTOV i'tov onooUpE(PEGOtt. dEvat, t(v 8F Kol VotltvoV Ev c(ojlov o Diels accepted the first clause and the word i'tov in the second one, but, as Gigon pointed out, icotvov instead of 4,v6v in the first clause indicates that it also underwenta rewording.53This casts doubt on the genuineness of co'ato;, which may well be a gloss. And there can be little doubt that it is indeed a gloss: the word means "one's world,"54 but such a metaphoricaluse presupposes the usual meaning "world," which was not the case even half a centurylater. B 124: &ronep odapla EiKfi KEXU?xWvoV 6 q(PTGV K0h1ZGto;, 'HpdlKhtTo, [6] IX6opto;.If K6~6to;is assumed to be a part of the quotation, and if Diels's emendation adppta for adp4 of the MS is accepted, then Heraclitus'contrastwould be between a randomheap of sweepings and the most beautiful co6ijto;. Both the Theophrastean context and the intrinsic meaning of the opposition suggest that the 50 The difficulty is concisely stated by G. E. R. Lloyd, Polarity and Analogy (Cambridge 1971) 273 n. 3: "It is strikingthat in Fr. 30 Heraclitusdenies that the world-order is the productof 'any god or mortal' ... This is such an explicit denial that it looks as if it is directed against some specific myth or theory. Yet we have considerabledifficulty in identifyingthis with any certaintyfrom our availableevidence." 51 This notion was reportedby Theophrastus,as reflected in a number of dependent accounts in which the fire's kindling and extinguishing are said to be KxtrXdtvx Ei••ap?tavrlv &vdyXrv(Simpl. Phys. 22.33 = DK 22 A 5) or simply Eitapkvxprlv (D.L. K•a' = 9.8; Aet. 1.7.22; 1.27.1; 1.28.1 DK 22 A 1, 8), cf. HeraclitusB 137. 52On the synonymy of ro'atog;and rd(t; see Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 11 and n. 5, 12 and n. 1, 17 n. 1. 53Gigon (above, n. 3) 10; cf. Kirk (above, n. 3) 63-64; Marcovich (above, n. 8) 100; Kahn(above, n. 45) 104, T. M. Robinson,Heraclitus (Toronto1987) 138. 54 Or, as Kirk(above, n. 3) 63, puts it, "thesum of one's experience";cf. Kranz(above, n. 3) 441. 118 AryehFinkelberg contrastturns on the idea of order;55the meaning of ~c6opo; is, then, "order,"but it remains unclear whether the word is used absolutely or with reference to the world, thus exhibiting the contextual sense of "world." If the cosmological context of Theophrastus'quotation is taken as indicative of the similar purportof Heraclitus' saying, the latter may have been (though not necessarily) the case, but Theophrastus cites the phrase for a rhetorical effect and therefore his context is indecisive.56The only secure conclusion seems, then, to be thatK16opo; is employed here in its usual sense of "order";whetheror not the word was used with reference to the world must remain undecided. Yet in speculatingon the possibilities one should rememberthat it would not be particularlydiscriminatingto postulate a contextual sense in ignorance of the context. It may also be observed that while the idea of orderlinessis pivotal in the supposedlyHeracliteanuse of K6copo;in B 124, in its cosmological application, as exemplified in Empedocles B 134.5 and B 29.5, the word does not distinctivelysuggest this idea. We turn now to the philosophersof the second half of the fifth century. The relevant fragments are those of Diogenes of Apollonia and Democritus.57 Diogenes B 2: aco t "ivth•sCUav E•ToV r heoei &p tx svuxa&7et mtdvayvra 6oKEt andv.icde w trepototh doorXpO vi• i0x•oC ocnr6o* a•rjat "tohe'o 0at P y XtX v qv, rqic ca, 5•op icai &tIp Kca (p E6v"tO )t KOCYJO) eo6vta Et0e x 6)a oa pauveEat v t Ko•do •6vxa, Ei 'iYp a i V'r J1?) iaci i -v , i'trpov 8v TTf pqoat, 'Sepovtoi &rtEpo toYPo•vtt '6 a)Ct&66v e'r"tErMtE RoXaXc; ~xa &'trepotoi'ro, o68api4 o 9te t(doayeaOt a&XXfXot•186varo K•cX. The emphatic repetition"in this I6o'Jo;9"may seem to suggest a conand indeed the doxographical trastwith some other ico1ao; or K6coraot, 55Cf. Gigon (above, n. 3) 52; Marcovich(above, n. 8) 550. 56Cf Kranz(above, n. 3) 440-441; H. Frainkel,"AThoughtPatternin Heraclitus,"AJP 59 (1938) 319; Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 97 and n. 2. 57In the fragmentswhich came to us under the name of Philolaus (whose floruit may be as late as c. 400 B.C.,see C. A. Huffman,Philolaus of Croton[Cambridge1993] 1-6), ic6oato in the sense "world"is quite frequent.Since, however, the authenticityof these fragmentsis controversial,it would be more prudentto reach our conclusions independently of these texts and to check their use of the word as against the conclusions arrived at. OntheHistoryof theGreekKOXMOX 119 traditionascribes to Diogenes the belief in a pluralityof worlds.58Now Diogenes Laertiusadduces the first sentence of Diogenes' book (B 1): "I believe that at the beginning of any accountthe authorought to make his starting point indisputable .. ." The opening words of B 2 ("my opinion, in sum, is ...") and its general content suggest that the fragment is such an "indisputablestartingpoint," and indeed Simplicius, who cites it, says that it directly followed the proem. Consequently even if a few sentences between B 1 and B 2 are missing, it seems obvious enough that they were not dedicatedto the theory of pluralworlds. From the philosophical point of view as well the contrastbetween our world and other worlds is scarcely possible here, for the principle Diogenes is formulatingis universal. It follows that on the assumptionof the established sense "world"for -6Ko?to;,the emphatically repeated demonstrativemust be pointless. Further,if ic60go; means "world," Diogenes' wording appears intolerably and surprisingly pleonastic, 'r av [t•Fi6] T0 KG[(1o comparedwith his usually succinct style: ei y'&p w wad pwpi i p ii3 Kid 6,raxx [oa qxpaiveE6v'tx[viv], yi iS' i t6t pp Rp -drKIo? 'rat Ev eitou~rov rt ix•h. Finally, the phrase rx I6vrxo], Y~o•e av 'r5Fe ( r tv '06e 6avrao vuv suggests a contrastwith rx& K0o•JL• if is rendered as "world,"yields k6vtxa7tp~oev, which, Kr6t~o) K•doog the between the present and previously patently impertinentopposition existing componentsof the world. Diogenes' opposition is between the apparentlymanifold and essentially unified nature of things,59and the temporal specification of the manifold as "existing now" habitually puts this metaphysicalcontrast on the cosmogonical plane; therefore the implied ra or rather t6 bv (8oe ) ic6ct'o ~bv tp6o0ev is unified natureitself, viz. the arche.60 roapog;,then, must refer to the general arrangementof things,61irrespective of whether this is the articulatedworld or the uniform arche. The latter application is exemplified by Empedocles' use of KcJopog; with referenceto the uniform Sphere, and Melissus' use with reference to homogeneous being; if in Empedocles B 134.5 KoJCpog is assumedto refer to the world, Diogenes' usage would exactly parallelEmpedocles' in that the word would apply to both the uniform arche (which is 58D.L. 9.57; Ps.-Plut. Strom.12 (= DK 64 A 1, 6), etc. 59So correctlyKerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 178. 60Cf. Reinhardt (above, n. 3) 174. 61Cf. Kirk(above, n. 313. 3) 120 AryehFinkelberg comparable with the homogeneous Sphere) and the differentiated world. The emphaticallyrepeateddemonstrativeand the list, otherwise pleonastic, of the world components are thus intended to specify the sense "arrangement"of Ko6~jto;as "cosmological arrangement,"and the fact that Diogenes was at pains to secure this sense shows that by his time the word was not habituallyused in the cosmological context. in the sense "world"occurs twice, In Democritus'fragments co6aiog; in B 274 and B 34,62but both instances are unreliable. The authenticity I of B 247 (&v6pi aotp noa yfi yap &ya0fiGXatpi; 6 VUXfiG •atii. the has been for reason that the phrase con; Koa6Jog) rejected Jtntag sists of two corruptediambic trimeters,63and this meter is hardlyincidental, for the phrase is a banal variation on a sentiment popular in fifth-centuryAtheniandrama.64It is noteworthythat in the second line of the trimeter the meter is broken precisely by the unmetrical As to B 34, it comes from David the Armenian,a Christian KoCYIo;g.65 Neoplatonistof the sixth century,Prolegomena38.14 (Busse): cati6c(rEp v w)inavri 6p&04evXr p[~v 6povTa otov T& ~t6vo(g t T otov e 6eta, 6&Kai 6pXovTawaxi S av6p6r(iEta ap6pvlxva t ep (bXv va px& 6o•oyxa t 0a, 1 &v0pdrOt iicP, b•t v ic•ax K6pCrLP ....ov tp6') acrbv v Awtl6'Kptrov 'z8& 6;vx &p %?t6vC0 r(J ictai v cal'rca0opoFvat, 'r & tpxovtat ic•ai oPXoUxtv •wa -tx gev piovov; ica 6pxolotv (; 6 60lt WoRtep6 Xoyo;, 'r ... &8•a 6 vw; fl En?tteoupa. a•pxov'tat W6o0tCFp 62In B 180, B 195, and B 274 the meaning is "adornment";in B 258 and B 259 the referenceis to political order. 63J. Freudenthal,Die Theologiedes Xenophanes(Breslau 1886) 38 n. 3. 64Both in tragedy (e.g., Eur. fr. 777, 1047 N) and in comedy (e.g., Aristoph. Plut. 1151); the maxim is cited also in prose writers(Thuc. 2.43; Lys. 31.6). See DK ad B 247; R. Philippson, "Demokrits Sittenspruche,"Hermes 59 (1924) 369-371; S. Luria, "Zur Geschichte einer kosmopolitischenSentenz,"Proceedings of the Academyof Sciences of the USSR, 1925, 78-81; id., "Einstellungendes Klassikertextesbei Stobaios,"RhM 78 (1929) 88-90; cf. Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 173 and n. 4, but the popularityof the sentimentalreadyin the second half of the fifth centurymakes her suggestion of the Stoic provenanceof B 247 unnecessary. 65Some scholars (notably S. Luria, Demokrit [Leningrad1970] 602, who denied the genuineness of B 247, see the previous note, but later changed his mind) are ready to admit that Democritus could cite the popular verse maxim; if this was the case (which does not seem particularlylikely), the unmetricalK6otog;could not originally belong to Democritus'quotation. OntheHistoryof theGreekKOXMOX 121 David has no doxographicalauthority,and his attributionof the notion of ttxpb; Kx6`tLoto Democritusdoes not find supportin other sources. The earliest instance of the term is in Aristotle who, without specifying its provenance, applies it to animals in general.66The term, again in applicationto animals, is related by Galen to "men of antiquityexpert in inquiry into the nature of things."67Scholars are willing to see in Galen's reference to ancient philosophers of nature an assistance to David's attribution,but this seems to be a mistake:the parallelbetween the world and man suggests a world ruledby Reason, which the parallel between the world and animal does not; these are two conceptions of different philosophical provenance. In the Atomists' world there is nothing akin to the human intelligence, and therefore of all the Presocratics Democritus is the least likely choice for being credited with formulatingthe conception of man as microcosm.68But not only is the philosophical plausibility of David's attributionscant, the comparison he draws between the world and man is patently Platonic, and his appeal to the authorityof Democritus is surprising. Considering that the microcosmic theory was quite popularin laterphilosophy in general and in Neoplatonism in particular,and seeing that beside Democritus there is no other Presocraticphilosopheraddressedin either of David's extant works,69the question arises whether the Democritus referredto is the Abderite, or ratherthe prominentthird-centuryNeoplatonist of the same name, whose theory of soul (which is significantfor our case) was influentialenough to be included in a doxographyeventually used 66 Phys. 252b26. The argumentAristotle considers in Phys. 8.2 is that if it is possible for an animal to rouse itself from rest to motion, it may be possible for the universe as a whole to be now at rest and now in motion. Luria (above, n. 65) 425, says that he is "deeply convinced" that not only the term, but the views considered by Aristotle, are Democritus', but Guthrie (above, n. 4) 2.471 n. 2, seems closer to the truth when he remarks that "this is certainly not an analogy of which Democritus would have approved." 67De usu part. 3.10 (= DK 68 B 34). 68The idea was implicit in Presocraticthoughtfrom its very beginning, but, as Guthrie (above, n. 4) 2.472, comments, "the most striking thing about their [the Atomists'] achievementis the extent to which they freed themselves from the anthropomorphicconception of the universewith which the microcosmic theory is most naturallylinked." 69 Save, of course, Pythagoras and the Pythagoreans. David's reference, In Porph. 105.11 (Busse), to Heraclitus' mannerof writing as exemplifying &a`pemais irrelevant, for since Aristotle's Rhetoric Heraclitus' style was commonplace;note the popular dictum (cf. D.L. 2.22 = DK 22 A 4) concerningthe deepness of Heraclitus' meaning which David adduces. 122 AryehFinkelberg by Stobaeus.70But even if we assume thatDemocritusmeanthere is the Abderite, David's appeal to his authorityin connection with the Platonic theory of the microcosm would allow two explanations:either the notion of jtipo K6icago;as such was intimately associated in the Greek traditionwith Democritus' name, or David mistakenly credited him with the Platonic conception of the microcosm. The fact that in mentioningthe microcosmic theory Aristotle and Galen fail to refer to Democritus, as well as the general silence of Greek doxographyabout the Democriteanprovenanceof this popular notion, speak against the formerpossibility,and thereforethe latteris more probable.71 It thus emerges that the fifth-centurytexts do not furnish any clearcut evidence for Koago;oas "world." The word is consistently used in and even in this sense no sysits primarysense of "order,arrangement," tematic employmentof it in cosmological speculationsis traceable. On the contrary,certaininstances of the Presocraticuse (notably,Melissus' and Diogenes') suggest that the word had no distinctive cosmological connotations. Xenophon's testimony that "world"was not among the proves to be correct. fifth-centurysenses of 6oCjgo; II A philosopherwho began to teach in Athens in the last years of the fourth century, Epicurus, defined Koago; as nTIptoijr ti oupavoi, The definia yiyv ai itdrvTat qpactv6~geva ~oapaCE ix is a well attestedsense of tion need not much surpriseus, for "heaven"nept•Zoiaa.72 the GreekKiago;. This meaning is explicitly statedin the Epinomis,73 70 Ecl. 1.49 (1.370.1-2 Wachsmuth). 71As H. Langerbeck,A6•i; intpoagii• (Berlin 1935) 77, saw. The title of Democritus' book Mipb S; may have been an ultimatesource of the confusion. 72Pyth. 88;6idiooto;S roi cf. 112: ritva& Palvet oi CdRvov Tb~~Ipo; 'oapa oTpEpocatl ' axoT i, K6 oE arvat, niEpi0 r ... &XX&cxKai &vrlv po; ro'roroC -to o 'outnv'verxl ppE•qEat Ccx roi irEPiirOXEiV, yiF-IcwXovaxi'ylrOEplEarivcxl id (0O;uruCii Kai 'C,raXaca Krx. For furtherinstancesof this use in Epicurussee flepi pqaFo;ota', col. IIIa-IVain D. Sedley, "Epicurusand the Mathematiciansof Cyzicus,"CronacheErcolanesi 6 (1976) 37-38. 73Epin. 987B7: the sphere of the fixed stars is said to be what "one would especially seems to be used exclusively in the call Although in the Epinomis K6oagIo; "heaven"(977B2; 986C4; 987A5, B7, D8), the only generally recognized instance senser?toago;." of this meaning remains 987B7, though the synonymy of -co"ago;,"OXtIRno;,and oibpavd;at 977B2 (for this use of"Ok•vXno;cf. Parm.B 11.2-3) is often noted, see, e.g., Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 50; Mansfeld (above, n. 16) 43; cf. W. Burkert'sobserva- OntheHistoryof theGreekKOLMOY 123 is frequentin Aristotle,74found in the thirdcenturyin Cleanthes'Hymn to Zeus75and in the astronomicalwork of Euclid,76is reportedin the first century A.D. by Philo to be a regular use of the word,77and is recorded by Greek lexicographers.78The use is attested as early as t KOO IsocratesPanegyricus 179: cti yxNpyj; tri Et&taindal; )Ib io '11 Riv 6; , 8' E'pU'PTn% 'Aaiaoq rt 8Xoa [[tijRCVr; Koa, was finished c. Rtvrl; K course 380, was not oflaoovjgvrle Xi. The speech, which an esoteric philosophical piece; we may thus infer that by this time the use of in the sense "heaven,"viz. synonymouslywith o^Opav6q, K6atgo; was fairly popular. This conclusion finds supportin Isocrates Busiris 12, composed several years earlier: &dpayocptot; Rev olou)r6nouno r u tot; )i rov REv to; n; alo nr' •Rpsov •Xzrauovoivo0u, ... 8' &F v i7v [sc. o6pav Rv Egypt] 8taCpi0tpogRLvou;, Cai"rlv Xa,,iaroc in tob The sense which Isocrates uses Krk. KEtiivylv xK6ajo; hereK6aoto is best clarified by the comparison with Herodotus 1.142: oi &8 tov '"o0ve;o-rot ... o.• ioC tO) Lv tOK•) loRv o1Jpovo wK(Xt O)po)ev t vot ... yxp x ati7' ivo t'aTzoXavov i6SpaodU6 nt6ktax o.tes oT9pia It tb inotist f9 'Ilovi oite x& Xt ... tx& inb roi0IUXpo .•tu g•v sTe Kai &ypoi itew6gtva, tix 6k 'nb ToGOspgoi [s Kiial aO g 8Fo;g.79It thus emerges that where Herodotussays 6v to4 iatc•toi oupavoi, Xoao tion, Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism,trans. E. L. Minar Jr. (Cambridge, Mass. 1972) 245 n. 36, that "at 986C the word [is] connected in an emphaticway o6atgo; with paths of the stars." 74E.g., Meteor.340b10, 12; Met. 1063a15;EN. 1141bl. 75Ap. Stob. Ecl. 1.1.12 = H. v. Arnim, Stoicorumveterumfragmenta (Stuttgart1905) 1.122.3-4: ao' 86i n&; 6E 6ato;, Xtaao6oFevo;nEptiyyatcv,//Iiei•rat. Cf. Arius Did. fr. 33 Diels (above, n. 14)•c467.7 (= Arnim, 1.34.27): r*v 8' iXtIovIKaiTiv aGXk•vrlv 6io Oi riiv ri'v8' n'&'xvacxohiv, &d'n' &vaToXfi; K*6aooGRo in8 pop&qOapeaOl, wvavCI (6t&ovpt'v o(98ion Ii'rcapaivovra;. rtavt6I1Oo` iEK 6.15 (Menge): YIaOor' 6t&t Tfij; lVo I'Civ ininE6ov 69piroyv&8 8.29: i E~i 12.14); (cf. FiCninTov rbv o6agIov ic6ajgotneptarpoqi~;Xp6vo; aOriv,iV ) &iro' jvaToki; ini iv ,r. i1 lccxaTovT&vx&haviv earipoy & &ava'tOXijv 'an'Vt rTv tVij; napaylver•at &q' o lnoToiv '6Trnouv ini acxbyvv6nrov. Ev totvvy 6 6ato; ao;Ka' 77 Philo De aet. mund. 6.73 (Cohn-Wendland): yFcxTat tiv [np&Tov]oao2x$aica Agoipavo) Ica rIapoov KaTx& neptoXiv ((ai) yi; cKac •zv in' abxrfi ('ov iaic quTwv, KaO' eTpov ii'6vo; o;pav6;q nK. For the use of o6aIgo;for "heaven"in general literaturesee Diod. 1.169.17, 19; 173.8 (Milller). 78 Pollux 4.158 (247.24 Bethe): obpav6;q, c6a0TCo;,AiCiko;, Cvat, S3ca T& iv TO iicuxy, & oi inokoit xakooatv nKcr.Hsch. Lex. 2812 (3.354 Schmidt): n6xo;~,o(8ta oupavo6, -o6ago;o kX. 79 For other instances of Herodotus'use of oupav6q in the sense of "climate"see J. E. Powell, A Lexicon to Herodotus2 (Cambridge1938), s.v. iC6atao;. 76 Phaen. 124 AryehFinkelberg Isocratesuses ev ahcaio' toU Isocrates' use of 6oago;for Kxo•Cgo)v. "climate"testifies that as early as about390 B.C.the synonymy between olpav6o and K6ago; was so close and familiaras to make possible the occasional use of the latterin derivativesenses of the former. in the sense of "heaven"is frequent in Plato, The use of K•coog; although it is often overlooked by translators and commentators.80 Leges 820E-821B: AO. ao[pov 86i1 ,Rbe'tX&o•aa opaotr7 OrlOtyV loitgv`otg, av OeNv oi ... To9vavtiov ?X .bv 7a1i &poCnqcl oioa •t~y3toaov TiRt&O oitCe?rleltv 88&vo'me.stoXrunpaygoIcai 5Xov [bv KIca0ovqpNThv yp o38U' otov etvat--zo F_ veiv tI&goairig n toitoiAEpvvovzaog--oa to vavtiov ytYv6pievov6po; g &v yti~yveo~t 'otcevov ov 6tXX' iarpov r?npt~gdOrlaxi otoorov ... KA. eic6ra oiyetg" ave'upfioog•v; The two referencesto the study of the stars and the subsequentdiscussion (821B-822D) of the tracksof the heavenly bodies indicate that the inquiryinto tbv gyytorov O0bvcail iXov tbv 6i0agov is astronomyand thereforeK6ogo; must mean "heaven"here ratherthan "world."8' &' vo6v nidvra a t Philebus 28E: cb pydvaoit coal fig; 6taovcooaEdt 'v o oS CoXO6poouKct?l (iou iaocldolg doalpyov oehal Vrl;g acot ove(g ot &;tov Icxr. Plato's counting "theK6(coog"with the sun, neptupopa; ri1g as visual manifestationsof the revolution and the moon, stars, heavenly Mind's orderingactivity again favors the sense of "heaven." Similarly, in Criti. 121C3, where Plato says that Zeus called all the gods into ' "their most honorable residence" which icarx eoov nravro;gro the I aCi op& ioc yeveaeog Er KcT6xootP3EP3cuia •E~,F•Ev, avoids the the whole heaven" not only translation"in the middle of idtvraa oddness of the location of the god's residence "in the middle of the whole world"(in the midst of the sphericalearth?in between the earth and the sky?) but is distinctly suggested by the icaOopQ,the basic sense of which is "to look down." 80But see D. J. Furley's comment, Aristotle On the Cosmos (Cambridge,Mass. 1978) 349 note c. 81Also in its two other occurrencesin the cosmological context in the Laws (897C8 means "heaven";in 897C this sense is furtherwarrantedby the comand 967C5) Kico"Tog parisonwith Plato's explanationof the benefitsof sight in Tim.46E-47C. OntheHistoryof theGreekKOLMOI 125 Timaeus27A: "8o4ev y xp iifRivTipgatovgLv, iCTOvTa cuTpovott'pyov to. 7avLbrgEi&vat l XlctoXa Kcxtatov fLgov Kal 7Lcpi qcpeTCoog t to InetnrOTgtjvov, Xyetiv p06pOevov &rbt ig o K6ogo(TO) nIpTov &kEi; yev~(oeS, eevx&v 5vOp8nyov (pa3ntv Kxh. The phrase &p6dgpievov-FXUexe&vsuggests a series of consecutive accounts, more than two-of the world and of man-as the traditionaltranslation of the as "world"makes it mean. Again, on the currentrendering, Ko•R•og Plato's emphasis on Timaeus' being an astronomerappearsirrelevant: to account for the generationof the world and of man one might well (and would better) have been a philosopher. The meaning "heaven" suits the context better: "beginningfrom the generationof the heaven and going down to the creation of man" is indeed a series of accounts in which Timaeus' expertnessin astronomymay find its properapplication. The fourth-centuryuse of Ka6~1ogfor "heaven"brings us back to Aitius' report,accordingto which Pythagoraswas the first who called tilvyiv 8T(ov rneptoxlyv 6cogov. The phrase resembles Epicurus' neptoxTi tig oupavob, and, more remotely, Aristotle's 6 K•X6og •-rti ri"vyiiv.82As we concluded above, the reportreflects rteptxov the use of K6•Rgogby the Pythagoreansof the last generations,and we •c6•gogit can now see why may have drawnTheophrastus'attention:it became currentin Athens at the beginning of the fourth century B.C.and was takenup by philosophers. Another semantic developmentwhich took place in this period was the extension of the meaning of oupav6g;which, in addition to its primary sense of "heaven,"came to mean "world." The first instance of this use seems to be Rep. 509D: ... 68o evat, alpacitexItv a~ 6patoi, i~va ;e Iai 6tonlou, tb TV vo-roi YVvoug b 86'a?6t)o tIl ouipavou a eooa t nrepi t6 voxa. The meaning is frequent ei?inv 860 ( otcoipi in Plato83and is well instanced in Aristotle.84The use is attested in 82Meteor 339b4. Cf. 6 epi qtiv yfiv 6KoCgo;which is composed of the four elements o 6 Iog; (Meteor.340b12) located below 6 (Meteor 339a19, 340b8, etc.). This is 0'6 ; ExivoU oi xo. (Meteor 339b18; ~icaog; [sc. aether]i•rThprlS n7pi r,& avo cpopx; i•Tog cf. fr. 26 Ross). Cf. Theophrastus' similar subdivision of the heaven into the upper and lower regions, De igne 351.19-25 (Wimmer): il npcfirrla(cpppa, which consists of the element whose nature is and and i'lxepi r•v figyi~; cpcaipav [sc. ui•xro; cKacapa•, which is oapcapa] cKaxi &d cx-araxyFveFatv (that Theophrastusconceived of the formeras filled withegLytvtvrl the ratherthan aetheris immaterialhere). 83E.g., Tim.28B2; Pit.Oepgo6v 273C1; Phlb. 30B5; Lg. 896E1, etc. 84E.g., Phys. 212b17; De caelo 301a17; Met. 990a5, etc.; the third sense of ocpav;6 in Aristotle's definition at De caelo 278b10-21: "In yet another sense we call 'the 126 AryehFinkelberg philosophers,but if it were not popularenough, Plato could not hope, as he most probablydid, his wordplayin Republic509D be understood by the generalreader. Plato's use of for "world"is well exemplified, but it seems •o6•og;in which the word is that not in all instances traditionallytranslatedas "world"does it have this meaning. Gorgias 507E-508A: cpaq 86'oi odpaKaXhiKeXt;, Kai aocpoi,Jo vbv cai yfiv ;caiOECoCg iai &vOpthnou;g 'ilv (otvoviav ouv•xetv Kcai Kai aocppoo;vlv Kcai8tccat6trlTa,KcaiTb Cai Kooglt6trl-a pt•,~av "Xov 6 •raipe, oi~ drCoogitav x [to1o taia Coaiocotv, K6Cdoaov 8t6, The currentrenderingof the ico(tog; as "world"or o`Ni d•oXao(iav. is contrastedwith "world-order"raises some problems. First, K6oaLog but "world"can hardlybe the opposite of "intemperance."85 dwKoX(aoia, Secondly, -rbOXov can scarcely mean "the universe"here: the denial that the universe may be called "intemperance"is absurd, and moreover, in the sense "universe"to ~iXovneed not be specified by the oXov does not refer to the universe, it demonstrativeto^ro. But if -r6 cannot be called "a world-order."rboiOXovto^ro is the fellowship of "the heaven and the earth, gods and men" ("the heaven and the earth" stand here for the respective abodes of gods and men, not for cosmological entities) which rests on "orderand temperanceandjustice." For this reasonthe sages refer to this all-embracingcommunityas a (moral) order,not disorderliness86and intemperance,and that is why the intemperate, who "is incapable of fellowship" "would be dear neither to a fellow-man nor to a god."87 heaven' the body encircled by the extreme circumference:the whole or totality we are in habitto call 'the heaven'." 85To avoid the difficulty translatorsresort to awkwardverbal additions:"... they call this universe a world-order ... not a world-disorder"(Dodds [above, n. 10] 308, ad 508A3); ". .. they call the sum of things the 'ordered'universe ... not the world of disorder and riot" (W. D. Woodheadin E. Hamilton and H. Cairns eds., The Collected Dialogues of Plato 2 [Princeton1963] 290). 86For the moralsense of &riooa(iain Plato cf. Symp. 188B. 87Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 223-224, is correctin stressingthe moral and political, ratherthan cosmological, purportof the passage. The sages Plato refers to are commonly maintainedto be the Pythagoreans(see Dodds [above, n. 10] 308, ad 508A3; cf. A. E. Taylor, Plato. The Man and His Work[London 1926] 128-129; Guthrie [above, n. 4] 4.284, Kerschensteiner,ibid., and others) and the passage is often taken as witnessing the Whether or not it is Pythagorean(for a balanced view see Pythagoreanuse of Ki6otgo;. the Burkert[above, n. 73] 77-79), linguistic use is quite regular:the sense of the K~6ojto; OntheHistoryof theGreekKOLMOZ 127 Phaedrus 246B-C: X1 RCX cxv XVUX a av0XC &m o8pavcv Xoi zoC , irtv-ra tt'o E1U1Xat; d8 7reptroXi, .XToT' -v Xo1)A 'v•xTo ytYvotFVrj.TOzaCgtiv o0v 'Tv K6opov o~oa 1cuaiin;Rtspo•tvrvl pte poiropsi -rEici dvmroa T & E l <pUpEat 8totKE1C, 8 tEpoppl )oaOa o;g v oGtpEEO) 'tvog0 o &vt1iXPrlat, oT eoax, yri'vov Xa4Coixoa KcXk. c&ta K•aotmoOl1 The verb 8totiko is usually takenhere in the sense "to manage,to control,"the ensuing translationbeing: "when a soul is perfect and winged it travelsin the heights and controls the whole world."88Yet the parallel with Kacott o0dEac suggests the other sense of &8otl~, namely "to inhabit"(cf. Tim. 19E), while the contrastbetween r6v oK6aoov and o&toa yrji'vov ,a[poioax indicates that the reference is &totw•1 to the heaven. The soul journeys throughout the whole universe, rndtva oupav6v, taking now one form, now another:when it is "perfectand and inhabits rndvra winged" it travels in the heights ([tewexoporopd) r6v K6aoaov,"the whole heaven"(precisely as Plato portraysthis in the following paragraphswhere he depicts the procession of gods and souls throughoutthe heaven);but when, strippedof its wings, it falls from the heaven, it enters o0&toa yqi.vov, viz. inhabitsthe earth.89The passage is of great interest:the fact that which standsfor "heaven"is conK•6o•og for "world,universe"suggests that trastedwith o0pav6g which stands by that time (presumablythe mid-sixties of the fourth century B.C.90) K6coog;had still not acquiredthe sense of "world." If I am correct that the rendering of as "world" in Grg. Kco•og;that this 508A3 and Phdr 246C2 is erroneous, it emerges meaning is found only in the late dialogues, notably, the Timaeus,Politicus, and Philebus (i.e., presumably from the fifties of the fourth century B.C. onwards). Since these dialogues seem to be the first Greek texts in which is used in the sense of "world" (we shall return to Ko6oLo;S is "social order"which Plato associates with the related moral notions, coojit6zr;qand 88 See, e.g., Platon. Oeuvrescompletes,5ed. L. Robin 4 (Paris 1961) 3e partie.Phetdre 246C, translation;R. Hackforth,Plato's Phaedrus (Cambridge1952) 70. 89Mansfeld (above, n. 16) 43 n. 31, 122 n. 288, is preparedto recognize in the K6otgo; sense of "heaven"here. 90For a concise critical survey of the studies concerningthe chronology of Plato's dialogues, see L. Brandwood,"Stylometryand Chronology,"in R. Krauted., The Cambridge Companionto Plato (Cambridge1992) 90-120. 128 AryehFinkelberg Xenophon's Memorabilia in a moment), it seems reasonable to conclude that the usage was Plato's own terminological innovation. The way in which the term is treatedin all three dialogues supportsthis conclusion. In Timaeus28B3, before he starts to employ the word in the new sense (in 24C1 is used in the political context, and in Ko6•1o; 27A6, as we have seen, in its regularsense of "heaven")Plato defines n Kcoa~o;as a synonym of oi6pav6g (in the sense of "world"):6 8 ir& W 11 ia'TXV _ovowX xi a •XXo oTt lro'TE ogi6vo; ' oIapav•;--ii KOgOO; K-tX. In the same manner, the first ixotto, tro~0' iyIV davotd0om'o time the term occurs in the Politicus (269D8) it is expressly introduced as a synonym of oUpaxv6g(=world): 8v &i8oiUpavbv m icic6xl ov CX LEv nxapx noXXav xro yevvvioavxog 7rn(OvotdKxa1CEv, •ai cap1ovplv Finally, in the first of the two occurrences of the Etzei?rlXpEv KcTX.91 word in the terminologicalsense in the Philebus (29E1; 59A3; as in the Timaeus,here too the very first appearanceof the word, in 28E4, is in the sense of "heaven")its conventional characteris carefully pointed out: Ta-rxbv8i &8 Xca3g XnRpi ro•8 ~v K6otLov XTyog•v. It thus for seems evident that Plato did not expect that his use of Koatgo; "world"would be readily understandableoutside the Academy.92 There was however one writer who immediately noticed Plato's terminological innovation. Above I allowed for the sake of the argument that Memorabilia 1.1-2 is of an early date, but now we may try to determineits chronology with a more precision. If these chapters are of an early date indeed, the peculiar sense in which, according to Memorabilia 1.1.11, "the men of wisdom" used Kacoog;can only be "heaven."93Now the 91In both dialogues all the occurrencesof ic6ogio; subsequentto the definition are in the terminologicalsense. The only exception is Tim.40A where the meaning is "adornment"(so correctlyF. Astius, LexiconPlatonicum [Leipzig 1835] 207, s.v. cK6aoog;; Cornford's "world"is a mistranslation),though Mansfeld (above, n. 16) 43 and n. 31, seems correctin detectingthe pun on "adornment"and "heaven." 92 W. Burkert,"Platonoder Pythagoras?Zum Ursprungdes WortesPhilosophie,"Herwas inventedby Plato rather mes 88 (1960) 159-177, suggested that the term (plXoYocpia than by Pythagoras.If my conclusions are correct, xc6'ogo, currentlyconsidered a distinctively Pythagoreanterm, was also Plato's innovation.If so, Philolaus' fragments--at least those in which ic6aoog;occurs in the sense of "world"(B 1, B 2, B 6, B 17; all these are accepted by Burkert[above, n. 73] 218-277; and Huffman [above, n. 57] 15-37 and passim)-must be a post-Platonicforgery. It is not for nothing that in accountingfor the PythagoreandoctrinesAristotlefailed to mentionPhilolaus' book. 93 So in F W. Sturz,LexiconXenophonteum(Leipzig 1801) 1.776, s.v. Kc6o`o;. On the History of the GreekKOWMOI 129 discussion of "the natureof all things"is specified by Xenophon as the runs"and inquiry into "how what the men of wisdom call the Ko"tgoq into "by what necessities each of the heavenly phenomena takes place." The latter inquiry is astronomical;if the means "heaven,"the KoqoLto; former would be astronomicaltoo, and the whole discussion of "the natureof all things" would turn out to be about astronomyalone. The sense of the K6co0o;must, then, be "world." This being so, Memorabilia 1.1-2 cannot be earlier, or at least much earlier, than Plato's Timaeus.94 Xenophon's "the men of wisdom" are thus the Academy, and it is their peculiaruse of Ko6Lgo;he recordshere and imitates elsewhere: 6'rbv Xkov aoov T ... o'rto t&x oa'itt'tov K•ioalvVzoxv p v rpd&x'Trv (Mem. 4.3.13).95 6p&'opat gt'ytorxo Plato seems to have not intendedhis new usage to replace the traditional ones: he used Ko~0ao; interchangeablywith oppabv6;,and in the Laws he returned to the use of the word in its regular meaning, "heaven,"a use which he never entirely abandoned;96Aristotle continues to use in the sense of "heaven,"and in reference to the K•6o•o; world he uses 6o.ato; less frequentlythan ou'pav6;. At the same time Aristotle's use of the word in Plato's terminologicalsense suggests that the term was not eventually discarded in the Academy, and hence its absence from the Laws seems to have been due to Plato's ad hoc decision ratherthan to a principledrenunciationof the usage. It seems that in working on the TimaeusPlato felt the need for an additionalterm for "world" which would convey semantic nuances absent in o)pav6;. What, then, could be Plato's reasons for introducing 6oag.o;as an additional term for "world"? The traditional scholarly association of 94 Perhaps the new usage was initiated earlier in the Academy, in oral discussions; Xenophon's referencemay be to the oral use of the term ratherthan to specific dialogues. All this however must remain purely speculative. Our textual evidence is Phdr. 246C, which is the terminuspost quem (presumably,the sixties of the fourth century), and the Timaeus, which is the terminus ante quem (presumablythe fifties). The Memorabilia, which is now commonly considered a unified composition, must, then, be later than Phaedrus and probablyeven later than Timaeus. For a critical survey of the discussion of the date of the Memorabilia,see R. Nickel, Xenophon(Darmstadt1979). 95 Cf. the way in which Xenophon conveys a similar idea in Cyr.8.3.13: ... eeoFo yeE Icr. ... oi cai-rivE-riiv6Wv 6ttyv •Xh•v 96 Lg. 821A2,897C8; 967C5 oiv(*Xoxotv mustmean"order," a meaning whichis sug(at ic•(6ogo; in theprevious sengestedby vo; ... 6 8taicExcoogincgi))oa caZr' o-opavov irtv0' in thesense of "heaven" is foundin Tim.27A6andPhlb. tence);werecallthatKc6oL'o; 28E4(i.e.,in bothcasesbeforetheformalintroduction of thenewterminological sense) andin theCritias(121C3),whichpresumably followstheTimaeusimmediately. 130 AryehFinkelberg K6oJog;with beauty and orderliness seems to be irrelevant. Timaeus 29A: "If this K6o0og;is beautiful (KcX6;) and the creator good, it is obvious that he looked to the eternal [pattern],but if what is awful to say is right, then to the created one. It is clear to everyone that he looked to the eternal, for it [sc. this K60oYog]is the most beautiful (iKktolrno;) of creations .. ." Clearly, the assumption that cK6o"o; strongly implies the idea of beauty would turn Plato's reasoninginto a sophistry. As to the idea of "order,"in Plt. 273B5 the Kcoaog;is said to be in a state of disorder before it comes to its present orderly condition.97 Plato's meaning can perhaps be better isolated if we consider the word from the linguistic point of view, namely, that of its morphology and the semantic field to which it was linked by Plato's innovativeuse. in the sense of "world"was the extension of its sense Using K6~C1og; This extenof "heaven"by analogy with the extendeduse of oopa(v6g. relation with 8tosion of meaning brought cK6?oo;into a semantic which were used /a/ctarot;6 KooaIo) and its derivative8td&Kcooao; in the cosmological context alreadyin the fifth century.98There is how/ ever a principal morphological difference between 8td•Kootog; on the while the on and other: the one hand, 8StaK16(Xojt otg, formeris the verbalnoun relatedto K6ctJog,as the designationof its Sta•xooF`o action, viz. cosmogony, the latter,if relatedto the verb, comes to designate the result of its action, viz. the world as an outcome of cosmogony.99I would therefore suggest that Plato sought for a term 97 Note that the logical subject of the phrase 'v ,riEZXov&tr(aiatlXpiv ei; zrv no,,fi; is 0K60ojo; 6 viyvK~6ojgov (272E5, 273A1). a0ptPto(uOt 98For the first time in ParmenidesB 8.60, which is the first known occurrenceof the was used word (zrv oot Ey 6c8tcoojpov otuc6rzandvrozor`pazro).The verb 8t•aoopj(io 0 by Anaxagoras(B 12) with referenceto the cosmogonical activity of the Mind. 8toiCooigo;is a verbalnoun and as such designates action-"(distributive) marshalling,setting in order,regulating"(as was stressed by Reinhardt,[above, n. 3] 175, but ignored by Kranz [above, n. 3] 434; see also Kerschensteiner[above, n. 3] 13). Its use in the resultative sense is derivative, and hence later. For this reason in ParmenidesB 8.60 and in the Atomists' book titles--MEyaq o8tiKooajo; and Mtcpb &8tdrooKgo;-theproperrendering of the word must be "[world-]ordering"ratherthan "[world-]order"(in Parmenidesthis sense is authenticatedby the fact that the 6t&acoolgo; which the goddess is promising to relate turns out to be a cosmogony; Kahn's interpretation[above, n. 3] 227, of the in B 8.60 as "the system of the naturalworld"neglects both the morphology 8t~IKootgo; of the word and the contentof the Doxa). 99As Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 13, cf. 14, 16, observed. On the History of the GreekKOLMOZ 131 which would be a resultativenoun in respect to the action conveyed by 8taKooaglo, and icoogo was just the word. This suggestion seems to be corroboratedby a semantic developmentwhich evidently took place outside the Academy but which seems to have been motivated by the same terminological need-I mean the extension of the use of 8t61ooago; / to designate, not only cosmogony, but also o86acoardlot; the ensuing world. The first instance of this use is Aristotle Metaphysics 986a6, which is the only occurrenceof the word in the cosmological context in Aristotle, but in later authorsthe use is abundant.100 This usage conforms to the general semantic developmentof the word which graduallycame to be used also in the resultativesense.101As a and K6Jogo;became synonyms, and in the course result, taocdoagrlot; of time these terms generally replaced the use of oupav6; in the sense of "world." III It remainsto examine the semantic developmentas a result of which Kcoaogo came to designate the world's several regions. Presumably drawing on current exegeses Plutarch construes the five aoCiootin Timaeus55C-D as earth, water, air, fire, and heavens,102and scholars are prepared to follow his interpretation, thus allowing "world's The passage reads regions" as Plato's intended meaning of Koa6goti.103 as follows: in the Stoics: 100Ps.-Arist. De mundo 391bl 1 (StoaKcolrolat),400b32 (Sta6Kooago;); D.L. 7.137; Arius Dyd. ap. Eus. Prep. Evang. 15.15 (= Arnim [above, n. 75] 2.169.19), etc. 101This use seems to be first attestedin Thuc. 4.93, where the word is applied to battle order.In Plato Stoacirlo;t; occurs several times, but never in the cosmological context; it is however noteworthythat he uses the word predominantlyin the deverbativesense. In Symp. 209A7 the meaning is "the orderingof society"; in Critias 118A1 "the organizing of the territory"by the works describedin the next paragraphs;in Lg. 853A3 "the arranging of the law"; in Tim.23E2 the sense is ambiguous,but it seems that what is meant to have been recorded is the chronicle of founding the city ratherthan its constitution;the only clear instance of the resultativemeaningis Tim.24C4. It may, then, seem thatPlato's was too strong to put the word to the feeling for the deverbativesense of &taKcdoaglo; terminologicaluse in the resultativesense. 102De E. 389F-390A; De or 430B-C. def. 421F-422A, 422F-423B, 103R. D. Archer-Hind,The Timaeus of Plato (London 1888) 198-199, ad loc.; A. E. Taylor,A Commentaryon Plato's Timaeus(Oxford 1928) 378, ad loc.; F. M. Cornford, Plato's Cosmology (London 1937) 221; Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 51-53; cf. Mansfeld (above, n. 16) 43. 132 AryehFinkelberg & 81i Ei vr6voXa Xoy~t6Igvo; •ttXgE &knopoin~drepov it ~xovrx;, 'r6 lgiv &Xnipou;Xpl Kcogou;o fvat Xiyetv i irCnpaXq v devat 66y(iya &nEipou; ijyiatxr' &v ?vor;q7(xipov trvb; &A Eva i i •xv axbro); Fxrl0ex lunrtpov xpe~Ovevat, 7n6'rEpov o yetyv nori npoon•icnt, ne_<(uxd;au taXXov &v a(xiq o'Trg LiKCxOq 6taunopi7otj. 'r jgivo3v 6i1 nap' 1[t(6v va acxbyv ixar&x & Ei; 6XX(anirl 'rv eiK6CaX6yov nTUcx6o vrtrljvut el 6v, EXXo;g 5dot. 860x phi•q; 'rtepa Timaeus' unaccounteddigression from the discussion of the primary bodies to the question of how many i6~o0aotshould be assumed is puzzling. However, what seems clear is that the question posited in the first clause refers to the numberof worlds allowed to be in existence, which is confirmedby the comparisonwith Timaeus31A-B.1'4 But if the io6agot in the first clause means "worlds,"'"xva i~i' vre (x a'rooi in the next clause and 'vaxatxr6v in the last one must also refer to worlds. Plutarch'sexegesis is unwarranted:whateverthe purportof the passage may be, the K6aoLotmeans "worlds,"not "regions."105Besides this Timaeuspassage two other texts have been referredto as supposedly testifying the fourth-centuryorigins of the notion of the universe as stratifiedinto several oajogot. Damascius De Principiis 321 (Ruelle) = Eudemus fr. 150 (Wehrli, 70.12-19): &S 6E1pto; ~ j; evaoCt&d•i mic Xp6vov cxi Z&vmro EpEFicr [.tv X8oviavI'x; srpEi;npcjaX;q Tcv 8voiv, &pxd;, 'ilv ~aXvg(Pninp6 x io 6 av, 'Xv &8Xp6vov notiIoat -KTouy6vov XrlV aXixr&; poZ& roi ci {6p, riv pnkuijv, Ualoto 7np ici irveiwcoacai oxtt, npitv C g 1v v vorl ou, tCvTe vo)v TnoxilV &rlv 8tplvtt• LZFotg uov oivat 8&0v, rlV vTC 'aixTbv iv'Zxov KacXcL[tiVjv, yewvev & tol)Tov (kxog i'a•g inEv, ( ibo) n7epi nesvtEKoopgov. E•o pcXv•xItK(Xtpo;. o1v 6p0•e EvaoCpavbv ii InoXX Kai neirpou; X•ytv '04 •i nrpoostpjiKcaOEv, nI6epov ... 68t& va, Ei'nspCa-r nap6d&itYga iv 6pe6terpov; taOra 86Erl1itoOpyrg1vo;otat "tb oi•zre&0ooijZ'&nIEpo; e~nicO1eV6 rnot~vKC6ogou;,6XX' Ef 688govoyevi~; o pav6; 105Though conceding Plutarch's interpretation,Cornford (above, n. 103) 220-221, wonders:"Itstill remainsa puzzle why Plato should speak of the notion that thereare five cosmoi = regions in the one world as an alternativeto a single cosmos = world or an indefinitenumberof worlds"[Cornford'sitalics]. OntheHistoryof theGreekKOEMOX 133 Damascius draws here on Eudemus, and Kerschensteiner106 suggested as must be his, that the explanationof the Pherecydian tuXo'o coatoot for, she argues, the surmise i'owg bespeaks Eudemus' attemptto EittEnv construe, in following Aristotle Metaphysics 1091b8, Pherecydes' approach as midway between theology and natural philosophy. The suggestion does not appeartenable when Damascius' whole passage is considered. The first two underlined phrases are clearly Damascius' own surmises, and the third is quite on a par with them. The explanation of as og must, then, be Damascius' (and it rtevr_4guXo; nrev'r•co~o may be added that this explanationneed not be more relevantthan his two previous conjectures). Furtherevidence of the early use of Kc6?aog for several cosmic regions has been found in the Theophrasteanreport on Anaximanderdiscussed above (pages 108-109), the plural acoigot in which have been admitted to refer to the elemental spheres.107Yet Simplicius' plural seems to be due to a corruption,the correct version being the singularKacoiogin Hippolytus.108But if nonetheless Simplicius' version is preferred,the grammaticalparallelbetween rob; oipaseems to suggest the meaning "a single vou; and toi; K6tomago in each (arrangement) single oiUpav6;(world)." At any rate, if coato;S is to have describedthe cosmic stratain others' Theophrastus supposed doctrines by the term co6aogot, he may certainly be expected to have used the term in his own stratification of the universe (De igne 351.19-25), which is not the case. Yet although the notion of the world's several a6oigotcannot be plausibly traced back to the fourth century B.C.,its preconditionsare already there. Mansfeld109aptly compares the notion of regional with the popularview of the universe as composed of concenK6at1ot tric elemental spheres,110as well as with the subdivisions of the heavenly region in the early Academy"' and the Aristotelian distinction 106 Kerschensteiner (above, n. 3) 53-54 and n. 1. (above, n. 16) 44-45; cf. Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 44. 108 See Finkelberg(above, n. 21) 486, 493-494. 109Mansfeld (above, n. 16) 43-44. 110See, for instance, Arist. De caelo 287a30-b14; and in the Stoics: D.L. 7. 137, 155; for furtherreferences see Mansfeld (above, n. 16) 114 and notes 250, 251, 252; 115 and notes 253 and 256. Mansfeld traces this view back to Aristotle,but it was alreadyprefigured in the Presocraticcosmologies. Ill Xenocrates fr. 15, cf. fr. 5 and 18 (Heinze = fr. 213, 83, 215 IsnardiParente);Heraclides Ponticus fr. 96 (Wehrli). Cf. P. Boyanc6, "La religion astralede Platon ' Cic6ron," REG 65 (1952) 331-335; Burkert(above, n. 73) 245 n. 36. 107Mansfeld 134 AryehFinkelberg between the upper and lower heavens. As to the term 6co(toq, Epinomis 987B advises to reserve the name for the sphere of the fixed stars alone, but in the second partof AMtius'reporton Philolaus, which, as Burkerthas shown, is a Platonic concoction,112we find the typically is the Platonic threefold division of the heavens113in which ioa'to; as distinct name of the sphereof the five planets, the sun and the moon, which is the outerheaven, and from oUpav6;, which is from"Ok•hgnro;, ro l)1noo(krlvov Kai R-pPyetovjgipo;. Thus it seems that the name Kojogo; was applied to more than one, if eventuallynot to all, heavenly regions, and it was but a short step to make this cumulativeuse systematic. Again, Aristotle's two senses of Koa(log, the upper and lower heavens, readily suggest the terminological distinction between two heavenly KG6got.114We may thus suppose that the "regional"meaning of K6opog;was a generalizationof its use in the sense of "a (particular) heavenly region (sphere)" for all the world's spherical strata.115The pseudo-HippocratictractDe hebdomadibus,which seems to be the first in the "regional"sense, confirms known instance of the use of 6o'Tgoq this conclusion. In the first two chapters of the treatise the world is divided into seven ro4t; (1.41, 50, 63 Roscher), jgoipat (1.70), or g'pip (1.78) which severally (1.43, 70, 2.15, 42) and collectively (1.95) are referred to as K6oJgot. These are the outer heaven, the spheres of the stars, of the sun, of the moon, of air,of water,and the earth,beneathwhich there are other Ki6ogotoiot 8 -rv t0bv opttolyv jloto vetvj •18v (2.1). The these feature of peculiar K6opGotis that, except for the earth and the outermostheaven (2.15), all of them (including the spheres of air and 112Aet. 2.7.7 = DK 44 A 16; Burkert (above, n. 73) 244-246. 113Burkert's"of the cosmos" (above, n. 73) 245 and n. 36, repeatedin Mansfeld'srefer- ence (above, n. 16) 43 n. 34, to Burkert,is mistaken. e' yet [sc. Aristotle] &51o 114Epiphan.Adv. haer 3.31: E{vat 5& tbv &vwKai Ko6o•go•T TbvKXdOC CT X,. 115It should be noted in this connection that the Stoics seem to have used the term a(paipa for both the celestial spheres and the elemental sphericallayers:Arius Did. fr. 31 Diels (above, n. 14) 466.9 (=Arnim [above, n. 75] 2.169.1) ... rnepteXeo0at&% rtdoa T&; ( cov Tfi T•&v &(hav&v ocpaipaq. t&v 5e nr(avwgevwvdyrlxonmXb Irxavwgjvw0iv & Toi Kp6vou, tger& Ta(xriv TijvTzo-At'd, tdhrlv elvat TeX&tlV(xZCv)&~havwvTilv Tv to3 icaijleC' etra ilv toi "Apeog,Pefij; &e% TfiT 'Ap(poSi'lT, ilV 'Eptoi,j i azr(lV & jlV i TvfiG i i&o't tSi av tzcod~pt ... nDR&8 iAvl Rald(ovdo eFxa •lv toi illioi, TV ov pog, oP p U (TO) i6azo, tail ae&lIv TEXEvETo3Xa aR v (PEP rlV TjilVTo t t' Ta(av 5•%til%T- Yiq Rept Cbg•oov oralgeovToDlrogot ceIteIVlqK X. OntheHistoryof theGreekKOXMOX 135 water as well as the subterraneanones) move in circles (2.6, 47). This bizarrebehaviourof the 6oaTjotsuggests their origin in the astronomical theory of the homocentric rotating spheres. The Hebdomadiccosmology seems to be a generalizationof the astronomicalmodel for the world as a whole, and the use of K6o'tot for the designation of all the elemental spheres must be part of this generalization. If so, the tract evidences the derivationof the use of K60ototin the "regional"sense from the use of the word for heavenly spheres.l16 More specific conclusions must remain conjectural. The source on which the Hebdomadicauthorpresumablydrew could hardly be astronomical. First of all, Eudoxus' sphereswere known as and uptipa1t,17 certain of features the Hebdomadic its secondly, picture suggest philosophical, ratherthan astronomical,provenance. Indeed,the name of the outermost sphere 6 (2.15, 42) evokes Epinomis 06X•rtigto; Kcotio; where and 977B, 6o(0og;,"Okugnrog;, oaUpav6gare used synonymously of the outerheaven (cf. as the name of the outer heaven in the "Oh••rtog; Platonic account of Philolaus); if Roscher's emendation lprilrou for Xcipitro(1.44) is accepted, this epithet of the outermostsphere would parallel Theophrastus' description (De igne 351.24) of his rpdokrl but above all, the immobility of the outermost apcixpa as Ktircxog; is K6cLog; conspicuous:in so far as it is not the sphereof the fixed stars, it cannot come from an astronomicaltheory. To these it may be added that a person who, like the Hebdomadic author,does not hesitate to locate the fixed stars and the planets in the same spherecan hardlybe a reader of astronomicaltreatises. The source of the De hebdomadibus must, then, have been a philosophical tract in which the theory of the homocentricrotatingspheres was adaptedto the Academic-Peripatetic stratificationsof the heaven into several main regions, and these concentric stratawere termed K6O(0ot.The piece seems to have originated in Platonic-Peripateticcircles: Eudoxus' theory (as improvedby Callippus) of the homocentric spheres was introduced into philosophy and adaptedby Aristotle;the Hebdomadicterminology suggests Academic, 116 Cf. Corp. Herm. 1.1.7: EirthxKoagIot= the seven planets. 117Both in astronomical and general literature,see, e.g., Arist. Met. 1073b17; Eucl. Phaen. 12.6 (Menge); Arch. Aren. 256.1 (Heiberg); Diod. 1.172.32, 34 (Miiller). It is however noteworthythat ic6agog was the established astronomicalterm for the sphere whose radiusis the straightline between the centers of the earthand sun, see Arch.Aren. must be derivativeof its 218.2, cf. 218.24, 31 etc. This terminological use of K6o•gog meaning "heavenlysphere." 136 AryehFinkelberg and if Roscher's emendationis accepted, also Peripatetic,provenance, while the use of KoG'Tot for all the heavenly regions is a generalization of Platonic (but perhapsalso the astronomical-K6oJlgo;as the term for the solar sphere)usage. But whateverthe detailed points of semanticdevelopmentmay be, it seems evident that the "regional"sense of 6oajgo;,besides the use in the sense of "world,"is anotherextension of its meaning "heaven.""118 The word which meant "heaven" and then "a (particular)heavenly sphere,"came to designate also all the other "spheres"of which the universe was commonly believed to consist.119Assuming Mansfeld's date of the De hebdomadibus,this use must be late, aroundthe first century B.C. TEL AVIV UNIVERSITY 118 Not the narrowing of the sense of "world" as is generally supposed; see, e.g., Kerschensteiner(above, n. 3) 58-59; Mansfeld (above, n. 16) 44 and n. 35. 119This is the exact meaning of icoaJgogin its "regional"use. The meaning was never lost and the word seems to have been used only for the world's strata or strata-like 6 regions, as in Herm. ap. Stob. Ecl. 396.17; 405.1 (Wachsmuth),where 0'er6polo; are distinguished(LSJ, s.v. c6ajgogiv, "of any region K6oagogand 6 ~irntx6vioqK6Tagog in Stobaeusis misof the universe"[LSJ's italics], with referenceto 6 pverdpoato Kpog6to leading). The popularconstrualof the word as referringto "partialarrangements"of the world (as, for instance,in Cornford[above, n. 21] 9: "K6ajgothere [in Hippolytus'report on Xenophanes]might mean successive 'arrangements'in which dry land and sea are distinct ... Or the may be those other 'climes, sections or zones of the earth'which Ka6•aot of their own (Adt. 2.24.9)," or in Kirk [above, n. 22] 178 n. 1: "... have suns and moons the ambiguous use of Kdoagot [in the same report of Hippolytus] ... there properly i.e. of the earth'ssurface .. ."), is a linguistic fancy. 'world-arrangements,'